1 Cere The Problem of ‘Nature’ in Family Law Daniel Cere McGill University Symposium on Jurisprudence of Marriage and Committed Relationships Boston College, March 13, 2009 Introduction Current debates over the meaning of marriage are implicated in a wider set of debates over the meanings of “nature,” the “natural,” the “body, and the “biological” in law.1 David Delaney’s Law and Nature provides a comprehensive (and entertaining) survey of the varied legal renderings of “nature.” His study explores legal theories and cases dealing with natural disasters, wilderness preserves, endangered species, animal experimentation, reproductive technologies, bestiality, genetic screening, and criminal pathologies. Curiously, Delaney’s only investigation into the interface of law, nature, and sexual intimacy turns out to be his exposé of law’s interest in bestiality. Bestiality (or “zoophilia”), Delaney explains, is part of a wide class of sexually intimate acts uncontaminated by any extraneous procreative concerns. Bestiality’s complete disconnect from human procreative potential is usually assumed to be the basis for the traditional condemnation of bestiality as “unnatural.”2 However, according to Delaney, law’s condemnation of zoophilia is not really due to the fact that such acts “violate” nature, but due to the fact that they violate an unwritten sexual code of exclusive humanism that restricts erotic intimacy to the domain of the human. Zoophiles are too intimately and erotically involved with the natural. Their “back to nature” aspirations aim at fusion with the natural by crossing and penetrating the species divide.3 Richard Collier states that, “Family law, perhaps more than any other area of legal study, is concerned with this relationship of law and nature, with how the ‘natural’ connects, not just to the intimate, personal and ‘private parts’ of life—to sexual desires and activities, love and personal commitments—but also to ideas of community, sociality, and citizenship.” Richard Collier, “Male Bodies, Family Practices,” in Body Lore and Laws, edited by Andrew Bainham, Shelley Day Schlater, and Martin Richards, Oxford, Portland Oregon: Hart Publishing, 2002, pp.154 2 David Delany, Law and Nature, pp.6, 244. This is not to suggest that the zoophiles should be credited for accomplishing this disconnect. According to England’s distinguished family law scholar, Andrew Bainham, that honor should go to a Mr. Baxter. According to British common law, marriage must be “consummated” and this requires “full penetration of the vagina by the penis.” Mr. Baxter did accomplish this feat, but he happened to do it while wearing a condom. In a 1947 law case over the question of the “nullity” of the Baxters’ marriage that eventually reached the House of Lords, the legal status of Mr.Baxter’s condomed penis was deliberated upon by the honourable members. In a decision that, according to Bainham, “has massive implications for us today,” the Lords ruled that Mr. Baxter’s condomed penis in Ms. Baxter’s vagina did constitute a conjugal “consummation.” Bainham argues that one can trace a direct line from this “hugely important” decision to contemporary debates over the conjugal rights of same-sex and transsexual couples. “Sexualities, Sexual Relations and the Law,” in Body Lore and Laws, edited by Andrew Bainham, Shelley Day Schlater, and Martin Richards, Oxford, Portland Oregon: Hart Publishing, 2002, pp.174-75 3 David Delany, Law and Nature, pp.6, 258. 1 2 Cere However, a new set of legal debates and court challenges over nature, humanity and conjugal intimacy have surfaced in the last half decade requiring some updating of Delaney’s account. These developments have been forcing zoophiles to make room for somewhat more conventional folk determined to affirm connections between conjugal intimacy and nature. The zoophiles now have company, namely defenders of the historic common law definition of marriage.4 Many legal scholars and some courts have dismissed these invocations of nature as fruitless efforts to anchor human sexuality in largely discredited ideological frames. But many others have been swayed by these appeals to the ‘natural’ nature of opposite-sex conjugality. If the critics prove to be successful in defeating these appeals, then zoophiles can bide their time and eventually reassert their claim to exclusive legal rights over the domain of ‘natural’ sexuality. However, the verdict is still out, and legal debates over the ‘nature’ and ‘naturalness’ of conjugal marriage are currently drowning out the nature-loving conjugal concerns of zoophiles. 1.1 Beyond Nature and the Body “‘Nature,’ as we know, is a word contrived in order to introduce as many equivocations as possible into all the theories, political, legal, artistic, or literary, into which it enters.”(Sir Leslie Steven). Stephen’s introductory comments to his discussion of Hobbes’s doctrine of the “state of nature” highlight the conceptual slipperiness of “nature.”5 His one-hundred-year old remarks also serve to correct near-sighted impressions that insight into the complex, elusive and promiscuous meanings of ‘nature’ should be credited to the conscious-raising power of contemporary postmodernism.6 Less than twenty years ago, Marilyn Strathern lamented that the concept of “nature” was a now a firmly established and fixed feature of contemporary discourse: “On the face of it, nothing today seems further from erosion than the concept of nature.”7 That observation is definitely dated. Today, concepts of ‘nature’ or the ‘natural’ are widely perceived to be complex, multivocal and elusive. According to Delaney, ‘nature’ is an unwieldy, polysemous, ambiguous, unstable, radically context-dependent, contingent, and an ‘ideologically saturated’ concept that requires scare quotes when used in polite company.8 4 Apologies to defenders of the historic common law definition of marriage who may take offense at this association – and to any offended zoophiles. 5 Sir Leslie Stephens, Hobbes, London: MacMillan, 1904, pp.173. 6 Such impressions and/or claims can derive from the variety of more recent studies on the equivocality of “nature.” See Klaus Eder, The Social Construction of Nature: A Sociology of Ecological Enlightenment, London: Sage, 1996; David Delaney, Law and Nature, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003; Kate Soper, What is Nature? Culture, Politics and the Non-Human. Oxford and Cambridge Ma.: Blackwell, 1995; Donna Haraway, Simians, Cyborgs, and Women: The Reinvention of Nature, New York: Routledge, 1991. Recognition of the equivocality of words is longstanding feature of Western literary scholarship and biblical criticism. 7 The context of her comments is a discussion of reproductive technologies: “Against a background of concern about the natural environment, constant reference is made to what is also natural in human behaviour, and nowhere is it more emphasized than in the debates over the new reproductive technologies.” Marilyn Strathern, Reproducing the Future: Essays on Anthropology, Kinship and the New Reproductive Technologies, Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1992. 55. 8 David Delaney, Law and Nature, pp. 15-17. 3 Cere Post-naturalism is pervasive in the post-Foucaultian world of sexual scholarship. Susan Bordo declares that “there is no ‘natural’ body. ...Our bodies, no less than anything else that is human, are constituted by culture.”9 Similarly, David Halperin insists that “sexuality is not a somatic fact; it is a cultural effect.”10 Major trajectories of sociological and legal scholarship are constructing theories of the body and gender that refuse any conversation with the discipline of biology.11 Suspicions of essentialist discourses on the body run so high in constructionist circles that Anne Bottomley feels compelled to adopt the acronym TB (“the body”) in order to reinforce her emphasis on “the empty/plenitude” of this semantic site.12 The body is view as a social “imaginary” deeply inscribed with gender specificity. 13 Sara Crawley and K.L. Broad argue “the consistency of gender performativity causes the belief in discrete biological sex categories, not vice versa... consistent dualistic gendered performances of the body give the illusion that masculinity and femininity and discrete categories of biological sex are real... gender feels ‘natural’ because it is well practices via performativity.”14 The body is a “performative construction,” a script that is “naturalized through repetition.”15 Given the dominance of certain scripts of corporeality, any focus on the body inevitably tends to gravitate towards a focus on the heterosexual binary of male/female. Ovid’s famous opening line of the Metamorphosis stating his “bent” to poetically revel in the endless transformation of “bodies changed into new forms” has taken on canonical status in the constructionist discourses on the body.16 A curious mix of biological and constructionist concepts dubbed the “new materialism” attempts to offers an account of biology that emphasizes the fluidity and plasticity of the material body itself.17 In this “new form of ‘corporeal materialism’” the body itself is perceived to be “nomadic” and “performative”: “the body is seen as an inter-face, a threshold, a field of intersection of material and symbolic forces; it is a surface where multiple codes of power and knowledge are inscribed; it is a construction that transforms and capitalises on energies of a heterogeneous and discontinuous nature.” 18 Part of the collaborative work of legal constructionist theories is to “burst the binary bubbles” of Susan Bordo, “Anorexia Nervosa: Psychopathology and the Crystallisation of Culture,” in Irene Diamond and Lee Quinby, eds., Feminism and Foucault: Reflections on Resistance Boston: Northwestern University Press, 1988, pp. 90. 10 David Halperiin, “Is there a History of Sexuality?” in The Lesbian and Gay Studies Reader, edited by H. Abelove, M. A. Barale, and D. M. Halperin, New York: Routledge, 1993, pp. 416 11 Tim Newton, Nature and Sociology, London and New York: Routledge, 2007, pp.20. 12 Anne Bottomley, “The Many Appearances of the Body in Feminist Scholarship,” pp.127, fn.2. 13 Moira Gatens, Imaginary Bodies: Ethics, Power and Corporeality, London and New York: Routledge, 1994. 14 Sara Crawley and K.L. Broad, “The Construction of Sex and Sexualities” in in Handbook of Constructionist Research edited by James A. Holstein and Jaber F. Gubrium, New York, London: the Guilford Press, 2008, pp.548. 15 Richard Collier, “Male Bodies, Family Practices,” in Body Lore and Laws, edited by Andrew Bainham, Shelley Day Schlater, and Martin Richards, Oxford, Portland Oregon: Hart Publishing, 2002, pp.153. 16 For example, Ovid’s opening line introduces Anne Bottomley’s essay, “The Many Appearances of the Body in Feminist Scholarship,” in Body Lore and Laws, edited by Andrew Bainham, Shelley Day Schlater, and Martin Richards, Oxford, Portland Oregon: Hart Publishing, 2002, pp. 127. 17 On the “new materialism” see Anne-Fausting Sterling, Sexing the Body: Gender Politics and the Construction of Sexuality, New York: Basic Books, 2006 and Myra Hird, Sex, Gender and Science, New York: Palgrave, 2004. 18 L. Braidotti, Nomadic Bodies, New York: Columbia University Press, 1994, pp.219 9 4 Cere male/female, nature/culture, corporeality/consciousness in order to create space for alternative and transgressive conceptualizations of the body.19 There is, so to speak, a mutual attraction between constructionist views of the body and legal conceptions of the body. The body is only meaningful for the law to the extent that it has become a thoroughly legalized category. In Bodies of Law, Alan Hyde delineates various discursive, constructed and performative constructions of the sexualized legal body, the “legal breast,” the “legal vagina,” and the “legal penis.”20 The claims and constraints of ‘nature’ are pushed aside; bodies are now the offspring of law. Biology offers the material stuff (“the array of bodily organs of different shapes and sizes and colours”) but discourse gives us the normative categories through which the body becomes meaningful and visible.21 Delaney’s exploration of law and nature concludes with a marriage of constructionism and law arguing that the natural world or material world is “constituted by the legal.” Law, he argues, “participates in the process of constituting the material: reorganizing it, transforming it, penetrating it, preserving it.”22 Delaney is highlighting not just a claim about “the social construction of reality,” but the “reality of social constructions.” 