1 Non-rationalism in East Asian Philosophy: A Whiteheadian Evaluation Wang Shik Jang (Methodist Theological University) Introduction It has been pointed out that non-rationalism is one of the strong characteristics of East Asian philosophy. It is often said that even some arguments that seem to be ambiguous and irrational are sometimes easily accepted in East Asian philosophy. Interestingly enough, many people have insisted that such a characteristic has not so much weaknesses but rather strengths. Scholars such as David Hall, Roger Ames and Francois Jullien have argued in this way. They have said that not only is non-rationalism a salient characteristic of East Asian thoughts, it also has many merits in this post-modern world. Although I agree with their argument in a sense, I also want to claim that their arguments are based on an exaggerated one. facts. To my understanding, they quite often go beyond the Although non-rationalism is a strong philosophical phenomenon in East Asian thought, it is fair to say that such a phenomenon has been so much emphasized by some scholars as to stand out erroneously. The phenomenon has often been magnified one-sidedly especially to the eyes of the interpreters who are inclined to be favorable to the merits of post-modernism. In other words, my claim is that if the phenomenon were seen from a different point of view, we would end up with different consequences. This is also to imply that rationalism is also prominent in the tradition of East Asian thoughts. Another point to be mentioned in this small paper is that the over-emphasis on nonrationalism made by some scholars as representing East Asian thoughts does not always make the positive contribution to the advancement of East Asian civilization. To my understanding, the bright future of East Asian civilization lies rather in the equal emphasis on rationalism as well as non-rationalism. In what follows, I will try to hold that East Asian 2 philosophy can be more successful in developing Asian civilization only when rationalism can be kept in balance with non-rationalism. Furthermore, I will attempt to show how we can discover the fact that rationalism has been as significant as non-rationalism in some East Asian traditions of thoughts, even if it has shrunk as a main trait sometimes. Finally, my suggestion is that East Asian thoughts can get some valuable insights from Whitehead’s philosophy as they wish to find out an ideal type of collaboration between nonrationalism and rationalism. I will hold that such an equal emphasis on non-rationalism and rationalism made by Whitehead’s philosophy can be of great help in giving rise to an ideal type of civilization in this post-modern world. 1. The Position of Non-rationalism in East Asian Philosophy It is often pointed out that non-rationalism is the main characteristics of East Asian philosophy. David Hall and Roger Ames have been two of the most important proponents for this. They have insisted on this point especially in terms of aesthetics, which is regarded by them as the key to understanding the main traits of East Asian culture. 1 As we know, aesthetic philosophies, generally speaking, construe aesthetic experiences as the primary factor in perceiving an object. Here, to say that an aesthetic experience is the primary factor in perceiving an object is tantamount to saying that an intuition or an irrational factor plays a primary role in the process of knowing. As we are all aware of, aesthetics is the academic field that deals with the world of immediate feelings or emotional experiences. Immediate feelings or emotional experiences start with an intuition, which is, generally speaking, vague and unclear. Therefore, the feelings based on an intuition are relatively undifferentiated and uncertain. What the feelings really are is not to be clarified until they are identified by means of the concepts derived from our consciousness and reason. Hall and Ames’ claim that the main characteristics of East Asian thoughts lie in the philosophy of aesthetics is correct in this sense, because it is true to say that both Buddhist and Taoist thoughts, generally speaking, have preferred non-rationalism to rationalism in their philosophical reasoning, wherein the role of immediate feelings or emotional experiences based on intuitions have been emphasized. 1 See especially, David Hall and Roger Ames’ book, Thinking through Confucius, ch. 3. 3 Francois Jullien, a French scholar, argues for the similar point. For him, the reason why Chinese philosophy, representing East Asian thoughts particularly, has preferred nonrationalism to rationalism is that the thoughts based on wisdom have been prevalent in Chinese traditions. According to him, what has been favored in the tradition of East Asia is not so much philosophers but rather the wise, for whom a wisdom is more important than a truth. Jullien claims that the philosophical reason in which wisdoms are more important than truths in East Asia can be traced back to the tradition that has been affected by a kind of process thinking. 