WILLIAM GOLDMAN 9/20/2011 For Educational Use Only BETWEEN WILMINGTON AND WASHINGTON: LESSONS..., 12 Harv. Negot. L.... 12 Harv. Negot. L. Rev. 103 Harvard Negotiation Law Review Winter 2007 Article Oracle v. PeopleSoft BETWEEN WILMINGTON AND WASHINGTON: LESSONS FROM ORACLE-PEOPLESOFT David Millstoned1 Copyright (c) 2007 Harvard Negotiation Law Review; David Millstone Introduction The Oracle-PeopleSoft takeover contest ended on December 13, 2004 with smiles and handshakes and praise from Vice Chancellor Strine.1 Such is the redemptive and re-interpretive power of success. Oracle had paid a rich price for its prize. Its all-cash offer was a 75% premium to the closing price of PeopleSoft common stock on June 5, 2003, the last trading day prior to the announcement of Oracle’s initial $16 offer. Billions would be wired to shareholder accounts in short order (arriving just after the first of January, thereby adding a year of tax deferral to the holiday cheer). PeopleSoft’s months-long scorched-earth defense became subtle and prescient after the deal. “Aren’t you glad we didn’t accept $16?” PeopleSoft director and Chairman of the Transaction Committee, A. George “Skip” Battle, told one investor in mid-November in justification of PeopleSoft’s vast and, in certain instances, unprecedented defensive arsenal.dd1 Oracle had even more to celebrate. They were, after all, the victors. The strategic wisdom of the acquisition and the reasonable- ness of the price were issues to be tested later. For the moment, Oracle had done something once considered impossible - the com- pany had waged a successful hostile takeover in Silicon Valley.2 *104 “We think hostile takeovers do work,” Ellison concluded with pride.3 But the process had its costs. Eighteen months of turmoil and hundreds of millions of dollars in transaction costs had benefited the lawyers and the arbitrageurs, and, even more so, rival SAP. Craig Conway, PeopleSoft’s erstwhile champion, was humbled. PeopleSoft’s current Chairman and CEO, its founder and largest individual shareholder, David Duffield was bitter but resigned. He and Vice-Chairman Aneel Bhusri opposed the deal and abstained from the final vote in favor of the merger. A letter Duffield sent to employees reflected his sentiments: “I offer my sincere apologies for not figuring out a different conclusion to our 18-month saga. It became clear to us that the vast majority of our stockholders would accept $26.50 and that Oracle was willing to pay it.”4 The story is a human one, and it would of course be naïve to expect such a messy process to have too clean of a conclusion. PeopleSoft’s shareholders did well. Oracle’s shareholders did well. Presumably a more efficient company was created. Shouldn’t we end the inquiry here? A protagonist’s fall from grace, a billionaire’s quasi-socialist grievances, name-calling, and sand-kicking may make good gossip, but are such events of any consequence? More precisely, are these facts relevant to the underlying legal questions of how we should structure the rules governing takeover negotiations? In this paper, I argue that they are, precisely because our corporate law simultaneously empowers managers and directors while crippling shareholders. The increased power of managers and directors is not the result of any particular reform, but rather the sum effect of many reforms, and, in particular, the unintended interactions of Delaware case law with federal rules serving to constrain shareholders. This evolution has created an unstable system that is far too sensitive to the idiosyncrasies, ideologies, and self-interests of managers and directors. It is not a broken system; far from it. It is sophisticated, highly evolved and in many respects the envy of the world. But it is needlessly influenced by “jejune, playground, adolescent, macho”5 conduct. *105 This is, I think, the particular moral of Oracle-PeopleSoft. The redemptive power of a successful, negotiated transaction only goes so far. A thorough analysis of the 18-month saga reveals a process that was strikingly mismanaged by Oracle. Often ignoring its advisors and relying on limited hostile-deal experience, Oracle’s team invited needless headaches and © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 1 WILLIAM GOLDMAN 9/20/2011 For Educational Use Only BETWEEN WILMINGTON AND WASHINGTON: LESSONS..., 12 Harv. Negot. L.... eroded its credibility with mercurial course changes and rhetoric. This difficult situation was exacerbated by PeopleSoft’s questionably legal scorched-earth defense and the bad faith its management and certain board members exhibited in handling Oracle’s overtures. In contrast, investors dealt with the situation in a composed, dispassionate and rational way. And ultimately it was the investors who brought the two sides together. Takeover negotiations take place against a background of rules that determine whose views matter and how much. By undermining shareholders and thereby empowering managers in such negotiations, Delaware’s jurisprudence has added unnecessary volatility to what is by its nature a difficult, at times explosive situation. What should be a debate about value devolves, as we saw in Oracle PeopleSoft, into a name-calling, flak-jacket wearing circus replete with personal vendettas and threats to pets. While all of this is eerily amusing to watch, it imposes real costs on employees and shareholders, not to mention customers and judges. In this contest, the same deal terms were available to PeopleSoft in February of 2004 as it received in December of that year. So much of the debate was not about value, but a tour of the very personal aspirations and hatreds of the companies’ principals. The rules of the game ought to be restructured to minimize such “jejune, playground, adolescent, macho”6 conduct to the extent possible. One way to do that, to dampen the volatility that results from having self-interested managers dominate takeover negotiations, is to unburden the restrictions that prevent shareholders from effectively participating in such negotiations. The Oracle-PeopleSoft case should make us question the wisdom of Delaware’s endorsement of the suspicious doctrine of substantive coercion. Additionally, it suggests the benefits of an increased role for investors in takeover situations. Such a role would be substantially enhanced by easing the outdated restrictions on shareholder communications that chill interactions among shareholders. This Paper is organized as follows: In Part I, I review the history of Delaware’s endorsement of substantive coercion as a justification for maintaining a poison pill. I *106 then turn to the emergence of the countervailing doctrine of proxy out which has become the safety valve on pill misuse. In Part II, I review the history and present incarnation of federal restrictions on shareholder communications. In Part III, I return to Oracle-PeopleSoft. I consider the lessons of the deal and its implications for Delaware’s takeover jurisprudence and for federal restrictions on shareholder communication. I argue for the increased involvement of shareholders in takeover disputes based on that experience. I show that Oracle-PeopleSoft suggests both that directors and management cannot generally be trusted to conduct hostile takeovers absent the discipline provided by the market through active shareholders. I document the new realities of shareholding, especially the rise of hedge funds and show how they contradict traditional assumptions about shareholder ignorance and passivity. I show how Oracle-PeopleSoft belies traditional assumptions of shareholder passivity and ignorance and illustrates the extent to which shareholders can be a force for reason in situations animated by personal vitriol and other non-economic considerations. Finally, I draw these arguments together and suggest a relaxation of restrictions on shareholder communication to provide for increased shareholder involvement in fundamental transactions. I note that Delaware’s restrictions on shareholders, in particular the restrictions on the free alienability of shares created by the poison pill, cannot be evaluated independently of the doctrinally separate restrictions on shareholder communication provided for by the federal regime. If shareholder voice is to be the ultimate safety valve on misuse of the pill, if it is to replace alienability through a tender as the manner in which shareholders express their point of view, then shareholder communication needs to become less anathema in the eyes of the law. I argue that shareholders consistently demonstrate their reasonability in takeover situations. Today, they are well-informed and active. They are not pushovers in negotiations, nor are they obstreperous. These qualities provide a critical counterweight to the sometimes volatile and ideological personalities driving takeover contests. I. Wilmington - Substantive Coercion and Proxy Out Proxy contests and tender offers are not perfect substitutes. Early on, tenders were an extension of the trading market almost completely unfettered by regulation. Proxy contests in contrast were burdensome and subject to the extensive disclosure obligations provided for in the Securities Exchange Act. In 1965 Professor Henry *107 Manne described proxy contests as © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 2 WILLIAM GOLDMAN 9/20/2011 For Educational Use Only BETWEEN WILMINGTON AND WASHINGTON: LESSONS..., 12 Harv. Negot. L.... “the most expensive, the most uncertain, and the least used of the various techniques” for acquiring control of a corporation. 