23 The legal, he argues, is performed and instantiated on bodies “on all bodies, in all places, and at all times.”24 Every instrument is a legal instrument, every body is a legal body, every location a legal location, every event a legal event, every intimacy a legal intimacy. The law is lurking in and pulsing through all “things.” Delaney legal materialism spotlights “the imperialism of the law vis-a-vis the social totality”: “all of the material world, all of the material artifacts of the cultural order of modernity, are the instruments through which “the legal” is realized in the world.” The power of law to thoroughly legalize the material dimensions of human existence is a pivotal instrument for “the destabilization of the taken-for-grantedness that hinders efforts to reimagine and reconstitute the world.”25 Delaney’s intoxicating, almost hallucinogenic, vision of the penetration of law into nature, may seem extreme. It appears to proclaim the final victory of nomos over physis. 26 But with the Therese Murphy, “Bursting Binary Bubbles: Law, Literature and the Sexed Body, in John Morison and Christine Bell, eds. Tall Stories: Reading Law and Literature. Aldershot, Dartmouth Publishing, 1996. 20 Alan Hyde, Bodies of Law, Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1997. 21 Alan Hyde, Bodies of Law, pp.258. 22 Delaney, Law and Nature, pp.404. 23 Stephen Pfohl, “The Reality of Social Constructions,” in Handbook of Constructionist Research edited by James A. Holstein and Jaber F. Gubrium, New York, London: the Guilford Press, 2008, pp.645-668. 24 Delaney, Law and Nature, pp. 405; also see John Law and Annemarie Mol, “Notes on Materiality and Sociality,” Sociological Review 43 (1995) 274-294. 25 Delaney, Law and Nature, pp.406. 26 Pheng Cheah and Elizabeth Grosz acknowledge the ways in which Western dualism highlights the normative and coercive power of the law or nomos over nature or physis can be a form of violence against “embodied differences.” But they reign in their critique noting that the recognition of embodied difference is “as dangerous as it is ethically imperative” because “a recourse to a notion of real differences in nature between the sexes can lead to legally sanctioned discriminatory treatment because ‘discrimination.. is only illegal or unconstitutional when the classes being compared are similarly situated’.” Pheng Cheah and Elizabeth Grosz, “The Body of the Law: Notes Toward a Theory of Corporeal Justice,” in Thinking Through the Body of the Law, edited by Pheng Cheah, David Fraser, and Judith Grbich, Washington Square, New York: New York University Press, 1996, pp.5. 19 5 Cere deconstruction of physis, it is difficult to contain claims to “ultimate authority” by nomos.27 Chief Justice of Canada’s Supreme Court, Beverley McLachlin, defines the sweep of law’s authority in a slightly different way to Delaney, but she seems to reach similar, somewhat Hobbesian, conclusions for this new leviathan. The law, she writes, “exercises an authoritative claim upon all aspects of selfhood and experience in a liberal democratic society.... [It] makes total claims upon the self and leaves little of human experience untouched.”28 1.2 Nature Endorsing Perspectives Time to get back to nature? Nature-dismissing perspectives may be prevalent today, but Western thought also has fairly significant “nature endorsing” traditions.29 Ancient Greek, Roman Stoicism, and Medieval thought were shaped by views of nature as a cosmic order or a “vast chain of being” that encompasses and situates human existence.30 In this view, nature is saturated with intelligibility, and all beings within nature exist in a continuum sharing both physical and psychical lines of kinship.31 Revised versions of this perspective can be found in postEnlightenment Romantic thought as well as contemporary deep ecologies that portray nature as an encompassing ecosphere. These “nature endorsing” views tend to advance an ethics that highlights a precautionary principle. Alexander Pope’s poetic version of this principle--“From Nature’s chain whatever link you strike, Tenth or ten thousandth, breaks the chain alike”—captures this inherent cautionary concern for disruptive interventions into the complex interconnections of the natural order.32 However, in contrast to the static and closed conceptions of nature in classicist world views, modern conceptions of nature attempt to provide an intelligible account of the historical, processual, dynamic, developmental, contingent, and evolutionary dynamics of nature.33 The chain of being turns out to be a spiralling double-helix chain of becoming that is constantly interacting and genealogically evolving with the world around.34 In a sense, this heightens precautionary concerns since there is no reassurance of any cyclical return to right order. The 27 For a discussions of the dialectic of nomos and physis in Western thought, see Louis Dupré, Passage to Modernity: An Essay in the Hermeneutics of Nature and Culture, New Haven: Yale University Press, 1993. Its impact on the evolution of legal theory is explored by Donald Kelley, The Human Measure: Social Thought in the Western Legal Tradition. Cambridge Ma.: 1990. 28 Chief Justice Beverley McLachlin, “Freedom of Religion and the Rule of Law” in Recognizing Religion in a Secular Society, Montreal and Kingston: McGill Queens University Press, 2004, pp. 14, 16. 29 The term “nature endorsing” is used by Charles Taylor to describe important trajectories of modern thought, Sources of the Self, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1989. Also see Noel Castree, “Socializing Nature: Theory, Practice, and Politics,” in Noel Castree and Bruce Braun, Social Nature: Theory, Practice, and Politics, Malden, Ma.: 2001, pp.6-8/ 30 Kate Soper, What is Nature? Culture, Politics and the Non-Human. Oxford and Cambridge Ma.: Blackwell, 1995, pp.21-25. 31 R.G. Collingwood, The Idea of Nature, Oxford: Clarendon, 1945, pp.3-4/ 32 Kate Soper, What is Nature? Culture, Politics and the Non-Human, pp.22. 33 On the significance of the modern shift from classicist to historicist world views see Bernard Lonergan’s influential essay, "Transition from a Classicist World View to Historical Mindedness" in William Ryan and Bernard Tyrrell, eds. A Second Collection, (Philadelphia: Westminster Press, 1975), pp.1-9 34 Margaret Somerville, “Old Nature, New Science: Respecting Nature, the Natural and Life” in Margaret Somerville, The Ethical Imagination, Toronto: Anansi Press, 2006, pp.95-156; for Somerville on the double-helix metaphor see pp.77-78. 6 Cere unique ecological and evolutionary assets of future generations will be decisively shaped by current choices. Contemporary social theorists have become critical of the dangers of an uncritical turn to thoroughgoing deconstructionist approaches to the natural. In What is Nature? Kate Soper argues against strong versions of social constructionism that consistently contextualize “nature” in ways that lead to a “denial of nature.”35 Some scholars in the social sciences are beginning to react to the dominance of the more extreme forms of social constructionism. They argue that we have witnessed a trade-off of biological reductionism for a form of “discourse determinism.”36 Others worry that strong constructionist theories of nature will lead to a form of relativism that treats the discourse on nature as the mere play of politics and power. While social constructionist perspectives feed left-of-centre libertarian agendas in the domain of sexuality and family, they also fuel right-of-centre libertarian agendas in the domain of ecology. Deep ecologist, Gary Snyder notes that constructionist arguments abound in right-wing parodies of ecological issues such as global warming, wilderness preservation, or endangered species protection. Ecological concerns are regularly debunked as political constructs designed to push particular liberal agendas.37 Justice Scalia’s dissenting opinion in Babbitt v. Sweet Home Chapter of Communities for a Greater Oregon (1995) offers evidence for Snyder’s concerns. Scalia argues that regulations which constrain human interventions into nature based on appeals to notions of “endangerment” represent little more than the play of discourse to promote particular political interests. He concludes that the legal construct of “endangerment” represents an “unreasonable and unlawful limiting of human freedom to transform the material world.” 38 Scalia’s argument is clothed in irony as he playfully dismisses ecological appeals to “nature” as cartoonish constructions that barely mask political interests. He shrugs off any serious consideration of the ecological arguments about changing ecosystems, habitats, or the dynamics of reproduction that anchor these concerns.39 References to the specificities of natural processes are treated special-interest pleading devoid of real legal significance. In Scalia’s world, the dominance of legal categories renders indivisible “the materialities of ecosystems and bodies.”40 Similar concerns are being raised about deep constructionist approaches to the human body and sexuality. Bryan Turner’s impressive body sociological work on nature and the “body” employs constructionist methods, however, he has two serious reservations about social constructionism as an ideological framework. First, Turner argues that “most constructionist accounts of the body neglect or deny our experiences of embodiment.” This, he argues, has “the consequence of 35 Kate Soper, What is Nature? Culture, Politics and the Non-Human, Oxford: Blackwell, 1995, pp. 250. But Soper immediately adds that many of our emancipatory gains are owed to our refusal to conform to nature. (pp. 251). 36 Tim Newton, Nature and Sociology, London: Routledge, 2007, p. 22. 37 Gary Snyder, “Is Nature Real?” Whole Earth Magazine, Winter 1998, www.wholeearthmag.com/ArticleBin/188.htm. 38 Comment on Scalia’s dissent by Delaney in Law and Nature, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003, pp.211. 39 David Delaney, Law and Nature, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003, pp.211-12. 40 For Scalia, Delaney notes, “The physicality of the world played no part in the stabilization of legal meaning.” Delaney, Law and Nature, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003, pp.212 7 Cere denying the very humanity of the agent. As the human body disappears behind the social and cultural constructions that produce it, the vulnerability of the human agent is also obscured.”41 He argues the social construction must not obscure the importance of the lived experience of embodiment. Second, he argues that the performativity” of the body is not free-floating, but deeply anchored in the biology of human life. Aging is not merely a discourse constructed and enforced by disciplines like gerontology.42 Disability is not a performance, it anchored in “real performative impediments associated with disability status.”43 Deep forms of social constructionism seem to miss the obvious “thingness” or quiddity (the “whatness”) of the human condition.”44 Kate Soper also raises some cautionary concerns for the “‘nature-sceptical’ critiques of progressive gender politics.” Constructionist discourses, she notes, now seem to dominate social and legal theories of sexuality. In their view, there is no domain of the “natural” distinct from the cultural discourses that construct and give meaning to ‘nature.’ Soper begins by warning her colleagues to temper the ideological edge of their assault and, in particular, to carefully avoid the temptation “to pit their ‘nature’ deconstructions against the ecological cause.”45 But Soper’s concerns go further. She notes that constructionist theories of sexuality have contributed to a fairly uncritical ethos of technological intervention into biology (abortion, contraception, reproductive technologies, sex change surgery, etc.) rather than the kind of “the ecological injunction to respect the rhythms and modalities of ‘nature’” characteristic of most environmental approaches.46 While Soper notes the “potentially reactionary dimensions of ecological naturalism,” she also points to “the limitations, and indeed ultimate incoherence, of the anti-naturalism professed in contemporary approaches to sexuality.”47 Human beings, like all other living creatures, are determined by biology in the sense that they are embodied, mortal entities with specific genetic endowments, and possessed of a particular sexual anatomy and physiology.48 Soper challenges the strong forms of constructionist “anti-naturalism” that deny the naturality not only of gender, “but that of sex and the body as well.”49 Theorist like Wittig, Delphy and Butler seek to utterly deconstruct “sex” as a category constructed to reinforce a heterosexual regime.50 Soper argues that “insofar as a theory of sexuality and the body denies a realist conception of nature, it is not only incompatible with ecological thinking, but incoherent in itself.”51 41 Byran S. Turner, “The Constructed Body,” in Handbook of Constructionist Research edited by James A. Holstein and Jaber F. Gubrium, New York, London: the Guilford Press, 2008, pp. 506. 42 Byran S. Turner, “The Constructed Body,” pp. 498. 43 Byran S. Turner, “The Constructed Body,” pp. 508. 44 Byran S. Turner, “The Constructed Body,” pp. 508. 45 Soper, What is Nature? pp. 120. 46 Soper, What is Nature? pp. 123. 47 Soper, What is Nature? pp. 124-25. 48 Soper, What is Nature? pp. 125-26. 49 Soper, What is Nature? pp. 127. 50 Soper, What is Nature? pp.128; see Diana Fuss’s discussion of Monique Wittig and Christine Delphy in Essentially Speaking: Feminism, Nature and Difference, London: Routledge, 1988 51 Soper, What is Nature? pp.131. 8 Cere Family law seems caught in the very throes of the constructionist revolution. However, social constructionism’s current dominance in the domain of discourse on sexuality and gender studies may prove to be transitory. When progressive and critical social theorists like Soper and Turner, scholars who have devoted a considerable amount of their attention to the question of “nature” and the “body,” begin to voice serious reservations about the hegemony of constructionist discourse it signals that we may be in the early stages of an intellectual shift. However, both Turner and Soper are clear that the way forward will be intellectually and morally demanding. Those sitting back waiting until it’s time to smugly flog the dead horses of constructionism won’t be shaping the future conversation. 2.1 ‘Nature Endorsing’ Perspectives in Family Law In the meantime, court cases and public debates continue to heat up. The place of the “natural” in family law and social theory may be on the endangered list, but it is not extinct.52 It has been a significant feature of the numerous legal decisions that have supported the historic common law definition of marriage. The argument from nature is viewed as the rational basis for law in Hernandez v. Robles (2006). While other supporting lines of argument are acknowledged, the court advances two grounds that “rationally support” the opposite-sex limitation on marriage. The first ground focuses on the “natural tendency” of opposite-sex intercourse to lead to the birth of children. The natural procreativity of opposite-sex bonding is the procreative fulcrum of human society. The institution of marriage is anchored in this natural foundation, namely “the biological fact that human procreation cannot be accomplished without the genetic contribution of both a male and a female.” Given the ecology of human procreation the state has ground to offer inducements in the form of marriage to opposite-sex couples to make a “solemn, long-term commitment to each other.” Second, the “binary nature of marriage” is sex-inclusive. Marriage not only creates an institutional frame for the natural ecology of opposite-sex procreativity both it also strives to create an enduring community between the parents and their offspring.”53 Morrison v. Sadler (2005) argues that the state has “a legitimate interest in encouraging opposite-sex couples to enter and remain in, as far as possible, the relatively stable institution of marriage for the sake of children who are frequently the natural result of sexual relations between a man and a woman.” 54 The natural sexual ecology of opposite-sex relationships sets in motion a dynamic generativity that requires institutional framing and support. Morrison argues that the non-procreative nature of same-sex coupling means that these relationships are “not at “risk” of having random and unexpected children by virtue of their ordinary sexual activities.” Therefore, the basis for laws extending marriage benefits to opposite-sex couples but 52 See the variety of voices in the recent 3 volume collection edited by A. Scott Loveless and Thomas B. Holman, The Family in the New Millennium: World Voices Supporting the Natural ‘Clan’ Westport Conn. & London: Praeger, 2007. For a full-throated proclamation of the “natural” in contemporary debates on the family see Allan C. Carlson and Paul T. Mero, The Natural Family: A Manifesto, Dallas: Spence Publishing, 2007. 53 Hernandez v. Robles, 7 N.Y.3d 338 (N.Y. Court of Appeals 2006) 54 Morrison v. Sadler, 821 N.E.2d 15 (Ind. Ct. App. 2005) 9 Cere not same-sex couples is reasonably related to a clearly identifiable, inherent characteristic that distinguishes the two classes: the ability or inability to procreate by “natural” means.”55 In Andersen v. King County, Justice Johnson cites “the unique and binary biological nature of marriage and its exclusive link with procreation and responsible child rearing” as a central plank of the rational basis argument for the common law definition of marriage.56 J. Johnson acknowledges that while there are “numerous rational bases” supporting the reaffirmation of marriage “as the union of one man and one woman,” sex-difference and the natural procreativity of opposite-sex relations provide the most fundamental foundations for law: The complementary nature of the sexes and the unique procreative capacity of one man and one woman as a reproductive unit provide one obvious and non-arbitrary basis for recognizing such marriage. The binary character of marriage exists first because there are two sexes. A society mindful of the biologically unique nature of the marital relationship and its special capacity for procreation has ample justification for safeguarding this institution to promote procreation and a stable environment for raising children.57 In contrast to U.S. developments, recent Canadian jurisprudence on marriage gives an appearance of comfortable consensus approaching near unanimity. However, the appearance is somewhat deceptive. Court challenges to the common law definition marriage were initially launched in three of the more liberal provincial jurisdictions in Canada (British Columbia, Ontario and Quebec) where the prospects for success for high. Given the prominence of these jurisdictions in the Canadian federation, favourable judgments would create a real momentum for change. However, the first judgment delivered by the British Columbia Supreme Court in Egan v. The Attorney General of Canada (2001) decided against the plaintiffs and reaffirmed the common law definition of marriage.58 The appeal to nature was central element in the Attorney General of Canada’s defence of the common law definition of marriage in all of the court proceedings. An oft quoted passage in the legal debates on same-sex marriage was an opinion from J. Forest in Egan v. Canada (SCC, 1995). Forest open highlighted the natural and “biological” basis of opposite-sex marriage: ...marriage has from time immemorial been firmly grounded in our legal tradition, one that is itself a reflection of long-standing philosophical and religious traditions. But its ultimate raison d'etre transcends all of these and is firmly anchored in the biological and social realities that heterosexual couples have the unique ability to procreate, that most children are the product of these relationships, and that they are generally cared for and nurtured by those who live in that relationship. In this sense, marriage is by nature heterosexual. It would be possible to legally define marriage to include homosexual 55 Morrison v. Sadler, 821 N.E.2d 15 (Ind. Ct. App. 2005) pp. 26-27. “Becoming a parent by using “artificial” reproduction methods is frequently costly and time-consuming. Adopting children is much the same. Those persons wanting to have children by assisted reproduction or adoption are, by necessity, heavily invested, financially and emotionally, in those processes. Those processes also require a great deal of foresight and planning. “Natural” procreation, on the other hand, may occur only between opposite-sex couples and with no foresight or planning. All that is required is one instance of sexual intercourse with a man for a woman to become pregnant.... 16) 56 Andersen v. King County, 138 P.3d 963 (Wash. 2006) 57 Andersen v. King County (2006) 58 Egale v. Canada, BCSC 1365, (2001) 10 Cere couples, but this would not change the biological and social realities that underlie the traditional marriage.59 The original Ontario Superior Court judgment in Halpern v. Canada (2002) was seen as the landmark decision insofar as it recognized a fundamental problem of discrimination in the current framework of Canadian marriage law. However, the judgment was also marked by a real hesitancy about the option to redefine marriage and this hesitancy was reflected in its decision to refer the issue back to the federal Parliament for deliberation. The first Halpern decision recognized the seriousness of the proposed legal transformation of marriage: … the consequences and potential reverberations flowing from such a transformation in the concept of marriage, it seems to me, are extremely complex. They will touch the core of many people’s belief and value systems, and their resolution is laden with social, political, cultural, emotional and legal ramifications. They require a response to a myriad of consequential issues relating to such things as inheritance and property rights, filiation, alternative biogenetic and artificial birth technologies, adoption, and other marriagestatus driven matters. The Courts are not the best equipped to conduct such a balancing exercise, in my opinion. This is not an incremental change in the law. It is a profound change.60 (emphasis added) The resolution of the Canadian marriage debate did not occur in a legal forum; it was settled by a tight political vote in sharply divided federal parliament. Margaret Somerville, one of Canada’s best-known public intellectuals and McGill’s Samuel Gale Chair in the Faculty of Law, made significant contributions to both the legal and the wider public debates over marriage. Somerville’s defence of the common law definition of marriage is grounded in a broader approach to legal ethics that emphasizes the principle of “a presumption in favour of the natural.” Her 2006 Massey lecture on “Respecting Nature, the Natural and Life,” develops this cornerstone of her ethical theory.61 Somerville acknowledges constructionist concerns about the elusive and shifting meanings of the natural. She also recognizes the difficulties of defining the relationship between the “natural” and the “cultural.” However, she argues that postmodern attempts to deconstruct and dismiss the significance of the “natural” pose serious threats to human life and flourishing at a number of fundamental levels: ecological, technological, biological, and anthropological. Deconstructions of nature also have a way of violating basic the rights and interests of those especially vulnerable to aggressive human intervention: children, the elderly, the infirm, the handicapped, non-human species, and ecosystems. Somerville argues that advancing a “basic presumption in favour of the natural” as a core ethical principle requires a consistent and coherent nature-respecting ethic to deal with the wide array of ecological, technological, bio-ethical, and anthropological issues that involve the complex interface between human choices and the diverse dimensions of nature.62 Over the years Somerville’s call for a consistent nature-respecting ethics has won her applause and approval in many academic and public forums as she tackled a wide range of complex 59 Egan v. Canada, [1995] 2 S.C.R. 513, par.536. Halpern v. Canada, (2002), par. 97-98. 