2 East Asian thoughts usually rely on the philosophy of process or becoming, in which the very nature of reality is change. As we know, since something that changes cannot be grasped by our intellectual power, thought in the form of reason and concepts cannot provide direct access to the nature of things. Therefore, the thinking based on seeking a truth is quite often replaced with the thinking based on seeking wisdoms. For only seeking wisdoms can guarantee the access to the nature of things, whereas seeking truth is futile in doing so. According to Jullien, process thoughts in East Asia make a thinker judge nothing even when he wishes to do make a judgment. This is because there is no concept that can be employed as the final criterion in our world where everything is in process and changing. In a word, any thinkers in the East couldn’t be fixated on a position, because they knew that every position is changing and in process. This had led to developing a wisdom tradition in East Asia. For Jullien, the meaning of wisdom is contrasted with that of “philosophy” connoted in the West. Here, what he means by the term “philosophy” in the West is generally the system of thought based on an exclusive truth in which only a correct truth is sought for. According to him, such a tendency to seek an exclusive truth has been constituted by the Western style of thinking by means of which other kinds of truths are so excluded as to form a stubborn philosophic community. In short, the western philosophic community favors a consistent system of thought in which an exclusive truth is pursued, the system that is called “philosophy.” By contrast, according to Julian, the Eastern attitude of seeking “wisdom” is not so much exclusive but rather collaborative. The community that prefers wisdom over truth has a tendency to appreciate the value of a truth in its relationship with others. It goes without saying that this community does not much care about setting up the tradition of an 2 Francois Jullien, Un Sage Est Sans Idee 171 4 exclusive truth or a consistent system of thought in which such an exclusive truth is emphasized. Some people may argue that if a philosophic community does not have a consistent system of thoughts, there will be only a slim chance to make a great advancement in civilization. This is because it is often assumed that a great advancement in civilization is more likely to take place in the context where there is a single-ordered society based on such a consistent system of thought. In other words, it is assumed here that a philosophic community based on a single-ordered society can easily be able to avoid a chaotic situation wherein there is merely little chance for making advancement in civilization. However, this hasn’t been the case in the East Asia. It is not true to say that the East Asia has had little chance to make a great advancement in their civilization. There is no doubt that it has created its own unique cultures and civilizations in the history of human beings. It may be fair to say that the East Asian philosophic communities have often preferred nonrationalism to rationalism in the sense that seeking an exclusive truth and setting up a single-ordered society are not favored by some school of East Asian thoughts Nevertheless, this also doesn’t mean to say that while non-rationalism has been principal in the East Asia, rationalism has never been so. No wonder that this was not the case either. Even Jullien also concedes that a strong type of causality theory has existed in ancient China, a rational theory which is quite similar to the Western type of theory that has played an important role in developing science and technology in the West. that rationalism is discovered in the East too. East that was seeking the exclusive truth. Therefore, it is fair to say There was even a philosophic tradition in the Jullien goes on to argue, however, that the only reason that rationalism based on a causality theory was not prevailing in the East was coincidental. Due to some contingent occasions, such rationalism based on the causality theory was regarded as secondary, having been marginalized and trivialized in the long run in the East. Therefore, Jullien holds that although East Asians were well aware of a truth seeking an objective appropriateness or a logical validity, they couldn’t have a holistic conceptual system by means of which multiple kinds of truth can be covered. 3 As we know, since a holistic conceptual system can provide an ideal tool by which the logical coherence of multiple positions and fields can be secured, philosophies cannot become fully rational until they finally construct such a system. 