7 This changed substantially with the adoption of the Williams Act in 1968, which imposed disclosure requirements on tender offerors comparable with those required in proxy contests. Nevertheless, tender offers retained a number of advantages. Foremost among them was that a prospective acquirer could take his case straight to shareholders. This gave an acquirer the ability to obviate a self-interested management and board. For shareholders, the possibility of finding real liquidity for a position in an underperforming company gave some substance to the Wall Street Walk, the idea that if you do not like what management is doing, you should sell rather than complain. And the opportunity for profit by ousting self-interested or underperforming managers ensured that a robust market of acquirers would actively seek out such situations. Many academics saw this as a critical part of our corporate law and argued for board passivity in response to offers. In a famous article, Ronald Gilson presented this view: The result of management adopting successful defensive tactics is to make impossible a tender offer which management has not blessed. . . . This result, however, is flatly inconsistent with the structure of the corporation. The market for corporate control is crucial to the corporate structure because neither other markets nor a fiduciary “fairness” standard effectively constrains some forms of management self-dealing.8 He added that “absent a pro-management shift in the traditional standard, pre-offer [defensive] tactics which can have no business purpose should thus be in jeopardy.”9 He was right, but not in the way he intended to be. The wave of takeovers in the 1980s convinced Delaware to take a decidedly “pro-management shift” in its jurisprudence.10 In Moran v. Household International,11 the Delaware Supreme Court accepted the idea that free alienability was not a necessary part of a shareholder’s package of rights. A board could use the newly devised poison pill to block a *108 tender offer it considered threatening. Critically, for our purposes, the Court signaled that shareholders’ ability to wage a proxy contest was the safety valve on pill abuse when it reasoned that a pill would not significantly deter proxy activity: Thus, while the Rights Plan does deter the formation of proxy efforts of a certain magnitude, it does not limit the voting power of individual shares. On the evidence presented it is highly conjectural to assume that a particular effort to assert shareholder views in the election of directors or revisions of corporate policy will be frustrated by the proxy feature of the Plan. Household’s witnesses, Troubh and Higgins described recent corporate takeover battles in which insurgents holding less than 10% stock ownership were able to secure corporate control through a proxy contest or the threat of one. 12 This view was endorsed more explicitly in Unitrin, Inc. v. American General Corp., 13 when the Delaware Supreme Court used the possibility of a proxy contest to reason that a poison pill was neither preclusive nor coercive and thereby acceptable under Unitrin’s interpretation of Unocal:14 After acknowledging that the adoption of the rights plan was within the directors’ statutory authority, this Court determined that the implementation of the rights plan was a proportionate response to the theoretical threat of a hostile takeover, in part, because it did not ‘strip’ the stockholders of their right to receive tender offers and did not fundamentally restrict proxy contests, i.e., was not preclusive.15 Through this evolution in Delaware, proxy contests, the ugly stepchild of the takeover arsenal, became the centerpiece of the market for corporate control. Separate, but contemporaneous jurisprudence in Delaware reinforced the protections of shareholders’ rights with regard to proxy contests even as they were being weakened in other contexts. Blasius Industries, Inc. v. Atlas Corp.16 is the case most frequently cited regarding Delaware’s protection of the shareholder franchise. In that case, Chancellor Allen struck down a board-packing maneuver taken to thwart a proxy contest famously declaring, “The shareholder franchise is the ideological underpinning upon which the legitimacy of directorial power rests.”17 Two other cases, *109 Carmody v. Toll Bros.18 and Mentor Graphics Corp. v Quickturn Design Systems, Inc., 19 which rejected the validity of dead-hand and no-hand pills, respectively, further protected the shareholder franchise. In Toll Brothers and in the Chancery court opinion in Quickturn Vice Chancellor Jacobs rejected dead-hand and no-hand pills in part on the grounds that they disenfranchised shareholders. The Delaware Supreme Court affirmed Quickturn on the much narrower ground that the no-hand pill violated Delaware General Corporation Law § 141(a), but the effect was the same. At the same time that Delaware was defending the franchise, its endorsement of substantive coercion, discussed previously, was undermining restrictions on use of the pill. The doctrine was adopted without heed to the warning of Professors Gilson and Kraakman that, [S]ubstantive coercion is a slippery concept. To note abstractly that management might know shareholder interests better than shareholders themselves do cannot be a basis for rubber-stamping management’s pro forma claims in the face of market © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 3 WILLIAM GOLDMAN 9/20/2011 For Educational Use Only BETWEEN WILMINGTON AND WASHINGTON: LESSONS..., 12 Harv. Negot. L.... skepticism and the enormous opportunity losses that threaten target shareholders when hostile offers are defeated. 20 Since a company could find a bank that would conclude that virtually any offer was inadequate, substantive coercion became, as a practical matter, an unlimited justification of the pill. Today, as Vice Chancellor Strine has convincingly argued, substantive coercion and proxy out stand as the twin pillars of the law governing tenders.21 The doctrine of substantive coercion has expanded the board’s ability to block tenders, while proxy out has operated to constrain such discretion so it does not become unfettered. Vice Chancellor Strine (who coined the term “proxy out”) eloquently described this dynamic as follows: Indeed, the courts have deployed in tandem two doctrinal concepts to escape the ultimate “Just Say No” question. The first concept - “substantive coercion” - is the notion that directors *110 may legitimately use defensive measures (to some as-yet-undefined extent) to protect stockholders from making an erroneous decision to sell their shares for too low a price in a tender offer. The second concept - what I call the “proxy out” - is the idea that the poison pill is not a preclusive or unreasonable response to the threat of substantive coercion, so long as the stockholders are able to elect a new board that can dismantle the pill. When used together, the substantive coercion and proxy out concepts reduced poison pill litigation and funneled takeover fights into the director election process. 22 This evolution has changed corporate law in two basic ways. First, it has altered the balance of power between shareholders and the board. Second, it has magnified the importance of proxy contests. Whatever the benefits and deficiencies of proxy contests, those benefits and deficiencies have become significant drivers of Delaware corporate law. It is to those benefits and deficiencies we now turn. II. Washington - The Curious Evolution of Shareholder Communication The “purpose of law,” however, is absolutely the last thing to employ in the history of the origin of law: on the contrary, there is for historiography of any kind no more important proposition than the one it took such effort to establish but which really ought to be established now: the cause of the origin of a thing and its eventual utility, its actual employment and place in a system of purposes, lie worlds apart; whatever exists, having somehow come into being, is again and again reinterpreted to new ends, taken over, transformed, and redirected by some power superior to it; all events in the organic world are a subduing, a becoming master, and all subduing and becoming master involves a fresh interpretation, an adaptation through which any previous “meaning” and “purpose” are necessarily obscured or even obliterated. - Friedrich Nietzsche, On the Genealogy of Morals Although central to Delaware’s thinking, proxy contests are a federal fiefdom. This is an artifact of the 1930s when reformers became convinced that corporate law, historically the prerogative of the states, was a Hobbesian world of cunning barons and helpless shareholders. Berle and Means issued a call to arms with their famous *111 treatise, The Modern Corporation and Private Property.23 They documented the rise of the large corporation where small shareholders had ownership without the basic indicium of ownership - control. Berle and Means feared that this separation of ownership and control would lead to those in control taking advantage of those who own. Against this background, the federal government stepped in the fray as a champion of the shareholder with the 1933 and 1934 Acts. The 1934 Act provided continuing disclosure obligations, and, of particular relevance for our purposes, drew the federal government into the regulation of proxy contests. Congress left the details entirely to the SEC. The authority granted was broad; it was sea change. Section 14(a) of the 1934 Act provides: It shall be unlawful for any person . . . in contravention of such rules and regulations as the Commission may prescribe as necessary or appropriate . . . to solicit or to permit the use of his name to solicit any proxy or consent or authorization in respect of any security . . . registered pursuant to section 12 of this title.24 There is not a great deal of legislative history regarding § 14(a). But what there is suggests Congress intended to protect the shareholder franchise and thereby protect shareholders from management abuse. Jill Fisch, in an exhaustive study of the legislative history, finds substantial support for this interpretation. 25 For example, the Rayburn Report, in a section entitled “Control of Unfair Practices by Corporate Insiders,” states: “Fair corporate suffrage is an important right that should attach to every equity security bought on a public exchange.”26 The Report explains that corporate insiders can perpetuate themselves in office by soliciting proxies to secure their re-election without disclosing to shareholders: (1) their interest in the corporation; (2) the management policies they intend to pursue; © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 4 WILLIAM GOLDMAN 9/20/2011 For Educational Use Only BETWEEN WILMINGTON AND WASHINGTON: LESSONS..., 12 Harv. Negot. L.... and (3) the purposes for which the proxies are to be used. As Fisch explains in her study: *112 Thomas Corcoran, one of the principal drafters of the Exchange Act, had a broad view of the problems to which the proxy regulation was addressed. Corcoran believed that corporate insiders, through their control of the proxy process, were able both to perpetuate themselves in power and to use the voting process to further their private ends. He viewed the abuse of power by corporate insiders as central to the objectives of federal regulation: “It is one of the big worries about the corporate form of doing business in this country, that the shareholders, nor really even the boards of directors do not actually run corporations, but coterie of a very few men on the inside. . . . You are tied up, sir, with a problem so big that this proxy solicitation touches only one edge of it.27 The era of shareholder protection did not last long. The scope of the rules ballooned over the years as the SEC sought to extend its oversight, and, ever fearful of creating a loophole, gave its rules expansive and open-ended interpretations. At the same time, their