61 Margaret Somerville, “Old Science, New Science: Respecting Nature, the Natural, and Life,” in The Ethical Imagination, Toronto: Anansi, 2006, pp.95-156. 62 Margaret Somerville, The Ethical Imagination, pp.107-109. 60 11 Cere ethical issues including treatment of the serious disabled, the use of animals in research, reproductive technologies, and transplant tourism. However, her decision to apply this ethic to debates over the marriage question instantly made her the centre of a firestorm of public controversy. Somerville recognizes that an emphasis on the importance of recognizing “innate differences” between men and women, as well as “natural differences” between opposite-sex and same-sex relationships, has often been employed to justify “horrible breaches of human ethics and human rights” victimizing both women and homosexuals.63 However, a consistent naturerespect ethics, Somerville argues, cannot stubbornly dismiss all appeals to nature in dealing with the domains of nature, biology, sexual difference, sexual bonding, procreation, and kin connection. Marriage is a cultural construct that builds upon and works with the natural sociosexual ecology of opposite-sex bonding, procreativity, and child-bearing. The institution of marriage strives to create and sustain a unique social context for a uniquely vulnerable human category, namely children. In her view, ethics should strive to valorize and support the “natural” connections between children and their biological parents. According to Somerville, “oppositesex marriage establishes as the norm and institutionalizes the inherently procreative relationship between a man and a women, and in doing so establishes children’s rights with respect to the links to their biological parents and families.”64 Somerville’s case against the redefinition of marriage has to be read as part of her contribution to the international conversation on the rights of children as well as her distinctive approach to the ethics of reproductive technologies. Somerville argues for an enriched conception of fundamental rights of children and specifies three categories of birth rights: “[1] children’s rights to know the identity of their biological parents; [2] children’s right to both a mother and a father, preferably their own biological parents; [3] and children’s right to come into being with genetic origins that have not been tampered with.”65 These rights are universal since conception, genetic lineage, gestation, birth, and childhood are universal features of the human condition. Her consistent nature-respect ethic, coupled with her specific appeal to recognize the natural birth rights of children, makes Somerville particularly wary of proposals to fundamentally redesign an institution that seems uniquely tailored to reinforce the natural bonds between children and their parents. It is one thing for children not to know their genetic identity as a result of unintended circumstances. It is quite another matter to deliberately destroy children’s links to their biological parents, and especially for society to be complicit in this destruction. Needless to say, many have not welcomed Somerville’s determination to ethically challenge attempts to redesign marriage in ways that legitimize the destruction of children’s birth rights and their connections to “natural” kin. The curious feature of Somerville’s appeal to nature on the marriage question is the way in which it is framed within the context of deep commitments to environmentalism, human rights and liberal values. The mix seems baffling to many of her intellectual adversaries and many of her allies. However, Somerville’s position on the marriage question is fully consistent with her with her contributions to a wide range of ethical issues, contributions that have been widely hailed for their progressive and ecologically sensitive ethical humanism. 63 Margaret Somerville, The Ethical Imagination, pp.100. Somerville, The Ethical Imagination, pp.102. 65 Margaret Somerville, The Ethical Imagination, pp.147. 64 12 Cere 2.2. ‘Nature Dismissing’ Perspectives in Marriage Law The legal arguments opposing the historic common law definition of marriage tend to simply brush aside arguments that appeal to the “natural” social ecology of opposite-sex bonds or the birth rights of children. The analysis that follows does not focus on the array of legal arguments put forward by these decisions to make the case for redefining marriage, but solely on the response of these decisions to arguments appealing to the ‘natural’ foundations of marriage. The California decision, In re Marriage Cases (2008), notes that a significant number of U.S. courts and legislatures did advance “rational basis” arguments in their defence of the oppositesex definition of marriage. However, in their presentation of the arguments, the California court side-steps the direct appeals to the natural ecology of opposite-sex procreativity in order to refocus exclusively on one related aspect of their argument. According to California court, the central argument of the “rational basis” defence hinges on a problematic feature of heterosexual bonding, namely the heterosexual bent towards accidental or unintended pregnancies. In the case same-sex couples, “parenthood necessarily is an intended consequence ...[that] requires considerable planning.” However, “in the case of an opposite-sex couple a child often is the unintended consequence of the couple's sexual intercourse.” This problematic feature of heterosexual coupling requires state mandated incentives “to ensure that accidental procreation is channelled into a stable family relationship.” In this version of the argument, “a similar incentive is not required for same-sex couples” since they do not “not produce children accidentally” (emphasis added).66 There are no concerns about irresponsible procreating for same-sex couples since every child is, so to speak, a wanted child. However, this re-framing of the rational basis argument by In re Marriage Cases ignores the key conceptual term (“natural”) as well as the core arguments from nature employed in Morrison and Hernandez to highlight the distinct significance of opposite-sex bonding and procreativity.67 For the California Supreme Court, the only relevant characteristic of this category of procreation is the high prevalence of “accidental” or “unintended” pregnancies. All references to arguments for the “natural” character disappear from the court’s deliberations.68 The “nature endorsing” 66 In re Marriage Cases, 183 P.3d 384 (Ca. 2008), pp.42. These two cases were specifically cited by In re Marriage Cases. See Morrison v. Sadler, 2003 WL 23119998 (Ind. Super. Ct. 2003) 68 The word “natural” only appears once in a footnote quoting from article 16 of the UDHR. The reference is used to support the argument for a universal right to marry, but there is no comment on the UDHR’s use of the term ‘natural’ to define the family. In re Marriage Cases, 183 P.3d 384 (Ca. 2008) pp. 63, fn. 41. “It is noteworthy that the California and federal Constitutions are not alone in recognizing that the right to marry is not properly viewed as simply a benefit or privilege that a government may establish or abolish as it sees fit, but rather that the right constitutes a basic civil or human right of all people. Article 16 of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights, adopted by the United Nations General Assembly in 1948, provides: “Men and women of full age, without any limitation due to race, nationality, or religion, have the right to marry and to found a family. . . The family is the natural and fundamental unit of society and is entitled to protection by society and the State.” Numerous other international human rights treaties similarly recognize the right “to marry and to found a family” as a basic human right.” 67 13 Cere approach of Morrison and Hernandez is countered by the “nature ignoring” stance of In re Marriage Cases. This pattern is repeated in other judgments. The challenge to arguments concerning the natural dimensions of opposite-sex bonding proceeds less by critical counter-argument than by “nature ignoring” lines of argument. Justice Kaye’s dissent in Hernandez only refers to the “natural” when she quotes Justice Marshall’s partly dissenting judgement in City of Cleburne v. Cleburne Living Ctr. (1985): "what once was a 'natural' and 'self-evident' ordering later comes to be seen as an artificial and invidious constraint on human potential and freedom."69 The citation from Marshall seems sufficient to dispense with the appeal to “nature.” A similar approach is taken in Kerrigan v. Commission of Public Health (2008).70 New Jersey’s Lewis v. Harris simply ignores arguments from nature.71 Justice Mary E. Fairhurst’s dissent in Anderson v. King County (2006) argues that the central “issue at stake” in this debate is not the natural or foundational nature of marriage but “the liberty to construct and define one's own family.” J. Fairhurst turns to Planned Parenthood v. Casey (1992) for a canonical text to highlight her argument: “Our law affords constitutional protection to personal decisions relating to marriage, procreation, contraception, family relationships, child rearing, and education. . . . These matters, involving the most intimate and personal choices a person may make in a lifetime, choices central to personal dignity and autonomy, are central to the liberty protected by the Fourteenth Amendment.”72 In re Marrriage Cases (2008) also emphasizes the fundamental right to conjugal intimacy as the core of the marriage bond: the right to marry is the right to enter into a relationship that is "the center of the personal affections that ennoble and enrich human life" -- a relationship that is "at once the most socially productive and individually fulfilling relationship that one can enjoy in the course of a lifetime." The personal enrichment afforded by the right to marry may be obtained by a couple whether or not they choose to have children, and the right to marry never has been limited to those who plan or desire to have children.73 The core issues raised in arguments appealing to nature are systematically ignored in these decisions. Does law need to consider the significance of sex-difference in social sexual ecology of human mating? Does it need to consider the ‘natural’ procreativity of opposite-sex bonds? Does the issue of children’s kin-connection and lineage merit legal consideration in defining the legal contours of marriage? One can surmise that the refusal or failure to engage these concerns might be grounded on the conviction that they lack any legitimacy or merely mask discriminatory perspectives. 