3 Francois Jullien, Un Sage Est Sans Idee 152. And, this system has been 5 called metaphysics in the history of Western philosophy. The rationality of theories can be secured only within a metaphysical system of thought in the sense that without such a system based on a logical coherence, all theories cannot be given the validity of its own position, and therefore, end up with colliding each other. In short, without a metaphysical system as a reliable buttress, theories have little choice but to be in conflict and incoherent. If we apply such a definition of metaphysic to our discussion, then it may be fair to hold that East Asian thoughts have not been equipped with a proper kind of rationalism. In fact, it is not easy to find out in the East Asia such philosophies based on a metaphysical system as that of Thomas Aquinas or Alfred N. Whitehead. Again, this is not to be interpreted as arguing that there has not been any kind of rationalism in the East. This is merely to imply that in some aspects it is not an exaggeration to say that the rationalism based on a more consistent and coherent type of metaphysics has not been strong enough in the East Asia. II. Reconciliation between Rationalism and Non-Rationalism in Whitehead’s Philosophy It is obvious that Whitehead’s philosophy is pretty much aesthetically oriented more than any other philosophy. We may be able to discover the aesthetic tendency in a variety of Whitehead’s texts. For instance, when Whitehead describes what an actual fact is really all about, he says: “…an actual fact is a fact of aesthetic experience. All aesthetic experience is feeling rising out of the realization of contrast under identity.” 4 When he gives an explanation about the characteristic of the moral order, he says: “All order is therefore aesthetic order, and the moral order is merely certain aspects of aesthetic order.”5 In this way, as we can see it, Whitehead’s philosophy is aesthetically oriented. Due to this, furthermore, Whitehead’s philosophy easily incorporates non-rationalism into its frame of thoughts. As we saw in the above, when an aesthetic experience in the process of perception is stressed, the role of intuition or emotion is to become significant. This is why non-rationalism has performed a significant role in Whitehead’s philosophy. In Whitehead’s philosophy, immediate feelings, or physical feelings starting with an intuition usually turn out to be vague and unclear. 4 5 A. N. Whitehead, Religion in the Making, 111. A. N. Whitehead, Religion in the Making, 101. 6 However, Whitehead’s philosophy never goes to the extremes. It never neglects the importance of the other side, i.e., rationalism. Indeed, Whitehead’s philosophy always attempts to keep the balance between rationalism and non-rationalism. Then, how is it possible for Whitehead’s philosophy to affirm those two irreconcilable positions when it is obviously an aesthetics-oriented philosophy? For Whitehead, this is made possible due to the doctrine of what he calls “symbolic reference.” In what follows, we will be able to see how Whitehead’s philosophy, based on Whitehead’s doctrine of symbolic reference, can emphasize the importance of both non-rationalism and rationalism simultaneously. According to Whitehead, when it comes to any perceptual process, three factors are to be involved. The first factor is physical feelings, which are the most primitive phase in the perceptual process. This is the feelings of the efficacy of the object which is, in Whitehead’s epistemology, called the past, since the perceiver involved in the present is expected to feel the object as the past one. Since, what is felt is delivered from the past as an efficacy to the present, such mode of feeling is called “causal efficacy.” As we already talked about in the above, this kind of feelings is usually vague and irrational in the sense that those feelings are not yet put in order and differentiated. This mode of feeling is so primary or primitive that any kind of perception cannot avoid this, since without this, the perception as such doesn’t get started. This is why Whitehead’s philosophy can be called an aesthetics-centered one in which intuition or emotion is a significant factor. This also shows how Whitehead’s philosophy puts much priority on non-rationalism. However, what is felt in that perception does not consist merely of the causal efficacy, which is the physical feeling derived from one’s past world. only when something else is added. That is to become complete For Whitehead, what is added to that perception is composed of conceptual feelings, which are able to complement the vague and emotional factors in that perception. Such conceptual feelings are constituted by the variety of mental abilities, among which consciousness is one of the most prominent cognitive tools. Our consciousness usually depends on sense perceptions. However, although what we have perceived through senses is, strictly speaking, presented to us as an immediate thing, it cannot be regarded as fundamental. To use Whitehead’s terminology, “presentational immediacy” is not foundational or primary, since it is given to us only after something physical is obtained. What is fundamental and primary is an aesthetic experience based on intuition or emotion. This is what makes Whitehead differ from the traditional understanding. Traditional philosophy has interpreted sensory perceptions fundamental. However, sensory 7 perceptions put an attention, in terms of Whitehead’s philosophy, only to the perceived things abstracted from sensation, and, therefore, they are confined merely to dealing with limited elements. Therefore, from Whitehead’s perspective, the perception in the mode of presentational immediacy is no more than one factor that can explain what is perceived. No wonder that the perception made by presentational immediacy is of great importance too in the process of human knowledge. cut without such mode of perception. For all the feelings are not