purpose became confused and reinterpreted and hijacked. In a classic regulatory capture story, the SEC was co-opted by management, the very constituency it was meant to monitor. John Pound offers a fascinating and invaluable history of this phenomenon in his article “Proxy Voting and the SEC: Investor Protection Versus Market Efficiency.”28 As Pound relates, by 1955 the SEC was reviewing its proxy rules to offer management greater protection against “raiders”: The increasing visibility of proxy contests, and the increasing contentiousness of the campaigns, were sources of concern among policymakers and the public. Debate focused on the overall economic effects of contests and the possible need for further regulation. Management groups advocated regulations that would protect shareholders from the financial scheming of raiders. The American Institute of Management denounced ‘adventurers who do not hesitate to promise the impossible to stockholders distressed at the turn of events and bewildered as to what to do. They seek out situations of partial failure, not because they are imbued with a desire to institute reforms which objective analysis shows to be needed, but because only circumstances of distress can stampede the uninitiated stockholder into surrendering himself into their hands . . . . Their *113 purpose is self-enrichment and the enlargement of personal power.’29 This process continued. The rules, even with some minimal paring back in 1992, have grown to thwart, rather than protect, shareholder power. Pound again: The regulations have thus not only failed to solve the collective choice problem in voting, but have constituted an obstacle to natural market forces that could bring a solution.30 . . . In short, changes in ownership structure and communications technology have created the potential to solve the collective choice problem that has plagued corporate voting for over a century, and that originally motivated proxy regulation. But the regulatory structure has prevented these forces from operating. Deterring active communication about voting issues and coordinated, informal action, the rules have enforced a regime in which each institutional shareholder has been forced to act as if its peers did not exist. 31 The second major impediment to shareholder communication arose (somewhat accidentally) from federal concern over tender offers. In 1965, Senator Harrison Williams proposed federal legislation to protect target companies from what he called the “industrial sabotage” of hostile corporate raids on “proud old companies.”32 By 1968, the Williams Act had been enacted. The Williams Act introduced Exchange Act Section 13(d) and the related SEC rules requiring any person or “group” that beneficially owns more than 5% of a public company’s stock to file a Schedule 13D containing disclosure about the person or group, its stock ownership, its plans with respect to the company, and various other matters. This was intended as an early warning system for hostile takeovers, but has morphed into (according to the shareholders I spoke with) the primary restriction on shareholder communication. This evolution was abetted by an SEC with little regard for the chilling effect of such rules. Bernard Black relates one telling anecdote: Sometimes, obstructive rules appear almost by accident, with the SEC showing no appreciation for their consequences. For example, the Commission added the critical word “voting” to the activities that cause shareholders to be considered a “group” under the 13(d) Rules with the casual explanation that: “Minor *114 word changes have also been made from the predecessor [rule] . . . . The Commission considered ‘voting’ to be subsumed within the term ‘holding’ but has decided to make this express to avoid any misunderstanding.”33 The federal rules are now a daunting array of sometime picayune requirements that effectively chill shareholder communication and coordination. Their effect has been treated at length by a number of scholars. 34 The rules are too complicated to parse at length in this paper, but I think it is worth reflecting on the obstacles faced by a large shareholder looking to communicate and coordinate with other large holders. © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 5 WILLIAM GOLDMAN 9/20/2011 For Educational Use Only BETWEEN WILMINGTON AND WASHINGTON: LESSONS..., 12 Harv. Negot. L.... The Proxy Rules require anyone who “solicits” “proxies” from shareholders to deliver a written proxy statement containing various disclosures.35 Solicitation is defined broadly to include any communication to shareholders “under circumstances reasonably calculated to result in the procurement, withholding or revocation of a proxy.”36 Solicitation of 10 or fewer holders is excepted,37 but even this is problematic - if you solicit 4 holders who each solicit 4 more, have you tripped it? (This exception also adds to the arbitrariness of the rules. In some cases 10 shareholders will be a majority, in others well short of one). The disclosure is onerous and communications are subject to broad antifraud regulation. 38 Such problems are mild compared with the risks presented by § 13(d). The rule requires disclosure by any “person” of “beneficial ownership” of five percent or more of a company’s equity securities. 39 Persons will be a “group” and have their holdings aggregated if they have agreed to act together “for the purpose of acquiring, holding, *115 voting or disposing”40 of the issuer’s equity securities. Such agreements do not have to be in writing and can be proved by circumstantial evidence. 41 Holders who become members of a group are not only subject to disclosure requirement but can be liable under the short-swing profit rules of § 16(b) of the Securities Exchange Act.42 While the foregoing is quite onerous, the greatest potential liability is actually an unintended consequence of the rules, or, more precisely, the interaction between the federal rules and state law. Shareholders who are aggregated into a group whose holdings are in excess of a company’s poison pill threshold will almost certainly be subject to the financial Armageddon imposed by the pill. This is a result of the broad definitions of “beneficial ownership” contained in most rights plans (a definition generally modeled on § 13(d)).43 Such restrictions have had their intended (or unintended) effect. The investors that I spoke with are very careful about whom they speak to, particularly during contests for control. “We are very careful when we talk to other investors,” said one who cited 13(d) as his biggest worry. Another noted, “First, I only talk to my friends. Second, we don’t strategize. We hash out scenarios . . . like when you talk to someone about sports. This could happen, if that happened.” One investor described shareholders as constantly fearful of the rules. He recalled one time he had been invited to a meeting with management during the course of a proxy contest. When he arrived at the room, he realized the bankers had double-booked the slot and he was sharing it with another shareholder. This small scheduling error set off warning bells in both investors’ minds - they did not sit next to each other, they did not talk and when management arrived they opened the conversation with an explanation that they did not know each other, had no affiliation and certainly were not part of a group. “We are always aware of the rules and once we’ve filed a 13D we are extraordinarily careful. No conversations basically,” was one rule articulated to me. “People go to great lengths to avoid 13(d) liability,” concluded an investor. “Everyone has counsel working on these issues.” The perverse effect of these rules is evident in two recent cases. The recent tussle between Carl Icahn and Kerr-Mcgee is a fascinating example of how § 13(d) not only chills interactions, but has become a weapon against shareholders who oppose management. *116 Interestingly, this example was cited to me by two separate investors when I asked about their concerns regarding § 13(d). For a long time, investors and analysts had been criticizing Kerr-Mcgee for squandering its cash horde on exploration and non-core business rather than returning the money to shareholders. Such criticism had grown more pronounced in the recent bull market for energy. In March 2005, Icahn, who controlled 4.7% and JANA, a hedge fund which owned another 3%, joined together to launch a proxy contest primarily to force a distribution of the cash. 44 Kerr-Mcgee responded by accusing the two of having coordinated their purchases of the Company’s stock in violation of § 13(d). “Because they didn’t file as required, they were able to acquire more shares at lower prices than they would have been able to do otherwise, significantly disadvantaging other stockholders,” the Company said.45 While in theory this could be true, it is doubtful that the two coordinated purchases. The undermanagement at Kerr-Mcgee was an open secret in the investing community. Moreover, Icahn is clearly capable of managing a proxy contest without the assistance of JANA. It would make no sense for Icahn, who is well-advised, to coordinate a purchase program and incur liability for violations of federal law simply to ensure that he had a partner with whom to launch a proxy contest. The far more likely scenario is that Icahn and JANA independently reached similar investment conclusions and bought stock. Months later, when informal pressure on management had yielded no result, they joined together for a proxy contest. At that point, joining forces would make sense since extensive disclosure would be required anyway as a result of the proxy contest. Working together would allow the two to defer costs, speak for a larger block, and not duplicate work. The question of what actually happened will never be resolved since on April 14th Kerr-McGee caved and announced a series of measures, including a $4 billion stock buyback and the divestment of more than $2 billion in assets. 