69 Justice Kaye dissenting in Hernandez v. Robles, 7 N.Y.3d 338 (N.Y. Court of Appeals 2006), pp.5. Kerrigan v. Commissioner of Public Health (2008) See footnote 49: “The following comments of Justice Thurgood Marshall also are instructive in this regard: ‘‘[H]istory makes clear that constitutional principles of equality, like constitutional principles of liberty, property, and due process, evolve over time; what was once a ‘natural’ and ‘self-evident’ ordering later comes to be seen as an artificial and invidious constraint on human potential and freedom.” 71 Lewis v. Harris, 908 A.2d 196 (N.J. 2006) 72 Andersen v. King County (2006) 73 In Re Marriage Cases (2008) pp.43. 70 14 Cere In the landmark case of the Canadian marriage debate, Halpern v. Canada (2003), the Ontario Court of Appeal struck down the common law definition of marriage. The Attorney General of Canada did put forward arguments highlighting the ways in which marriage taps into a natural ecology of opposite-sex procreativity in human life. In response Justice Roy McMurtry admitted while it was “true” that due to the limitations of “biological realities, only opposite-sex couples could ‘naturally’ procreate,” nevertheless, it is largely irrelevant since same-sex couples can achieve the same goal by a wide array of methods such as adoption, surrogacy and donor insemination (par. 93). Justice McMurty then quickly dismisses the argument from nature arguing that the opposite-sex requirement is both over-inclusive (many opposite-sex couples are unable to have children or choose not to) and under-inclusive (excluding same-sex couples with children). The key issue, Justice McMurty concludes, is not the needs and capacities of opposite-sex couples: “The question to be asked is whether the law takes into account the actual needs, capacities and circumstances of same-sex couples, not whether the law takes into account the needs, capacities and circumstances of opposite-sex couples.” (par.91) The Supreme of Canada glanced at the question of the “natural limits of marriage” in its response to the Reference on Bill C38, The Civil Marriage Act. The justices note the core argument against redefining marriage maintains that “the institution of marriage escapes legislative redefinition” since “it is not a legal construct, but rather a supra-legal construct subject to legal incidents.” However, the justices impatiently dismiss this position arguing that institutions like marriage are evolving historical and legal constructs. Furthermore, they conclude that, The natural limits argument can succeed only if its proponents can identify an objective core of meaning which defines what is "natural" in relation to marriage. Absent this, the argument is merely tautological. The only objective core which the interveners before us agree is "natural" to marriage is that it is the voluntary union of two people to the exclusion of all others.74 Two points are worth noting in their brief discussion of the opposing view. First, the justices simply ignore rather than engage the arguments put forward to “indentify an objective core of meaning” that defines the “natural” character of the marital bond. They seem to assume that there is no argument that merits serious consideration and dismiss the stance as the mere assertion of a customary view that happened to be dominant in a particular historical context. Secondly, the only interveners who actually agreed with the justices’ formulation of the “objective core” of marriage were the interveners arguing for a redefinition of marriage according to that particular doctrine. The justices conclude that the proposal to re-define marriage is reasonable since everyone can agree on one “objective core” to marriage, namely that it is “a voluntary union of two persons to the exclusion of all others”--the exact formulation used by the contested Civil Marriage Act redefining marriage. According to this line of argument, the best way of escaping tautological thinking is simply to turn it on its head. What is noteworthy in the Supreme Court of Canada’s response is the refusal or unwillingness of the judges to engage the arguments defining marriage in terms of the ‘natural’ character of marital and familial bonds. These lines arguments had been widely circulated in part due to Somerville’s pivotal role as government expert witness in the various court cases as well as the 74 Reference re Same-Sex Marriage, 2004 SCC 79, para.27. 15 Cere robust public debate in the Canadian media and parliament. The arguments had received considerable support from a wide array of legal, political and public advocates. Most of the interveners in the Supreme Court reference who raised objections to the Civil Marriage Act appealed to children’s birth-rights and the “presumption in favour of the natural” lines of argument. The fact that they were not countered, or even merited recognition, suggests a deep ideological divide over the appeal to nature in the legal debates over the question of marriage. 3.1. Nature, Rights and the Family: Post-War Perspectives Despite the dismissive attitudes in many legal and academic circles towards arguments that appeal to nature, nevertheless discourse on the connection between nature, marriage and family is a longstanding feature of early modern and modern political thought. These appeals to the natural contours of marriage and family are deep features of the evolving liberal tradition as it struggled to define the relation of the state to this domain of human life. In recent history, this connection was strongly re-affirmed in the most widely hailed human rights document of the modern era, the Universal Declaration of Human Rights (UDHR). The initial drafting stages for the UDHR leaned heavily on the expertise of John Humphrey, a Canadian legal scholar who served as the secretary for the committee.75 Eleanor Roosevelt, the chair of the committee, commissioned Humphrey to get the process started by putting together a preliminary draft of the declaration.76 Humphrey’s original draft contained no mention of any rights related to marriage or family.77 However, the third version of Humphrey’s draft contained the following formulation: “Everyone has the right to contract a marriage in accordance with the laws of the state.”78 A slightly edited version of this formulation appeared in the first draft that was circulated to commission members.79 Humphrey’s proposal has three distinct elements: (1) marriage is a universal (“everyone”) right; (2) marriage is defined as a “contract”; (3) the right to marry is defined and qualified by state law. This conception of marriage rights seems to cohere with current approaches which view marriage as a construct of state law. The Goodridge decision to re-define marriage is grounded, 75 On the drafting process see: Johannes Morsink, The Universal Declaration of Human Rights: Origins, Drafting and Intent Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, and Mary Ann Glendon A World Made New: Eleanor Roosevelt and the Universal Declaration of Human Rights. New York: Random House, 2001, 76 For forty years authorship was attributed to René Cassin, French jurist and member of the drafting commission. Cassin did little to correct this misleading view. The historical record was corrected by John Hobbins’ landmark essay, “René Cassin and the Daughter of Time: The First Draft of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights, in Fontanus 2 (1989) 77 The Humphrey draft included in the appendix to Glendon’s is a later version that was circulated to the committee. The text of Humphrey’s original handwritten draft can be found in Hobbins’ essay on Humphrey’s authorship. “René Cassin and the Daughter of Time: The First Draft of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights, in Fontanus 2 (1989). For a fuller discussion of the drafting process for the UDHR article on marriage and family see Daniel Cere, “Human Rights and the Family,” Academic Questions 2009 78 The text of the third draft. The final draft that was circulated to the members of the committee can be found in Glendon, A World Made New 79 Cassin’s edit of Humphrey’s draft eliminated the reference “of the state” perceiving it to be largely redundant. “The Cassin Draft, Glendon, A World Made New, p.277. 16 Cere in part, on the principle that marriage is “an institution created by the state.”80 Other decisions favouring a redefinition of marriage have avoided such blunt statements, but the principle seems to implicitly anchor their arguments. This emphasis on the legal or political texture of marriage is a highly influential, though controversial, conception of conjugal society. This strong version of the legal constitution of marriage is reflected in the original draft of the UDHR and continues to have life in some recent human rights instruments. The European Union’s Charter of Fundamental Rights (2000) adopted a variation of Humphrey’s formulation when it affirms that “the right to marry and the right to found a family shall be guaranteed in accordance with the national laws governing the exercise of these rights.”81 The UDHR took a different direction. A significant amount of Humphrey’s preliminary draft on human rights did survive the heated article-by-article debate that took place over the 18 months of informal meetings and formal commission sessions. However, his marriage article did not. The reasons for its defeat are instructive. In the Second Session of the Commission (Dec. 1947) Charles Malik of Lebanon proposed new wording that eliminated any reference to the role of state law and defined the family as “a natural and fundamental group unit of society.” Malik argued that rights language on marriage and the family should not be framed so as to imply that conjugal society is a creature of state law subject to “the caprice of men.” He argued that the “family circle” was the foundational social crucible in which “the fundamental human freedoms and rights were originally nurtured.”82 In his view, a full-throated affirmation of the “natural and fundament” character of the family was critical to establishing its autonomy in relationship to the state. Malik wanted to ensure that the strong version of legal constitution of marriage was firmly repudiated by the UDHR. Given the chronology of the drafting process, it seems clear that Malik’s wording was based on a proposal that had been submitted by the International Federation of Christian Trade Unions. On December 3, 1947 Petrus Serrarens submitted a memorandum suggesting the following formulation: The family is the natural, primary and fundamental unit of society; it is older than society itself and has unalienable rights antecedent and superior to positive law. The family therefore must be protected by society and have its free development and its security of life ensured.” Serrarens insistence on the need to build a wall of protection around the family tapped into widely shared anxieties about the extensive violations of family rights by modern totalitarian states. Malik revised the proposal and submitted it for discussion the following week. The Soviet Union did raise objections to Malik’s version of the IFCTU proposal, arguing that there was no universal or natural form of the family. However, the substantive concerns of the 80 Goodridge v. Dept of Public Health, Massachusetts Supreme Court, Nov.18, 2003. Charter of Fundamental Rights of the European Union, art.9. http://www.europarl.europa.eu/charter/pdf/text_en.pdf 82 Quoted from Morsink, The Universal Declaration of Human Rights, pp.255. 