differentiated and clear- This is exactly what Whitehead really wishes to claim: feelings cannot become complete until they are followed by a rational process supported by our conscious recognitions. However, the greatness of Whitehead doesn’t stop here. Whitehead goes on to hold that the more complete type of our perception needs one more factor, which is called the perception in the mode of “symbolic reference.”6 The reason for the doctrine of symbolic reference is that although our perception is consisted of two modes, i.e., causal efficacy and presentational immediacy, how the perception can be completely rationalized cannot be grasped until another mode should be added. As is well known, the function of the symbolic reference is to associate what is given through aesthetic feelings with conscious grasp of meaning. This is to say that although those vague feelings given through the causal efficacy can be clearly recognized by the presentational immediacy, they are not all that exist there. What is obtained by the mode of presentational immediacy is limited by many elements. It is sometimes limited by our frame of thought in our community. In a word, it is affected and distorted by the paradigm of a community. If we apply this principle to our cultural theories, then it can be said that since our cultures are constituted with the variety of concepts, words, and languages, they should be so compared and contrasted that their limitation can be manifested. Until we do understand such limitations that each culture faces and until we are equipped with a more universal type of symbols or categories that can overcome the limitation of various cultures and civilization, it would be difficult for human beings to possess an ideal type of civilization in the future. This is why it is necessary for us to need a philosophy in which a better type of rationalism can be introduced. Here, such a philosophy should be able to suggest a system of thought that compare and contrast the limitations of cultures, consequently bringing about a more complete type of rationalism. 6 See especially chapter 1 of A. N. Whitehead’s Symbolism: its Meaning and Effect . 8 It seems to me that what makes Whitehead differ from East Asian philosophy is this. When it comes to a more complete type of rationalism, Whitehead’s philosophy is more systematic than East Asian thoughts. And, sometimes, this makes Whitehead’s philosophy more rationalistic than East Asian’s. However, this does not necessarily mean that Whitehead’s philosophy looks more rational than East Asian one. No, that is not the case. It is obvious that since East Asian thoughts are also well aware of the fact that nonrationalism should be complemented by rationalism, they too have emphasized the importance of both rationalism and non-rationalism. However, many East Asian scholars have stressed, especially when they try to compare East Asian thoughts to Western’s, that one of the most salient traits of East Asian thoughts is its non-rationalism. They even argued that such a trait makes East Asian thoughts have much strength in this post-modern era. Of course, I agree with those scholars when they said that East Asian thoughts can have some strength in this post-modern world, because East Asian thoughts is an aestheticoriented philosophy and considers non-rationalism significant. However, I disagree with them when they argue that the salient characteristic of East Asian thoughts lies only in its nonrationalism and therefore do not have to care about the construction of a systematic philosophy based on rationalism and a consistent frame of thoughts. It seems to me that the reason why they insist that the importance of both rationalism and a consistent frame of thoughts are not emphasized in East Asian thoughts is not because that those characteristics are really lacking in East Asia. That is merely because they wish to interpret so and insist that way. I believe both Whitehead and East Asian thoughts are very much similar when they try to reconcile non-rationalism with rationalism, even though they are all aesthetically oriented. What makes them different is merely that Whitehead has endeavored to construct a systematic philosophy wherein both rationalism and non-rationalism can be well incorporated into a more consistent frame of thoughts, whereas East Asian thoughts has made a relatively weak attempt to construct such a systematic philosophy. However, this does not mean to say that East Asian thoughts never emphasized the importance of rationalism and a consistent and coherent frame of thoughts. My point is merely that East Asian thoughts can be contrasted with Whitehead’s thoughts when it comes to proposing an ideal model of metaphysics by means of which both rationalism and non-rationalism can be embraced into a more consistent system of thought. I believe such a system of thoughts can provide us with a better opportunity to make a great advancement in building up our civilization in this post modern era. I also believe that an East Asian aesthetic philosophy can become a better type 9 of systematic philosophy when it endeavors to provide a frame of thought into which both rationalism and non-rationalism can be incorporated at the same time.