46 In exchange, © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 6 WILLIAM GOLDMAN 9/20/2011 For Educational Use Only BETWEEN WILMINGTON AND WASHINGTON: LESSONS..., 12 Harv. Negot. L.... Icahn agreed to drop his proxy fight. Confirming Icahn’s thesis, Kerr-McGee’s stock gained nearly 7% on the news. *117 Two things are clear from the example. First, situations will frequently arise where activist investors independently acquire stock positions based on similar investment theses. In fact, it is quite rare to find just one activist/value fund in a particular stock. When sophisticated investors have the same information and do the same homework, they reach similar conclusions. But these funds will then always be open to accusations of “group” formation if they attempt to influence management based on their common investment thesis. When two people independently take similar actions, there is always a possible inference of coordination. That inference is a weapon in the hands of a management that feels threatened. Even in situations, such as Kerr-Mcgee, where multiple investors actually come together to form an official “group,” they will still be open to accusations of not properly disclosing the precise moment of group formation. Current disclosure does not cure past infractions. In fact, such situations are probably more precarious for a shareholder because the formation of the group manifests an intent to act together. It’s not difficult for a company to allege that such an intent ripened into actual group formation at some point prior to the disclosure. The other thing worth noting about the example, although it is purely anecdotal, is how value-enhancing the coordinated action between Icahn and JANA was. The second example arose out of the AXA-MONY merger. This situation too involved an activist hedge fund running afoul of the federal rules. Recall the dispute concerned a management sponsored all-cash buyout of MONY by the French conglomerate AXA. AXA offered approximately $1.5 billion for MONY. Many shareholders thought this substantially undervalued the company (it was only 75% of MONY’s book value) and they were suspicious of the incentives created by $82.6 million in severance payments for MONY’s management, most of which went to MONY’s CEO Michael Roth. The $82.6 million, incidentally, was the final number actually paid to management. A larger sum and one that was less adequately disclosed was offered to management before activist shareholders blew the whistle. This severance package was actually larger than the entire deal premium paid to shareholders.47 The deal was opposed by a number of hedge funds and investors and by both Glass Lewis and ISS. Only after a bump in the deal price, a reduction in the severance package *118 and a postponement of the vote was the controversial merger finally approved by a narrow 53.4% margin. 48 During the course of the deal, the well regarded hedge fund, Highfields, had emerged as a leading opponent of the deal. Highfields began exploring a way of communicating its position to shareholders. The fund actually went to the SEC seeking “advice on any constraints imposed by the Exchange Act, particularly on whether an exempt solicitation under Rule 14a-2(b)(1) could ‘include a copy of MONY’s proxy card in its mailing for the convenience of MONY shareholders to facilitate . . . voting [against the merger].”’49 Highfields was advised by SEC staff that “although it [had] not been released formally, the Office of Mergers and Acquisitions at the SEC had considered and adopted a ‘nonpublished position’ in an informal April 1993 interpretation (circulated internally among SEC staff) that gave qualified approval to shareholders seeking to mail duplicates of management proxy cards as part of an exempt proxy solicitation under Rule 14a-2(b)(1). On the basis of these discussions with SEC staff, Highfields planned an exempt proxy solicitation to MONY shareholders that included duplicates of MONY’s proxy card and conformed to the restrictions described in the April 1993 opinion.”50 Highfields was then sued by MONY, which sought to enjoin the fund from sending the cards with its solicitation. In contravention of both the SEC’s advice and the spirit of the 1992 reforms, the Second Circuit found that mailing the cards violated § 14(a) and risked an “irreparable harm” to MONY. The court issued a preliminary injunction declaring: As we first announced on April 1, 2004, we hold that MONY has demonstrated a likelihood that it will succeed on its claim that Appellees’ use of duplicate proxy cards was outside the Rule 14a-2(b)(1) exemption and that, absent full compliance with SEC proxy regulations by Appellees, MONY will likely succeed in its claim against Appellees under Section 14(a). 51 This is an extraordinary result on a number of levels. Even a well-funded, well-advised investor who looked for pre-clearance from the SEC still ran afoul of the rules. It shows how unreasonably complicated the rules have become. It again shows how much of a weapon the rules can be in the hands of a management that wants to oppose an activist investor. It shows (anecdotally) how little benefit the 1992 *119 reforms had. But most importantly, I think, is the longer view. Stepping back from the actual text and history of Rule 14a-2(b)(1), we must wonder: what is the actual harm being prevented here? It is such a strange artifact of history, of a world where shareholders were far less sophisticated and information much more difficult to come by, that the power of Congress and the federal judiciary has been deployed to prevent a hedge fund (one that has been candid about its position) from mailing to other shareholders the exact same proxy card that management mailed to them a month earlier. Thus the curious present incarnation of rules designed to protect the shareholder from a “coterie of a very few men on the inside.”52 III. Between Wilmington and Washington: Lessons from Oracle-PeopleSoft © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 7 WILLIAM GOLDMAN 9/20/2011 For Educational Use Only BETWEEN WILMINGTON AND WASHINGTON: LESSONS..., 12 Harv. Negot. L.... Reflecting on the deal recently, one person involved in Oracle-PeopleSoft wondered, “Where were the boards?” He continued, “It was really a problem for both sides. [Management] did these deals and made these offers and the boards just came along.” This was a $10 billion merger. Billion. People’s lives, their careers and fortunes were in the balance. Investors, certainly, had much at stake. But employees, customers and vendors did too. “Think how many divorces are going to happen because of this deal,” mused one person involved. The bloodletting had real costs, financial and human. As the inimitable Strine cautioned, “This is not some game of phony Monopoly or some fun-loving little tricky stuff that people do.” And yet, the entire deal was marked by “jejune, playground, adolescent, macho”53 conduct. It is easy to look back and whitewash every action as preceding, and therefore somehow a necessary condition for, the ultimate negotiated result. But this is simplistic, and wrong. The negotiated solution was the product of two things, neither of which reflects well on the conduct of the parties - an investor actively looking for a way to bridge the divide between two sides who would not speak to each other and an activist judge of preeminent reputation and intelligence. As a person involved in the final negotiations remarked, “the real dealmaker here was VC Strine. In my book, this never would have happened without Strine.” I agree that Strine was vital. He acquitted himself admirably and though known for his interminable opinions, like all great judges *120 he is probably most proud of the cases where his presence obviated the need for an opinion at all. But as most M&A practitioners would agree, Strine is exceptional. He will not always be there to bail you out. Investors, on the other hand, will be there. It is their role in this that has been overlooked. This is, I think, the particular moral of Oracle-PeopleSoft. The saga should make us question the restricted role shareholders have been given in takeover contests, the strange patchwork of the paternalistic and the preemptive created in the nexus between Wilmington and Washington. Oracle-PeopleSoft was an offer to shareholders, a tender offer, blocked for 18 months by PeopleSoft’s board which had declared the offer “inadequate.” The doctrine of principal relevance in justifying such an action by the board of a Delaware company is substantive coercion. In addition, I believe substantive coercion is an appropriate starting point for this discussion because it is, I think, doctrinally prior to proxy out. As Vice Chancellor Strine explained, the increased importance of proxy contests - proxy out - is a response to the unfettered authority provided by substantive coercion. A. The Emperor Has No Clothes: Substantive Coercion is Not a Reasonable Explanation of the Interaction Between Boards and Investors What conclusions can we draw from Oracle-PeopleSoft regarding substantive coercion? The case study offers a dramatic repudiation of the doctrine. Recall that the doctrine is primarily concerned with preventing shareholders from tendering their shares in “ignorance or mistaken belief” of their true value. Management and the board are believed to have special competence in valuing the company they run. In Oracle-PeopleSoft, they certainly did not show any. At least they did not show any interest in addressing the valuation question in good faith (those two inquiries, as Professors Gilson and Kraakman observed when they introduced the concept, are inseparable).54 When Oracle’s bid was launched, the PeopleSoft board actually had a recent and carefully prepared valuation study - the fairness opinion from the J.D. Edwards merger. That opinion was three weeks old, the product of careful preparation and arm’s-length negotiation (insofar as the valuation goes to the merger exchange ratio). The opinion predicted 2004 earnings of $.69 per share. *121 In the course of two weeks following Oracle’s bid, that estimate was raised to $1.02 per share. The revised estimate served as the basis for the board’s determination that Oracle’s offer was inadequate. The banker who presented the revised estimates recalled no questions from the board. The PeopleSoft employee who prepared the revision could not, under oath, offer any reason for the change. This simply cannot be the process Delaware envisions when they defer to a board’s special competence in valuing a company. © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 8 WILLIAM GOLDMAN 9/20/2011 For Educational Use Only BETWEEN WILMINGTON AND WASHINGTON: LESSONS..., 12 Harv. Negot. L.... Unlike PeopleSoft’s board of directors, PeopleSoft’s shareholders had no such ignorance or mistaken belief about the Company’s earning potential. Not one of the investors I spoke with credited the revisions. “We were very skeptical . . . we’re skeptical of everything in this business, everything these guys say is self-serving and in the best interest of individuals and the company . . . it was just so self-serving,” was a typical comment. This view was confirmed by Wall Street, which had a consensus estimate for PeopleSoft’s 2004 earnings in the mid-60 cents per share, consistent with the original, not the revised estimate. In point of fact, 2004 earnings turned out to be approximately $.70 per share. This was right in line with Wall Street and shareholders’ expectations and within a penny