81 17 Cere proposal eventually worked their way into the Universal Declaration.83 By the end of the prolonged debates on the declaration, the commissioners settled on the following formulation of the right “to marry and found a family”: (1) Men and women of full age, without any limitation due to race, nationality or religion, have the right to marry and to found a family. They are entitled to equal rights as to marriage, during marriage and at its dissolution. (2) Marriage shall be entered into only with the free and full consent of the intending spouses. (3) The family is the natural and fundamental group unit of society and is entitled to protection by society and the State. In the course of the committee debates, all references to “nature” were weeded out of the UDHR document, except for one. The most dramatic casualty was the deletion of the reference to “nature” in article 1 which affirmed that all persons are “endowed by nature with reason and conscience” (emphasis added).84 By Dec.10th 1948, the date of ratification, the only reference to nature left standing in the Universal Declaration was the affirmation of the “natural and fundamental” character of the family. The final formulation represented a fundamental philosophical shift away from the concept of marriage and human rights advanced in the original Humphrey draft. First, art.16 defines the right to marry as a “compound right”--“the right to marry and to found a family”—underscoring the connection between marriage and its procreative potential.85 Second, the contractual language of marriage is dropped leaving it open to the diverse cultural and religious accounts of the core symbolic significance of the institution (e.g. contract, covenant, sacrament, etc.). Third, the portrayal of marriage as a function of state law is repudiated. The conjugal family is a prelegal institution, a “natural and fundamental” form of social life. Fourth, the validity of marriage is grounded in the “free consent” of the couple, not in ratification by state law. Fifth, the article replaces “everyone” with “men and women.” It situates the article in the context of the sex duality of human life while insisting on the basic equality of the sexes in the conjugal bond.86 Finally, the state and society are obligated to protect and promote this natural institution. This UDHR rights discourse on marriage and the family continued to strongly shape the evolving international human rights conversation.87 Jane Adolphe notes that UDHR language in art. 16 has been affirmed and expanded in a number of major United Nations rights documents including the International Covenant on Economic Social and Cultural Rights (1966) and the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (1966). The International Covenant on 83 Discussions of the debates can be found in Morsink, The Universal Declaration of Human Rights, pp.254-258 and Don Browning, “The Meaning of the Family in the Universal Declaration of Human Rights,” in The Family in the New Millennium, vol. 1, edited by A.Scott Loveless and Thomas B. Holman, Westport Conn. & London: Praeger, 2007, pp.38-53. 84 See Morsink’s discussion in “A Bargain about God and Nature” The Universal Declaration of Human Rights, pp.284-290. 85 On “compound right” see Margaret Somerville, “Children’s Human Rights and Unlinking Child-Parent Biological Bonds,” Journal of Family Studies, 13/2 ( 2007) 179. 86 The reference to “men and women” only appears twice in the UDHR: art.16 and the passage in the preamble affirming “the dignity and worth of the human person and in the equal rights of men and women.” 87 See Jane Adolphe, “Securing a Future for Children: The International Custom of Protecting the Natural Family,” The Family in the New Millennium: World Voices Supporting the Natural ‘Clan.’ vol.1, edited by A. Scott Loveless and Thomas B. Holman, Westport Conn. & London: Praeger, 2007, pp.191-224; esp. pp.206-211. 18 Cere Economic, Social and Cultural Rights strengths the language of entitlement by stating that the family must be accorded “the widest possible protection and assistance” (art.10). The “natural” family discourse also appears in major international rights declarations such as the American Convention on Human Rights, the African Charter on Human and Peoples’ Rights, the African Charter on the Rights and Welfare of the Child, as well as various Islamic declarations of human rights and freedoms. In short, it commands a fairly significant level of international support. The UDHR debates expose a classic tension in liberal discourse on marriage. Is marriage essentially a legal construct designed to facilitate certain human aspirations such as sexuality, intimacy, and the right to children? Or is marriage a “natural” institution entitled to protection by the state, but not constituted by state law? While contemporary liberal theory seems to be swinging strongly to the former view, the UDHR reaffirmed a tradition of liberal theory shaped by naturalist conceptions of conjugal society. By advancing this conception of marriage, the UDHR was able to secure a broad international consensus while simultaneously advancing a fairly hawkish stance on gender equality in the face of serious reservations from cultural and religious communities invested in more patriarchal conceptions of familial life. The drafters of the UDHR were convinced that there was no conflict between a strong affirmation of the “natural” basis of the family and a strong affirmation of gender equality. And they spelled this out in their final formulation of Article 16. 3.2. Nature, Rights and Marriage: The Liberal Tradition The “naturalizing” language of article 16 is likely to be something of an embarrassment for many contemporary human rights advocates in the West. This embarrassment signals that there has been a considerable shift away from traditions of liberal discourse that provided an intelligible framework for this concept. Divergent views of the significance of appeals to the “natural” dimensions of marriage and family do run deep in the liberal tradition. However, given the strong de-naturalizing drift of contemporary liberal theory, there is a tendency to overlook the foundational role of the discourse on the “natural” in the development of liberal discourse on the family. Charles Taylor argues one underrated element in the emergence of the modern self is the emphasis on “the affirmation of ordinary life.”88 The emerging modern social imaginary began to valorize the ordinary aspects of human life—conjugal life, family, work—as central to its concept of the “good life.” This represented a significant departure from classicist conceptions which devalued ordinary life as mundane life-sustaining activities that we share with other animals --- something to be downloaded or delegated to the lower orders of social life in order to free those capable of pursuing the higher goods. The emerging modern conception of nature affirmed the common pursuits of ordinary life as goods in themselves. The shift involved an 88 Charles Taylor, Sources of the Self: The Making of Modern Identity, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989, pp.211. 19 Cere attack on the elitism of pursuits that only the leisured few could meaningfully participate in.89 The “nature endorsing” traditions of modernity, Taylor argues, trace their roots to this affirmation of the good of “ordinary life.” 90 The affirmation of ordinary life worked its way into modern legal and political theory. The foundations of early modern liberal theory can be traced to the evolving natural jurisprudence traditions of 16th and 17th century Spanish and Dutch political thought.91 John Witte’s recent study, The Reformation of Rights, highlights the work of Johannes Althusius in revising and transmitting natural jurisprudence theory to 17th century political and constitutional discourse.92 Althusius’s distinctive contribution was his pluralistic and confederal conception of human society. While contemporary communitarian theory tend collapse marriage and family into the more generic category of civil society associations, Althusius draws a fairly sharp distinction between these two spheres of social life. In contrast to other consociational (consociato) forms, the family taps into the “natural symbiotic” basis of associational life; its social contours have “the same boundaries as life itself.”93 Anchored in nature these “conjugal and kinship” forms of life are the “seedbed of all private and public associational life.”94 Althusius clearly differentiates conjugal society from civil society. The endless variety of civil society associations are diverse, ever-changing, voluntary, and “transitory.” However “necessary and useful” they may appear to be within any historical context, they can always be “discontinued” and “disbanded” either by mutual agreement or the vicissitudes of time.95 Althusius cites four distinct spheres of autonomy that co-exist with the state: personal, conjugal societies, civil society associations, and religious communities. Each sphere has its own distinct character. Each sphere becomes a distinct site for rights talk. Each sphere can constitute potential site of resistance to the coercive power of the state. This approach implies that rights documents need to address each of these spheres as separate lines of rights discourse resisting temptations to collapse marriage, family or religion into more generic categories such as civil society, personal autonomy or conscience. In many ways, the fairly thick body of rights delineated by the UDHR appears to offer an approach to human rights and freedoms that reflects this Althusian pluralist conception of the diverse personal, familial, social, and religious foundations of human life. Furthermore, for the drafters of the UDHR, as for Althusius, the distinct place of the family in the rights tradition is 89 Taylor 1989, pp.213-14. Taylor, Sources of the Self, pp.211-233. 91 See Quentin Skinner’s survey of this evolving tradition in Foundations of Modern Political Thought 2 vols. 92 John Witte, “Natural Rights, Popular Sovereignty, and Covenant Politics: Johannes Althusius and the Dutch Revolt and Republic,” in The Reformation of Rights: Law, Religion and Human Rights in Early Modern Calvinism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007, pp. 143-207. Also Thomas O. Hueglin, Early Modern Concepts for a Late Modern World: Althusius on Community and Federalism, Waterloo Ont.: Laurier University Press, 1999. 93 Johannes Althusius, Politica: Politics Methodically Set Forth and Illustrated with Sacred and Profane Examples, edited and translated by Frederick S. Carney, Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, 1995, pp. 28. See Thomas O. Hueglin, Early Modern Concepts for a Late Modern World: Althusius on Community and Federalism. pp.76,116. 94 Althusius, Politica, pp.31 95 Althusius, Politica, pp.33. 90 20 Cere firmly anchored in conjugal society’s unique grounding in the “natural” ecology of human life. It cannot be subsumed under the category of “civil society.” The well-trod narrative of British liberalism follows a trajectory from Hobbes, through Locke to Mill. Despite the authoritarian bent of his political philosophy, Thomas Hobbes is widely recognized for the foundational role he played in the liberal tradition due to his contribution to the development of the modern concept of “natural rights.” Like Althusius, Hobbes sees the domain of the conjugal as central part of the natural order of human life. He ranks “conjugal affection” as second only to “self-preservation” – ranking it before “property” as a foundational interest of human nature, a significant concession for this hard-nosed materialist.96 Conjugal affection, Hobbes argues, is not a function of humanly devised “laws of matrimony,” but is anchored in “the Law of Nature.” Put simply, it is “the naturall inclination of the Sexes, one to another, and to their children.”97 Hobbes concludes that the basic order of natural rights consists in the triad of life, conjugal society, and property, rather than the more conventional account liberal rights to life, liberty and property. John Locke’s famous Two Treatises on Government begins with a lengthy response to Robert Filmer’s rendering of the political nature of familial life. Filmer repudiates Aristotle’s distinction of the polis and the household and argues that family is a thoroughly political form of life.98 According to Filmer, “If we compare the natural duties of a father with those of a king, we find them to be all one, without any difference at all but only in the latitude or extent of them.”99 Locke’s Two Treatises on Government, takes direct aim at Filmer’s attempt to fuse the political and the conjugal. Locke argues that “conjugal society” is a pre-political institution vital to human life because of the vital role it plays in generating and nurturing children. The familial and the political are fundamentally “different Relations” that operate according to different rules and values.100 Conjugal society “contains nothing of the Magistrates Power in it, nor is subjected to it.” 101 “The society betwixt parents and children, and the distinct rights and powers belonging respectively to them,” are, according to Locke, “far different from a politic society.”102 These two institutional realities are “perfectly distinct and separate; are built upon…different Foundations, and given to …different Ends.”103 “Conjugal society,” Locke 96 Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, edited by C. B. MacPherson, Hammondsworth: Penguin, 1981, pp.383. Hobbes states that “those that are dearest to man are his own life; and in the next degree (in most men), those that concern conjugal affection; and after them riches and means of living.”) See John Rawls’ discussion of Hobbes’s views in “Human Nature and the State of Nature,” Lectures on the History of Political Philosophy. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2007, pp.45. 97 Hobbes, Leviathan, pp.253. Hobbes has a mixed record on the question of patriarchalism. He envisages a form of matriarchy in the state of nature arguing that, in the absence of law or matrimonial contract, the natural dominion over offspring devolves to the mother. (Leviathan, pp.254) 98 Gordon J. Schochet, Patriarchalism in Political Thought, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1975, p.32. 99 Sir Robert Filmer, Patriarchia and Other Writings. Edited by Johann Somerville, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991, p. 12. 100 John Locke, Two Treatises of Government, edited by Peter Laslett. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988, II, sect.2, p.268. 101 John Locke, Two Treatises of Government, edited by Peter Laslett. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988, I, sect. 64, p.187 102 John Locke, Two Treatises of Government, edited by Peter Laslett. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988, II, sect. 84, p.322. 103 John Locke, Two Treatises of Government, edited by Peter Laslett. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988, II, sect. 71, p. 314. 21 Cere writes, “is made by a voluntary compact between man and woman; and tho’ it consist chiefly in such a communion and right in one another’s bodies as is necessary to its chief end, procreation; yet it draws with it mutual support and assistance, and a communion of interests too, as necessary not only to unite their care and affection, but also necessary to their common offspring, who have a right to be nourished, and maintained by them…”104 For Locke, the foundations of conjugal society lie in the natural socio-sexual ecology of human life: sex difference, the natural generativity of male/female bonds, and parental investment in their children. Locke does begin to press for a modestly egalitarian understanding of conjugal relations.105 Locke’s debate with Filmer’s Patriarchia in the first treatise is built around an argument for the distinctly non-political and natural character of the conjugal bond. At a number of key points in his argument Locke counters Filmer’s emphasis on conjugal authority and subjugation by advancing a more egalitarian reading of biblical texts dealing with the nature of the conjugal bond. Locke’s manoeuvres suggest that liberalism can envisage an affirmation of the “natural” character of conjugal society together with an emphasis on the egalitarian nature of companionate conjugal relations. In the evolution of the British liberal tradition, Mary Wollstonecraft’s Vindication of the Rights of Women marked a decisive turn towards a more unequivocal affirmation of gender equality. Wollstonecraft launched a powerful critique of the patriarchalism embedded in Rousseau’s romantic vision of the family and gender relations. Rousseau’s republican political vision defended the critical place of conjugal society in human life, however his defence was based on a heavily genderized conception of social roles that effectively confined women to the domestic sphere as exotic flowers for romantic passions of his manly citizens. However, Wollstonecraft’s demand that liberalism embrace conjugal equality was not based on a repudiation of the natural and foundational importance of marriage and family for human society.106 According to Wollstonecraft, the structures of male authority and tyranny were complex human constructions that actually distorted and damaged the natural conjugal and parental affections in the home. Cleansing the home of the oppressive clutter of patriarchal conventions and constructions would restore conjugal relations to their pristine natural beauty. In this view, the egalitarian family is not the politicized family, but the natural family freed from the oppressive political overlay of human conventions. De Tocqueville’s exploration of democracy in America develops this line of reflection by putting sociological flesh on the theoretical bones of Wollstonecraft’s argument for the egalitarian and natural contours of the family. Democracy in America provides a strong communitarian defence of the family and civil society as platoons of freedom in liberal democracy. However, 104 John Locke, Two Treatises of Government, edited by Peter Laslett. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988, II, sect.78, p.319. 105 Here I am siding with Jeremy Waldron’s qualified defence of Locke against Carole Pateman’s charge that Locke was a consistent and uncompromising patriarchalist. See Carole Pateman, The Sexual Contract, Stanford, Cal.: Stanford University Press, 1988 and Jeremy Waldron, God, Locke and Equality: Christian Foundations in Locke’s Political Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002, pp.35-40. 106 See Eileen Hunt Botting’s discussion of the important areas of common ground in the debates between Rousseau, Burke and Wollstonecraft in Family Feuds: Wollstonecraft, Burke and Rousseau on the Transformation of the Family. Albany: State University of New York Press, 2006, esp. Ch. 5. 22 Cere Tocqueville’s account also celebrates the warmth and natural affectivity of family life in America in contrast to the convoluted complexities and competitiveness of relationships in the aristocratic familial cultures of Europe. The “naturalness” of familial bonds in America, Tocqueville observes, is due to the egalitarian nature of those relationships. Freedom and equality foster “familiarity and affection,” and “new relations [spring] up in the bosom of the family.” “Democracy,” Tocqueville writes, “loosens social ties, but it draws the ties of nature more tight; it brings kindred more closely together.”107 Tocqueville argues that the social radiance of the “natural” family shines forth in the more egalitarian conjugal culture fostered by the America democratic ethos. Arguably John Stuart Mill represents a decisive shift in the evolving liberal discourse on the nature of conjugal society. Mill was not impressed with DeTocqueville’s reflections on the family and dismissed them as lacking ‘‘any considerable value.’108 Mill did continue and sharpen arguments for the full equality of women. However, the liberal insistence on the “natural and fundamental” role of the family in social life begins to fade from view. First, Mill suggests that there may costs incurred for the real advancement of women’s equality, and those costs may have to be born by the family in terms of more divorce, more family instability and a decisive relativization of the interests of conjugal society. “The question”, Mill writes, “is not what marriage ought to be, but a far wider question, what woman ought to be.”109 In this view, equality claims must trump concerns about the inherent or ‘natural’ nature of marriage. Actualizing individual choice and autonomy requires “the most unbounded freedom in uniting and separating.”110 Social and political reforms advancing women’s equality will be required to target the family and gradually resituate it so that it will not present an obstacle to women’s needs and aspirations. Mill recognizes that the promotion of equality rights will inevitably erode and destabilize traditional family forms.111 However, he is convinced that this price must be paid.112 Second, Mill views the institution of marriage and family with deep suspicion. Conjugal society will be adversely affected by the promotion of equality rights because its institutional purpose, like that of slavery, is one of oppression and domination. In The Subjection of Women Mill paints a profoundly dark portrait of oppressive nature of marriage and family. Marriage institutionalizes the subjection of women. Marriage cuts deeper than slavery since it imposes a form of forced prostitution.113 The woman in marriage is reduced to “being the personal bodyservant of a despot” who can demand sexual access at any time. (335) “The family,” Locke 107 Alexis De Tocqueville, Democracy in America, vol.2, New York: Schoken Books, 1961, pp. 233, 236. John Stuart Mill, ‘‘M. de Tocqueville on Democracy in America,’’ Dissertations and Discussions: Political, Philosophical and Historical (New York: Henry Holt and Company, 1874), 124. 109 J.S.Mill, “On Marriage” (1832-33?) in The Subjection of Women in Sexual Equality: Writings by John Stuart Mill, Harriet Taylor Mill and Helen Taylor, edited by Ann Robson and John Robson, Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1994, pp.9. 110 J.S. Mill, “On Marriage” pp.5. 111 A similar form of sober rights realism can be found in Michael Ignatieff’s discussion of the family and human rights in The Rights Revolution, Toronto: Anansi, ch.4. 112 A similar argue is made by Michael Ignatieff in his Massey lecture, “Rights, Intimacy, and the Family,” The Rights Revolution, Toronto: Anansi, 2000, pp. 85-112. Thought Ignatieff strikes a more sobering note: “We need to see our anguish and disarray about the family as a struggle to face up to the consequences of having got what we wanted. We wanted freedom and we should stop apologizing for it. We must simply pay its price.” (pp. 112) 113 J.S. Mill, “On Marriage, pp. 9. 