of PeopleSoft’s pre-Oracle estimate, but (unsurprisingly) nowhere near PeopleSoft’s fictitious $1.02 estimate that served as the basis for its response to Oracle. Not only did the board exhibit no particular skill in valuing PeopleSoft on its own, they did not make any good faith efforts to get assistance with the question. The Transaction Committee did not hire independent advisors. The board never requested written valuation studies from its bankers. Even in rejecting the $26 offer, the board accepted only a conclusory oral opinion from its bankers that the price was inadequate. No one on the board ever inquired what price would be adequate. Making matters worse, even some of PeopleSoft’s own bankers did not believe their own opinion that the $26 price was inadequate. PeopleSoft had retained both Citigroup and Goldman. In advance of delivering the opinion on the $26 offer, the chief of the Citigroup team wrote to the chief of the Goldman team, “I have a fundamental problem with your analysis. Rather than go into detail I will remain silent in this situation and look forward to having you guys on the buy side across the table from me.”55 It is perhaps going too far to hold the board responsible for the disloyalty of its *122 bankers, but such problems may have emerged earlier if the board had, for example, asked its bankers questions. Although the board rejected the $26 offer as “inadequate” and Conway declared “Oracle’s [$26] offer does not begin to reflect the Company’s real value,” the board later accepted and declared adequate what was, in real terms, a lower price (why does anyone ever look at nominal terms anyway?). Such a history does not inspire any confidence that the board has a special competence in valuation, at least one that can somehow be isolated from self-interest. One corollary to the substantive coercion doctrine is that a company should use the breathing space provided by the pill to make its case to shareholders regarding the company’s true value. In addition to putting out the fictitious revisions of the J.D. Edwards synergy estimates, Conway deliberately misled the market about Oracle’s impact on the Company’s financial health. He was fired for this, but only a year after he made the comments and only because the threat of perjury drew out the story. Rather than making its case to the market, PeopleSoft dissembled and in at least one instance lied. Of course, shareholders believed none of this. When Conway announced that no one was delaying purchases anymore as a result of the bid, PeopleSoft’s stock price did not suddenly run. This goes to a second corollary of the substantive coercion doctrine: shareholders are tender-prone, bowled over by any premium offer, unable to act strategically and willing to settle for a price much lower than can be extracted by management. This is a complicated question. Any incremental obstinacy by management will result in higher offers simply because all bidders with a lower price will be deterred. That is, you will produce higher offers but fewer of them, a result that may or may not be efficient. That is a question that cannot be sorted out with a single case study, but I do think Oracle-PeopleSoft contradicts the root idea that shareholders are especially credulous. PeopleSoft did not need to announce that $16 was too low; the market traded through the bid immediately. It was conversations with shareholders (PeopleSoft was not negotiating) that provoked Oracle’s moves to $19.50 and to $26.00, the number that effectively became the final price. At any point, shareholders who supported the deal at the then-current price and terms could have tendered their shares in a public display of support for Oracle’s offer. The tender *123 history is indicative of the discipline and organic organization of the shareholder base: 56 Percentage of PeopleSoft Shares Tendered TABULAR OR GRAPHIC MATERIAL SET FORTH AT THIS POINT IS NOT DISPLAYABLE The picture is a striking display of discipline. More impressive, though, is the final (pre-settlement) tender result - 61%. As discussed above, that was the result of a coercive situation. But even in the face of such coercion, it was a highly choreographed affair where shareholders (not perfectly, but reasonably well under the circumstances) gave Oracle the victory it needed while avoiding a result that might induce confidence or complacency. © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 9 WILLIAM GOLDMAN 9/20/2011 For Educational Use Only BETWEEN WILMINGTON AND WASHINGTON: LESSONS..., 12 Harv. Negot. L.... This was, I think, a particularly interesting moment with regard to the doctrine of substantive coercion. The shareholders I spoke with thought $24 was a fair price and would have accepted it if they had been forced into doing so with a credible take-it-or-leave-it offer. But shareholders did not, as a result, clamor to accept the $24 offer. Shareholders bargained. While chastising PeopleSoft for its intransigence, they offered support to the board in its demand for a higher price. And they correctly called Oracle’s bluff. They saw past the “best and final” bluster, they homed in on Oracle’s desperation as the critical clue to its mindset, and they demanded a higher number. This message was conveyed in meetings, through the press, through *124 the tender, and, as always, through the market. Consider PeopleSoft’s stock price for the week ended December 9th. This was the week following the tender but before settlement or trial. (December 9th was the day of Vice Chancellor Strine’s momentous conference call although, of course, no one knew that at the time.) PSFT Price--Week of December 9th TABULAR OR GRAPHIC MATERIAL SET FORTH AT THIS POINT IS NOT DISPLAYABLE Since PeopleSoft had already rejected $24, the earliest that a $24 bid could reasonably be received by shareholders would be following a proxy contest at the end of March 2005. Thus, purchasing stock at $24 in December 2004 would produce a negative return if you believed $24 was “best and final” (i.e. if you bought the stock on December 10, 2004, and received $24 in cash from Oracle on April 1, 2005, you would have a negative real return). Add to this that the trading level was widely believed to be $16 on a standalone basis giving the stock a 33% downside if Oracle gave up. The market clearly did not believe $24 was “best and final.” There are an infinite number of ways to parse the probabilities, but suppose the market thought there was a 10% chance of the deal falling apart and a 40% chance of receiving $24 on April 1st. Then at $24, the market was “expecting” a negotiated settlement (with 50% likelihood, the complement of the other two scenarios) at $26.50, exactly where it happened. Clearly shareholders were demanding more from Oracle. As one shareholder told Oracle, “This is your moment. But you have to pay up to get a friendly deal done.” *125 It was just such a shareholder who finally provoked the admission from Oracle that it had more in its pocket and conveyed this information to PeopleSoft. Thanks to Vice Chancellor Strine, that information became the basis for a deal, but it should make one wonder - it certainly made Strine wonder - why this had to come through an unnamed investor. Were the parties who actually carried fiduciary responsibilities (unlike the shareholder) unable to just sit down and have this conversation? What happened to the model of the board as a loyal bargaining agent for disaggregated and naïve shareholders? B. Your Stockholders Are Not Stupid . . . or Disaggregated The reality is that shareholders are not nearly as simple or as disaggregated as the substantive coercion doctrine presumes. This fact was noticed by many in the early 1990s with regard to institutional investors. At the time, it became the subject of a substantial amount of academic work.57 I think an equally important development, and one that has not received nearly the attention, is the rise of hedge funds. Hedge funds figured prominently in the Oracle-PeopleSoft case and their influence is felt in almost every takeover contest. Hedge funds now control over $1 trillion in assets, 58 making them a formidable market force more or less on par with the $8 trillion mutual fund industry.59 Hedge funds may control fewer assets than mutual funds and other institutional investors, but they are more sophisticated, more willing to hold undiversified positions (if they were not, they would have trouble outperforming the market) and more willing to be activistic. Having higher tolerances for risk and facing far less regulatory oversight than their institutional peers, they are in fact drawn to activistic and control situations since those situations offer outsized returns. Increasingly, hedge funds are themselves the activists (Icahn and JANA with Kerr-Mcgee) or the bidders (see, for example, the recent bid by Highland for Circuit City). Hedge funds have been called, derisively, a compensation scheme and not an asset class. This refers to the ubiquitous 1-and-20 fee *126 structure that they charge clients, 1% management fee and 20% of the returns (the carry). Aside from making a number of people very wealthy, I think this compensation scheme has implications for shareholder activism. Hedge funds are constantly looking for new ways to produce market out-performance in order to justify their fees. At the same time, hedge fund managers have far more to gain personally from a successful investment than their peers at institutions. This is turning them into activists in a way that other institutional investors have never been. It is important to note in this regard that © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 10 WILLIAM GOLDMAN 9/20/2011 For Educational Use Only BETWEEN WILMINGTON AND WASHINGTON: LESSONS..., 12 Harv. Negot. L.... the absolute size of hedge fund holdings is not an accurate measure of their importance to takeovers if there is reason to believe, and I would argue that there is, that they are more likely to be the shareholders in activistic and control situations than their institutional peers. A good example of this last phenomenon is the recent MCI situation. Hedge funds may not make up a large percentage of all U.S. telecom holdings, but the MCI shareholder list is a veritable who’s who of the hedge fund industry. Hedge funds are not everywhere, just the places where it matters most. One reason that the influence of hedge funds has not, I think, been sufficiently appreciated is that they are largely unregulated and culturally averse to disclosure. For every Carl Icahn, there are three or four hedge funds whose name no one has heard of taking large and influential positions. This phenomenon has been abetted by Wall Street, which makes enormous profits fronting for hedge funds, and by the emergence of a liquid derivatives market. For example, in the recent attempted buyout of Woolworth Plc by Apax, Deutsche Bank was holding 17% of Woolworth’s stock. This was almost certainly to hedge total return swaps with hedge funds, i.e., the stock was being held by the hedge funds and Deutsche was fronting for them. 60 As the recent King-Mylan deal showed, derivatives have complicated the landscape in innumerable ways largely beyond the scope of this paper. It is worth noting, though, that the influence of hedge funds is systematically underappreciated due to the lack of disclosure. A number of the investors that I interviewed, large PeopleSoft holders, were hedge funds. Although hedge funds are hot, institutional investors are still king. In recent years, they have grown more sophisticated as well and they are increasingly less willing to blindly support management. Investors that I spoke with attributed this phenomenon in part to Enron and related scandals. They also thought Regulation *127 FD, the SEC rule requiring equal disclosure, had played a large role in increasing institutional activism. Regulation FD upset the cozy relationships many institutional investors enjoyed with company managements and thereby lowered the costs of taking positions contrary to management. Hedge funds and institutional investors create a formidable and thoughtful shareholder base for modern corporations as was evident in Oracle-PeopleSoft. The model of an unsophisticated investor, unwilling or unable to actively oppose management is inconsistent with the realities of the modern market and contradicted by the sophistication exhibited by shareholders in Oracle-PeopleSoft. One final point with regard to shareholder sophistication. To the extent the assumptions of substantive coercion accurately depict some shareholders, to the extent some shareholders actually are too eager to sell at an insufficient price, that subset of shareholders is quickly relieved of its shares. This final point illustrates what is perhaps the most basic absurdity of the substantive coercion doctrine. Not even Delaware has closed the stock exchange. During the 18 months that PeopleSoft resisted Oracle, 2,784,809,000 shares traded. This is 7.4 times the total PeopleSoft shares outstanding. This was an extremely liquid market. If at anytime a shareholder believed the price, which was at all times a function of Oracle’s bid, to be sufficient, he could (and did) sell. Of course, the very people most in need of protection are also the first to sell their shares. Thus substantive coercion does nothing to protect those who actually exhibit “ignorance or mistaken belief” about value. Rather, through the Darwinian operation of the NYSE, their shares gravitate to holders who know what they are worth. C. With Friends Like These: The Board as a Loyal Bargaining Agent Oracle-PeopleSoft also suggests that boards may not be loyal bargaining agents. The poison pill has three primary justifications: 1) it gives the board the opportunity to communicate its story about true value; 2) it gives the board the opportunity to search for an alternative; and 3) it allows the board to act as a bargaining agent. PeopleSoft’s board failed miserably on 1 as the preceding discussion showed. They tried and failed on 2. Thus, after the first few months and certainly by fall 2004 (as Vice Chancellor Strine implied), 3 was the only justification sustaining their use of the pill. *128 But PeopleSoft’s board was never looking to bargain. Neither Conway nor Duffield, the CEOs during the contest, ever had any intention of doing a deal with PeopleSoft. The board implemented a series of defenses at least two of which had an extreme no-hand character. These defenses were the CAP and the antitrust review. The no-hand character of the CAP derived from the fact that it was a bargained-for contract with a third party. The no-hand character of the antitrust review derived from the government’s power to enjoin the transaction. In Quickturn, the Delaware Supreme Court rejected a poison pill with a far milder no-hand character. The Court (unhelpfully) justified this on the ground that the board did not have the authority to implement such a pill under § 141(a) of the Delaware General Corporation Law. This does not make a lot of sense given that the board has the power to precommit the corporation in other ways, such as through a CAP. A better critique of such devices is that they are inconsistent with directors’ fiduciary duties, the analysis offered by Vice Chancellor Jacobs in Toll © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 11 WILLIAM GOLDMAN 9/20/2011 For Educational Use Only BETWEEN WILMINGTON AND WASHINGTON: LESSONS..., 12 Harv. Negot. L.... Brothers. In any case, such devices are highly suspect under Delaware law and they evince an intention on the part of the board and management to preclude a transaction completely rather than negotiate to an appropriate price. This is why Gibson Dunn, PeopleSoft’s own counsel, warned against them. PeopleSoft’s motivation was made clear by Conway who urged his board to invite antitrust review because if the DOJ did not enjoin the transaction, it was “completely and only a matter of money.” Conway and the board did not seem to understand what their fiduciary duties required and they certainly were not loyal bargaining agents. What it means to negotiate a sale is that you are arguing over a price. Price is, by definition, “completely and only a matter of money.”61 If the price is high enough, you have done your job and you accept it. This unwillingness to bargain was also reflected in the Orwellian argument that became the last refuge of PeopleSoft’s board: we have a price but we can not tell anyone, because if we negotiate or show any interest, all our customers will leave. As Vice Chancellor Strine agreed, this argument is clearly disingenuous. How naïve could customers be? They had already endured an 18-month hostile takeover contest. But it was the one argument that preserved PeopleSoft’s twin desiderata: satisfy the Delaware burden of willingness to negotiate and do not negotiate. If it were not for an activist shareholder, an activist judge and the honesty of Skip Battle, the one person on *129 PeopleSoft’s board who deserves some praise for his conduct, negotiations would probably never have taken place. D. Shareholder Communication is a Basic Impediment to Shareholder Bargaining Power In sum, Oracle-PeopleSoft suggests that boards may not be loyal agents. At the same time, the case study offers evidence that shareholders have both the sophistication and discipline to tussle with a suitor and the appropriate incentives to reach the right conclusion. But the case for shareholders should not be overstated. They are not the board’s equal in negotiating power, not even close (though perhaps this is compensated for by the alignment of incentives). The power of shareholders is constrained in a number of ways (rational apathy, for example). One of the most substantial handicaps, and one that is completely artificial, is the limitation on communication created by the federal securities regime. The communication problem is pervasive, and it is difficult to identify particular events in the Oracle-PeopleSoft saga that might have been otherwise if the federal regime were not so exacting. Such a hypothetical requires us to entertain counterfactuals with so many variables as to be almost meaningless. How can we know who would have said what, and to whom, and when, had they not been prevented from doing so by the federal rules? Nonetheless, Oracle-PeopleSoft does offer some hints at the possibilities of enhanced shareholder communication. First, as I have argued throughout this paper, shareholders were quite effective at delivering their message even without being able to effectively communicate. This suggests that if they could more easily coordinate, they would be quite formidable. Second, PeopleSoft showed genuine responsiveness to CapRe, its largest holder. The loss of CapRe’s support was a critical turning point in PeopleSoft’s thinking and the moment I would identify when the “just say never” constituency began to lose out to Skip Battle. If CapRe had been able to deliver this message in coordination with other holders, it might have been able to turn events toward a negotiated settlement earlier (as it is, it seems CapRe effectively brokered the deal). But the problem and potential of shareholder communication was most obvious during the highly choreographed November 19th tender contest. Shareholders were in a tough position. PeopleSoft’s unwillingness to create a bid-ask (announce before the tender deadline an intention to redeem the pill if Oracle raised its offer) made this something of a Soviet election: there was only one side to vote *130 for. Shareholders faced risk if a majority were not tendered (30% downside) but also risk if the majority tendered were overwhelming and induced complacency (the last $2.50 extracted represented a 10% increase worth $1.1 billion to shareholders). PeopleSoft was no help in this matter; their interest was in seeing Oracle lose. They wanted to take advantage of shareholders’ desire to make this close in order to trick shareholders into tendering too few shares. Oracle was no help in the matter; their interest was in unqualified victory. So Oracle was spreading disinformation trying to scare shareholders into tendering. They were telling shareholders in the final hours that they had heard CapRe was pulling its shares and that a majority would not be achieved. This was, as it turned out, not true. CapRe tendered and even if it had not an (albeit slim) majority would have been achieved. In the middle of this were shareholders who had to sort this out on their own. The logical way to overcome this would be to work together. The problem was that if shareholders came together and coordinated their tender, they would almost certainly be in violation of at least § 13(d) and Rule 14d-9.62 This dynamic highlights, I think, one of the critical reasons for increased shareholder communication. Often in takeover situations neither side is adequately representing the interests of shareholders. As Oracle-PeopleSoft demonstrates, the federal limitations on shareholder communication have handicapped the ability of investors to act as effective bargaining agents. But this suggests a more basic problem with the evolution of Delaware law © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 12 WILLIAM GOLDMAN 9/20/2011 For Educational Use Only BETWEEN WILMINGTON AND WASHINGTON: LESSONS..., 12 Harv. Negot. L.... that has gone largely unnoticed. During the 1980s Delaware ratified the use of the poison pill. Then, through a series of decisions I have reviewed, Delaware gave