108 23 Cere argues, “is a school of despotism.” (346) It is a legalized form of “bondage” the directly controls and constrains the lives of a huge sector of the population: “There remain no legal slaves, except the mistress of every house.” (380) Finally, Mill launches a sharp attack on appeals to “nature” or the “natural” in advancing arguments about social and political order. In his essay On Nature, Mill rejected the Romantic endorsement of nature as a normative ground for human life. Mill anticipates postmodern critics of the concept of the “natural.” The appeals to nature are typically emotive and ideological: “Nature, natural, and the group of words derived from them, or allied to them in etymology, have...become entangled in so many foreign associations, mostly of a very powerful and tenacious character, that they have come to excite, and to be the symbols of, feelings which their original meaning will by no means justify; and which have made them one of the most copious sources of false taste, false philosophy, false morality, and even bad law.” (emphasis added) According to Mill, the concept of “following nature” is empty and devoid of meaning. All human action is transformative. Let us then consider whether we can attach any meaning to the supposed practical maxim of following Nature, in this second sense of the word, in which Nature stands for that which takes place without human intervention. In Nature as thus understood, is the spontaneous course of things when left to themselves, the rule to be followed in endeavouring to adapt things to our use? But it is evident at once that the maxim, taken in this sense, is not merely, as it is in the other sense, superfluous and unmeaning, but palpably absurd and self-contradictory. For while human action cannot help conforming to Nature in the one meaning of the term, the very aim and object of action is to alter and improve Nature in the other meaning. In short, Mill’s “comprehensive liberalism” decisively breaks ranks with the “political liberalism” of theorists like Locke, Wollstonecraft and Tocqueville on the marriage question. One of the most distinctive characteristics of this form of comprehensive liberalism is its determination to press for a gradual but thoroughgoing transformation of the institution of the family. The family for Mill is, most decisively not a “natural and fundamental” form of social life “entitled to protection by state and society.” It is a flawed legal construct that requires ongoing radical reform to meet evolving demands for equality and liberty. More recently, Martha Nussbaum has thrown her intellectual power behind the “Millean liberal” trajectory lamenting that “most of the liberal tradition did not follow Mill’s lead” on critical issues concerning sexuality, marriage and the family.114 Nussbaum takes up the torch from Susan Okin in her mission to nudge Rawlsian political liberalism into a more thoroughly liberal stance on the family.115 In her discussion, The Family: “not ‘by nature’,” Nussbaum leans heavily on Mill to argue against political approaches to the family, “both liberal and nonliberal,” that attempt to posit a “natural” grounding for the family.116 Like Humphrey and Goodridge, Nusshaum argue that the family is a “creation of state action” in a more “direct sense” than other 114 Martha C. Nussbaum, Sex and Social Justice, New York, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999, pp. 20-25, 65. See Susan Moeller Okin, Justice, Gender and the Family, 116 Martha C. Nussbaum, Women and Development: The Capabilities Approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000, pp.252-261. 115 24 Cere civil society institutions of society such as universities or religions.”117 “The state,” Nussbaum argues, “constitutes the family structure through its laws, defining which groups of people can count as families, defining the privileges and rights of family members, defining what marriage and divorce are, what legitimacy and parental responsibility are, and so forth.”118 The state does not simply “police” marriages, “it marries people”: [T]he state is present in the family from the start... it is the state that says what this thing is and controls how one becomes a member of it.”119 Nussbaum notes that there are soft and strong versions of the legal character of associations. In the soft version the law contextualizes institutions, in the strong version the law constitutes them. Nussbaum is arguing for the strong version of the legal constitution of marriage: All human associations are shaped by laws and institutions, which either favour or disfavour them, and which structure them in various ways. But the family is shaped by law in a yet deeper and more thoroughgoing way, in the sense that its very definition is legal and political.120 The curious feature of Nussbaum’s nature-dismissing discourse on the family is that it is set within the context of a complex and evolving intellectual project that offers rich resources for nature-endorsing ethical approaches. Her philosophical ethics develops traditions of Aristotelianism and neo-Stoicism noted for their non-dualist appreciation of the complex webs of interaction between nature and culture, nomos and physis, body and consciousness.121 Frontiers of Justice, for example, challenges contemporary liberalism to a new conversation on questions of human vulnerability, embodiment, aging, childhood, and disability. However, when Nussbaum turns to questions of the family, sexuality, sexual difference, or procreativity the arc of her thought seems to be channelled along a thoroughly predictable Millean lines. Conclusion Those attracted to nature endorsing conceptions of marriage, like most ecologically-minded folk, tend to be concerned about threats to the vulnerable dimensions of social sexual ecology of human life. The domains of marriage and family do raise fundamental rights concerns, but they are situated in the context of equally weighty concerns for nature, embodiment, and vulnerability.122 The international commission drafting the UDHR was attentive to these interconnections as it wove together language about ‘rights,’ the ‘natural,’ ‘protection,’ ‘motherhood and childhood’ (arts.16 & 23).123 The duty to ‘protect’ this unique web of natural bonds and rights loomed large in their final formulation of UDHR. 117 Martha C. Nussbaum, Women and Development: The Capabilities Approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000, pp.260-62. “The family is a social and legal construct in a much more fundamental and thoroughgoing way than these other organizations.” ibid. pp.275. 118 Nussbaum, Women and Human Development, pp.262-63. 119 Nussbaum, Women and Human Development, pp.263. 120 Nussbaum, Women and Human Development. pp. 262-63. 121 For a more recent statement of Nussbaum’s identification with the neo-Stoic tradition see, Martha Nussbaum, Frontiers of Justice. 122 Turner’s work on rights and vulnerability tries to ground a discussion of human rights in the embodied vulnerable nature of human existence, see Bryan S. Turner, Vulnerability and Human Rights, University Park, Penn.: Pennsylvania University Press, 2006. Martha Nussbaum’s recent work of disability raises similar concerns, however she applies them to the disabled and animals, not to children in the context of family. Frontiers of Justice: Disability, Nationality and Species Membership. Belknap Press, 2007 123 “Motherhood and childhood are entitled to special care and assistance.” (Art. 25) 25 Cere Jonathan Rausch’s hopeful argument that the current rights revolution, anchored in a very different vision, would somehow protect and revitalize marriage culture is proving, at least in Canada, to be a somewhat shaky, if not empty, promise.124 After the heated debates around the definition of marriage, the public conversation on marriage is now essentially dead. The legal and political achievement of marriage equality seems to have been the major goal for most gays and lesbians. Now that equality has been achieved, their interest in, and aspiration to, marriage has been modest, at best. Marriage rates in Canada continue to stagnate or decline. In Quebec, extra-marital births have risen to 62% and climbing. Michael Ignatieff’s more sober account of real price to be paid for the evolving “rights revolution” in the family probably offers a more accurate assessment of the road ahead. Ignatieff follows Mill’s tough-minded approach to the tensions between marriage, family, and commitments to liberalism as comprehensive political stance. With the penetration of liberal values deep into the texture of family life, ongoing destabilization is to be expected and welcomed. According to Ignatieff, the rights revolution driving current reforms in marriage and law has no real commitment to marriage and family as integral or ‘natural’ forms of life apart from concerns for the fundamental equality claims of its participants.125 Alternative conceptions of rights and liberalism that do situate marriage and the family as “natural and fundamental” dimensions of human society are deeply shaped by equality concerns, but not constituted by them. Although I find myself in sympathy with lines of liberal reflection willing to continue, develop and enrich a conversation on the ‘natural’ dimensions of marriage and family, I have mixed sympathies for proposals to use the coercive power of the state to legally impose any particular doctrine of marriage. The repressive power of these doctrinal impositions can cut both ways. In the heat of the debates over marriage the charge of repression is typically levelled against the imposition of opposite-sex doctrines of marriage. However, in the wake of redefinition, a new legal and doctrinal orthodoxy rapidly settles into place and new heretics soon feel the repressive weight of its authority. Imposing a new doctrine of marriage throws citizens committed to the historic understanding of marriage under a legal and cultural cloud. The expansion of the category of homophobia to include heteronormative and “heterosexist” speech works to close conversation in both academic and public settings. Heternormative conceptions of marriage may be alluded to in sanctuaries under the veil of religious freedom, but they are increasingly banned from polite conversation in the public sphere.126 Margaret Somerville’s recent experience illustrates these trends. Somerville is an internationally acclaimed ethicist, winner of the first UNESCO prize in science and ethics and recipient of the “Order of Australia.” Her nature-endorsing approach to ethics won her acclaim in the late 80s 124 Jonathan Rausch, Gay Marriage: Why it is Good for Gays, Good for Straights, and Good for America, New York: Henry Holt and Company, 2004. 125 It’s a price Ignatieff is willing to pay – Michael Ignatieff, The Rights Revolution, pp.85-112. 126 In Canada social and self-censorship is often reinforced by the policing of public discourse by active use of human rights tribunals, case law or employment penalties. Since the passage of the new marriage law, human rights complaints filed against Bishop Fred Henry, Roman Catholic bishop of Calgary, and Fr. Alphonse de Valk, editor of Catholic Insight, a national Canadian Catholic magazine, for their views on marriage and homosexuality. In addition, some marriage commissioners who have conscientious objections to performing same-sex marriages have been forced to resign. 26 Cere and early 90s as she fought for responsible public health care response to the AIDs crisis. However, in Canada her argument for the natural contours of the family has made her the focus for a remarkable stream of public abuse including continuous hate mail, threats, university petitions condemning her work, and demands to have her tenured position terminated. Ryerson University’s decision to grant her an honorary doctorate provoked significant controversy requiring elaborate security measures to ensure her safety during the event. 127 Her recent nomination to the “Order of Canada” was dismissed by the nominating committee on the grounds that she was too controversial, yet during the same year the honor was awarded to Henry Morgenthaler, Canada’s most controversial pro-abortion advocate. Perhaps the most curious expression of this wave of public shaming was an article in the Ottawa Citizen bluntly titled, “Is Margaret Somerville a Bad Person?” In short, theoretical debates aside, the appeal to nature in family law is now provoking, in some circles, more visceral ethical disgust and abhorrence than the nature-loving antics of zoophiles. In the Bodies of Law, Allan Hyde argues that blows against ‘nature’ and ‘biology’ are blows struck on behalf of the freedom and authority of human law-making. Treating the body as a “legal artefact,” a malleable construction, an imaginary, rather than a foundational biological reality, is, Hyde argues, a “powerful blow” for “legal creativity.”128 I suppose it is. Legal orthodoxies, whether political or religious, have often proved to be powerful and creative blows against the varied restrictions of ‘nature’—material nature, biotic nature, human nature, or even so-called “natural” rights. The appeal to ‘nature’ can be restrictive, reactionary, and even repressive. However, the appeal to ‘nature’ can also prove to be a cautionary stance against human hubris and, at times, a liberating stance against oppressive human ‘constructions.’ Somerville offers some of her reflections on this event in “Incorrectly Labelled” MercatorNet, Feb. 24, 2009, http://www.mercatornet.com/articles/view/incorrectly_labelled/. 128 Alan Hyde, Bodies of Law, pp.262. 127