directors incredibly broad discretion to deploy the pill with its endorsement of the always available doctrine of substantive coercion. These changes in the law hamstrung investors in dealing with disloyal managements by impeding the disciplinary effects of the market for corporate control. Thus, as was evident in Oracle-PeopleSoft, “just say no” has made investors increasingly subject to the “jejune, playground, adolescent, macho”63 antics of a company’s officers and directors. The one safety valve that has been preserved is the shareholder franchise: proxy out. In Delaware’s view, the appropriate response to a disloyal management is to oust them in an election. As Vice Chancellor Strine has argued, “Because the acquirer could simply elect a new board that could redeem the pill, use of the pill could *131 not be viewed as a fatal obstacle to the bid, and thus as injurious to the interests of target company stockholders.”64 E. The Tension Between Wilmington and Washington Unfortunately, Wilmington and Washington were not talking to each other. At the same time that Delaware law was evolving to place its faith in proxy contests as the primary source of market discipline, Washington’s regulation of that very proxy system, regulation that was originally designed to protect shareholder voice, was perverted through, among other things, capture by the managerial class. As was clear from the discussion in Part II, the federal proxy regime is now a formidable impediment to shareholder voice, not its champion. Professor Lucian Bebchuk has concluded from his extensive work on the shareholder franchise, “Although shareholder power to replace directors is supposed to be an important element of our corporate governance system, it is largely a myth. Attempts to replace directors are extremely rare, even in firms that systematically under-perform over a long period of time.”65 As Professor Bebchuk is fond of pointing out, under the current regime directors are more likely to be struck by lightning than to be replaced by shareholders in a contested election. Unfortunately, it is this proxy regime, crippled by regulation, for the most part perfunctory and ineffective, that Delaware relies on to counter managerial self-interest. It is this tension that makes Delaware’s compromise so unsatisfactory. Delaware put proxy out at the center of its thinking even though the regulatory regime governing proxy contests is not its prerogative. Washington developed checks on proxy contests and tender offers because it believed proxy contests and tender offers were not sufficiently regulated by the states. Senator Williams, for example, was concerned by the prevalence of tender offers and the threats they posed to “proud, old companies.” When Delaware later sought to curb tender offers in the 1980s it presumed, I think somewhat naïvely, an effective shareholder franchise that it could itself protect and defend through decisions such as Blasius. 66 But Blasius and its progeny are only half the story. The data provided by Professor Bebchuk and others suggest that the regulations Washington imposes are often outcome-determinative in themselves. As is often the case in law, the greatest effect of the federal regulations is not on the contests that *132 happen, but on the ones that never occur because the regulation has deterred them. I believe we can interpret the dearth of meaningful director elections as a reflection, at least in part, of Washington’s regulation. In making proxy out the linchpin of its thinking regarding poison pills, Delaware imported all the shortcomings of the federal regime. These shortcomings upset the balance Delaware was seeking by acting as a thumb on the scale in favor of management. Part of Delaware’s thinking was, I believe, that anyone with the resources to launch a tender would also have the resources to wage a proxy contest. Along these lines, a dichotomy is often made by academics between contests by a potential acquirer and contests generally.67 This distinction is not without merit. As far as it goes, it is true that many people (certainly not all 68) with the resources to launch a tender offer will have the resources to effectively fight a proxy contest and the inclination to do so. But this is not the end of the inquiry. First, it does nothing to address the situation of shareholders who prospectively want the ability to consider tender offers. If a shareholder believes that use of the poison pill generally is inefficient (as a majority today seem to, given the success of shareholder bylaw proposals on the matter), or if a shareholder just wants a board of directors who believe in the time-limited use of the pill but not in just-say-no, then the shareholder has little recourse. He faces all the obstacles to achieving these results created by the federal regime without the aid of a well-funded acquirer to help him. But such prospective exercise of proxy out is as important as the retrospective exercise. To be sure, some bidders will endure 18 months of turmoil, an antitrust trial in federal court, a tortious interference trial in California, a fiduciary duty trial in Delaware, being saddled with a $2.4 billion contingent liability and $200 million in parachute payments and an extra company it did not intend to buy, in order to close a deal. But some bidders will be deterred by that. For proxy out to be a viable concept, it cannot simply mean © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 13 WILLIAM GOLDMAN 9/20/2011 For Educational Use Only BETWEEN WILMINGTON AND WASHINGTON: LESSONS..., 12 Harv. Negot. L.... that shareholders have the ability to retrospectively undo the scorched-earth policies of a disloyal board. Such a system imposes all the costs of disloyalty on shareholders - on shareholders, that is, who know they have a disloyal board and want to oust it - by effectively forcing them to wait to oust their disloyal *133 board until a bidder emerges (the premise being that it is only the bidder who has the resources to run the proxy contest). This is silly. If proxy out is to be meaningful, it must be as much prospective as retrospective. Certainly, it means that a potential acquirer can fund a proxy contest to oust a board that is blocking the acquirer’s tender with a pill. But it has to also mean that prospectively shareholders can ensure that their board has an opinion regarding fundamental transactions that is reasonably similar their own. Once you admit this last fact, though, the dichotomy between contests over a bid and contests on a clear day is not consequential. Even in the context of contests where a tender has already been launched - contests over a bid - it is wrong to assume that the interests of a bidder and the interests of target shareholders are aligned. This is an important lesson of Oracle-PeopleSoft. Recall the investor who told Oracle that “while I supported what they were doing, I was a PeopleSoft shareholder, not an Oracle shareholder, and it wasn’t their interests that I was looking out for.” Just because a bidder has made a premium offer does not mean that it is suddenly part of a holy alliance with shareholders against an entrenched and disloyal target board. In Oracle-PeopleSoft, Oracle did a number of things that were quite unhelpful and not in the interests of target shareholders. Oracle launched an unreasonably low offer and used the offer to disrupt PeopleSoft’s business (see the “twist in the wind” e-mail).69 Oracle spread disinformation in an attempt to convincingly win the tender. Oracle’s executives used the Delaware trial to talk down the price. PeopleSoft acted badly, but Oracle was not on the side of the angels. It is really a function of how poorly PeopleSoft’s board conducted itself that anyone might think so. The apparent alliance between a bidder and target shareholders that arises from their mutual opposition to a target’s disloyal board is fictitious. A bidder and shareholders may agree that a target’s disloyal board is not doing its duty, but their interests quickly diverge after that. A bidder wants to purchase a company at the lowest possible price. A shareholder wants the bidder to overpay. Thus, even if proxy out is only analyzed in the context of a bid, the existence of a bidder does not solve any issues. If PeopleSoft’s *134 board had stood for election in March 2005 (that is, if a negotiated deal had not been reached) and Oracle’s slate had won, the newly elected directors would have voted, with considerable justification, to accept the $24 offer over which the election was conducted. But PeopleSoft shareholders did not want a board that thought $24 was the right price. They did not want a board of Oracle shills. They also did not want a board that had adopted the strange, Orwellian view that although there was a price for the company, it could never ever tell anyone. And perhaps if shareholders had been forced to choose between a board of Oracle shills and a board that would never negotiate, they would take the shills. But what they really wanted was a board that would, at the appropriate time and with the appropriate confidentiality, sit down with Oracle like adults and conduct a hard-nosed but fair negotiation. If shareholders do not have the ability to represent their own interests effectively in a proxy contest (as opposed to just voting for a bidder’s representatives) then they really face a Hobson’s choice - as they would have in an Oracle-PeopleSoft proxy contest - between a disloyal board who does not want any deal and a supine board that wants to sell at too low a price. PeopleSoft shareholders did not want $24 and they did not want $16, they wanted $26.50. F. Unburden Shareholder Communication The shortcomings of proxy out arise because the doctrine exists in the nexus between Wilmington and Washington. This interaction of federal and state law offers multiple avenues for reform but also raises the legitimate fear that an adjustment in one city will be frustrated by changes in the other. I believe the most elegant and most promising reform is also the simplest. Unburden the shareholder. Pare back the anachronistic restrictions on shareholder communication that have chilled dialogue and coordination. The benefits of enhanced communication could be achieved with two rather straightforward adjustments to the federal regime. Both reforms have been suggested at various times by other commentators, 70 but I see little point in sacrificing elegance for originality. First, expand the rather arbitrary 10-or-fewer exemption into a full-fledged big-boy exemption. Such a rule would exempt all solicitations between qualified institutional investors. The sophistication of shareholders in the modern marketplace - the sophistication that was evident in Oracle-PeopleSoft - means that shareholders can *135 evaluate solicitations from other shareholders without handholding by SEC staff attorneys. The paternalism is simply inappropriate at this point in the evolution of our securities markets. Furthermore, as hedge funds and institutional investors increasingly predominate, the reform would make the proxy rules increasingly less important. It has the nice feature of varying regulation (roughly) with the sophistication of the market. © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 14 WILLIAM GOLDMAN 9/20/2011 For Educational Use Only BETWEEN WILMINGTON AND WASHINGTON: LESSONS..., 12 Harv. Negot. L.... A second critical reform would be to scale back Regulation 13D. Although academic discussion often focuses on the proxy rules, it is immediately clear in speaking with shareholders that 13D is what they fear. One adjustment would be to raise the disclosure threshold from 5%. Having a tender offer early warning system was substantially more critical in 1968 before the advent of the pill. Today, shareholders in most companies cannot aggregate more than 15 or 20% without going to the board anyway. The 5% threshold is anachronistic. A second (more realistic) adjustment to Regulation 13D would be to narrow the activities that result in group formation. At the very least, voting groups should be excluded. A better rule might be crafted that also exempted other activities (holding, acquiring, disposing) in situations where control was not at stake. These two reforms would go a long way towards enhancing shareholder voice and reestablishing the shareholder franchise as a functional check on management. For example, in the context of Oracle-PeopleSoft, they would have allowed a large voting block of holders to form and effectively negotiate with Oracle, preempting management’s entrenchment. By enhancing the shareholder franchise, the reforms would operate to rebalance Delaware’s jurisprudence, which has tipped in favor of management as a result of Delaware’s misplaced reliance on proxy out. Oracle-PeopleSoft suggests that shareholders can be trusted. In fact, they were the only constituency in our case study that deserved the law’s trust and deference. They were not duped by small premia; they were not adverse to an efficient transaction. They were neither supine nor obstinate. And they remained dispassionate in a contest animated by personal vitriol. This is not due to their high moral character, their information, or their intelligence. It is, rather, just another example of self-regarding owners in a market reaching an efficient result. This is perhaps the most basic reason to prefer shareholder communication as the avenue of reform. It is adaptive. Unrestrained, sophisticated shareholders will devise imaginative solutions to situations that we cannot now predict. And, as a result, that we don’t have to. Footnotes d1 David Millstone, J.D., magna cum laude, Harvard Law School, 2005. dd1 All quotes from George “Skip” Battle, David Duffield and Craig Conway come from author interviews, unless otherwise noted. 1 David Marcus, Oracle Case Moot, Daily Deal, Dec. 14, 2004. 2 See, e.g., the comments of Karl Will, JP Morgan’s head of technology M&A in Britt Erica Tunick, The Oracle from Oracle, Inv. Dealers’ Dig., Feb. 7, 2005, at 26-32. (“Technology companies have traditionally shied away from hostile acquisitions, fearing that if the battle for a company upsets its employees, they may leave immediately after an acquisition. That’s a major issue because, in tech more than in many other industries, the value of the companies is closely linked to the talented individuals they employ. And even though that threat diminished after the dot-com bust left a lot of talent looking for work, and few rivals out there hiring it away, tech companies have remained leery of hostile tactics.”). 3 David Bank, After 18-Month Battle, Oracle Finally Wins Over PeopleSoft, Wall St. J., Dec. 14, 2004, at A1. 4 Olaf de Senerpont Domis, PeopleSoft Bows to Oracle, Daily Deal, Dec. 14, 2004. 5 Transcript of Telephone Conference at 16, Oracle Corp. v. PeopleSoft Inc., No. 20377 (Del. Ch. Nov. 24, 2004). 6 Id. 7 Henry G. Manne, Mergers and the Market for Corporate Control, 73 J. Pol. Econ. 110, 114 (1965). 8 Ronald J. Gilson, A Structural Approach to Corporations: The Case Against Defensive Tactics in Tender Offers, 22 Stan. L. Rev. © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 15 WILLIAM GOLDMAN 9/20/2011 For Educational Use Only BETWEEN WILMINGTON AND WASHINGTON: LESSONS..., 12 Harv. Negot. L.... 819, 845 (1981). 9 Id. at 889-90. 10 Id. at 890. 11 Moran v. Household Int’l, 490 A.2d 1059, 1080 (Del. Ch. 1985), aff’d, 500 A.2d 1346 (Del. 1985). 12 Id. at 1080. 13 Unitrin, Inc. v. Am. Gen. Corp., 651 A.2d 1361 (Del. 1995). 14 Unocal v. Mesa Petroleum, 493 A.2d 946 (Del. 1985). 15 Unitrin, 651 A.2d at 1387. 16 Blasius Indus., Inc. v. Atlas Corp., 564 A.2d 651 (Del. Ch. 1988). 17 Id. at 659. 18 Carmody v. Toll Bros., Inc., 723 A.2d 1180 (Del. Ch. 1998) (denying a motion to dismiss). 19 Mentor Graphics Corp. v. Quickturn Design Sys., Inc., 729 A.2d 25 (Del. Ch. 1998), aff’d on other grounds, 721 A.2d 1281 (Del. 1998). 20 Ronald J. Gilson & Reinier Kraakman, Delaware’s Intermediate Standard for Defensive Tactics: Is There Substance to Proportionality Review?, 44 Bus. Law. 247, 274 (1989). 21 Leo E. Strine, Jr., The Professorial Bear Hug: The ESB Proposal as a Conscious Effort to Make the Delaware Courts Confront the Basic “Just Say No” Question, 55 Stan. L. Rev. 863 (2002). 22 Id. at 864-65. 23 Adolph Berle & Gardner C. Means, The Modern Corporation and Private Property (rev. ed. 1968). 24 Securities Exchange Act of 1934, 17 C.F.R. § 240.14a (2006). 25 Jill E. Fisch, From Legitimacy to Logic: Reconstructing Proxy Regulation, 46 Vand. L. Rev. 1129 (1993). 26 H.R. Rep. No. 73-1383, at 13 (1934). The Rayburn Report was prepared by Congressman Rayburn to accompany a version of the © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 16 WILLIAM GOLDMAN 9/20/2011 For Educational Use Only BETWEEN WILMINGTON AND WASHINGTON: LESSONS..., 12 Harv. Negot. L.... bill similar in form to the bill that Congress eventually enacted. For a more involved discussion, see Fisch, supra note 25. 27 Fisch, supra note 25, at 1185. 28 John Pound, Proxy Voting and the SEC: Investor Protection Versus Market Efficiency, 29 J. Fin. Econ. 241 (1991). 29 Id. at 263 (quoting Tris Coffin, Proxy Warfare May Provoke Tighter Government Rules, Nation’s Bus., July 1955, at 92). 30 Id. at 280. 31 Id. at 279. 32 Stephen M. Bainbridge, Mergers and Acquisitions 10 (2003). 33 Bernard S. Black, Shareholder Passivity Reexamined, 89 Mich. L. Rev. 520, 566 (1990). 34 See, e.g., id. See also Thomas W. Briggs, Shareholder Activism and Insurgency Under the New Proxy Rules, 50 Bus. Law. 99 (1994); Bernard S. Black, Next Steps in Proxy Reform, 18 J. Corp. L. 1 (1993); John C. Coffee, Jr., The SEC and the Institutional Investor: A Half-Time Report, 15 Cardozo L. Rev. 837 (1994); Carol Goforth, Proxy Reform as a Means of Increasing Shareholder Participation in Corporate Governance: Too Little, But Not Too Late, 43 Am. U. L. Rev. 379 (1994); Mark J. Loewenstein, The SEC and the Future of Corporate Governance, 45 Ala. L. Rev. 783 (1994); Bernard S. Black, Next Steps in Corporate Governance Reform: 13(D) Rules and Control Person Liability, J. Applied Corp. Fin., Winter 1993, at 49. 35 Securities Exchange Act of 1934, 17 C.F.R. § 240.14a-3(a) (2006). 36 Id. § 240.14a-1(l). 37 Id. § 240.14a-2(b). 38 Id. § 240.14a-9. 39 Id. § 240.13d-1; 15 U.S.C.S. § 78m(d) (LexisNexis 2006). 40 17 C.F.R. § 240.13d-5(b). 41 Wellman v. Dickinson, 682 F.2d 355, 364 (2d Cir. 1982). 42 17 C.F.R. § 240.16b; 15 U.S.C.S. § 78p(b) (LexisNexis 2006). 43 For an interesting discussion, see Briggs, supra note 34. © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 17 WILLIAM GOLDMAN 9/20/2011 For Educational Use Only BETWEEN WILMINGTON AND WASHINGTON: LESSONS..., 12 Harv. Negot. L.... 44 Adam Wilmoth, Icahn Unveils Plans for Kerr-McGee; Investor Nominates Himself for Board, Oklahoman, Mar. 4, 2005, at B1. 45 Kerr-McGee Suit Claims Icahn Broke Federal Law, Gas Daily, Mar. 14, 2005, at 1. 46 Richard Siklos, How Icahn Rebranded from Raider to ‘Activist,’ Sunday Telegraph (U.K.), Apr. 24, 2005. 47 Ron Orol, ‘Parachutes’ Gain Popularity, Daily Deal, Dec. 13, 2004. 48 Axa Spreads its US Wings, Ins. Day, July 20, 2004. 49 MONY v. Highfields, 368 F.3d 138, 141 (2d Cir. 2004). 50 Id. 51 Id. at 146. 52 Fisch, supra note 25, at 1185. 53 Transcript of Telephone Conference, supra note 5. 54 Gilson & Kraakman, supra note 20. 55 Pre-Trial Brief of Plaintiff at 29, Oracle v. PeopleSoft, No. 20377 (Del. Ch. Nov. 24, 2004). 56 Slide prepared by Alexia Bertrand, Matt Fucci, Peter Massumi, Walter Scott and Matt Smith. 57 On the rise of institutional investors, see, e.g., Bernard S. Black, Agents Watching Agents: The Promise of Institutional Investor Voice, 39 UCLA L. Rev. 811 (1992); John C. Coffee, Jr., Liquidity Versus Control: The Institutional Investor as Corporate Monitor, 91 Colum. L. Rev. 1277 (1991). 58 Hedge Fund Research, Times (London), Apr. 28, 2005, at 48. 59 John Spence, MUTUAL FUNDS: The Boom After The Bust, Dow Jones News Service, May 2, 2005, available at Factiva. 60 Henry Sender, Mystery Shoppers, Wall St. J., Apr. 25, 2005, at C1. 61 Pre-Trial Brief of Plaintiff, supra note 55, at 1. 62 Securities Exchange Act of 1934, 17 C.F.R. § 240.14d-9 (2006). © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 18 WILLIAM GOLDMAN 9/20/2011 For Educational Use Only BETWEEN WILMINGTON AND WASHINGTON: LESSONS..., 12 Harv. Negot. L.... 63 Transcript of Telephone Conference, supra note 5. 64 Strine, supra note 21, at 877. 65 Lucian Arye Bebchuk, The Case for Shareholder Access to the Ballot, 59 Bus. Law. 43, 45 (2003). 66 See Blasius Indus., Inc. v. Atlas Corp., 564 A.2d 651 (Del. Ch. 1988). 67 See, e.g., Bebchuk, supra note 65, at 46. 68 One paper that I believe casts doubt on the willingness of a bidder to slog through a proxy contest is Lucian Arye Bebchuk, John C. Coates IV & Guhan Subramanian, The Powerful Antitakeover Force of Staggered Boards: Theory, Evidence, and Policy, 54 Stan. L. Rev. 887 (2002). 69 This was an email sent by investment banker Joseph Reece from Credit Suisse First Boston LLC, who was advising Oracle, to Safra Catz in which he described the initial bid as a ‘twist in the wind’ strategy. Reece advised Catz of Oracle to stay with this low bid ‘to create doubts in the minds of the market.’ In time, he wrote, ‘we should see a decline in the price [of PeopleSoft]’ (as reported by Susan Beck in Extreme Takeover, Am. Lawyer, May 2, 2005). 70 See, e.g., Briggs, supra note 34. End of Document © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 19