A New Story of Civil Liberty in the United States 205 A New Story of Civil Liberty In the United States William Preston, Jr. David M. Rabban, Free Speech in Its Forgotten Years. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1997. I 1927 LEON WHIPPLE PUBLISHED THE STORY OF CIVIL LIBERTY IN THE UNITED States, the first attempt to describe the historical role of freedom from the American Revolution to 1920. In his foreword, Whipple wrote that “this book was born out of war and ignorance.” A generation that had just confronted wartime repression and a postwar Red Scare thought there was a tradition of liberty to which they could appeal. Whipple, instead, pointed out that there were as many precedents for intolerance as for liberty (Whipple, 1952: v). Even though the DaCapo Press reissued The Story of Civil Liberty in 1952 during the height of McCarthyism, its message has strangely failed to influence interpretations of the events before and after World War I. Neither has anyone attempted to write a similar full account of the role of rights throughout the nation’s history. With the appearance of David Rabban’s Free Speech in Its Forgotten Years, that deficiency has been addressed for the years 1870 to 1920 and a long lost history has been recovered. Rabban has discovered the previously unknown origins of free speech controversies, litigation, and judicial decisions, found new arenas of advocacy and legal philosophy dealing with First Amendment issues, revised our understanding of Progressivism and its attitudes toward free speech and dissent, and reinterpreted the dynamics that influenced the Supreme Court’s wartime decisions on free speech. All in all, this is a major contribution based on vast and meticulous research. Rabban’s aim is to trace the evolution of “rights consciousness,” basically a history of ideas about free speech and the First Amendment “in their diversity, complexity, and transformations” (p. 20). Two major traditions dominated this debate. On one side, the federal and mostly the state judiciary remained hostile to free speech, greatly restricting its expression due to the “bad and remote tendency” it might have to affect adversely public safety, health, morals, or convenience. In opposition was a mixed bag of “libertarian radicals” who “defended the primary value of individual autonomy against the power of church and state” and, N WILLIAM PRESTON, JR. (Box 1868, Vineyard Haven, MA 02568) is Professor Emeritus of History, John Jay College of Criminal Justice. He was a founding member of the Organization of American Historians’ committee on freedom of information. Social Justice Vol. 25, No. 2 205 206 PRESTON therefore, interpreted First Amendment rights in the most protective sense (p. 23). Organized in the National Defense Association (1878) and the Free Speech League (1902), they challenged the many censorship attacks of the infamous Comstock Law (1873) against supposed immoral speech and publications, supported the free speech of organized labor and numerous radicals, and opposed the use of libel, contempt, and injunction doctrines to criminalize speech. Meanwhile, a cadre of legal scholars independently began to formulate alternative interpretations of the First Amendment that would provide more protection to free speech claimants. Theodore Schroeder, Thomas Cooley, Ernst Freund, Henry Schofield, and Roscoe Pound condemned the “bad tendency” test even though their own social theories diverged on where the line between individual and social interests should be drawn. Had these legal philosophies not become part of the contemporary “rights conscious” climate, the succeeding debates of the Progressive era and the war would not have taken the direction they did. In Rabban’s view, the significance of the prewar decades lies in the contested terrain between the two extremes of judicial hostility and radical libertarian opposition. The former, of course, won hands down in case after case. Yet losers can become winners if their advocacy over time infiltrates the dominant paradigm under more favorable circumstances. Free speech proponents were an elite minority, yet their advocacy, litigation, publicity, and legal stature and connections did transform consciousness, as the Progressives were to prove. Civil liberties and excessive individualism were not top priorities on the Progressive political agenda, as Rabban points out in a brilliant chapter on their social thought. Although they attacked corporate malefactors’ systematized exploitation of workers and the unjust distribution of wealth, they regarded this predatory behavior as individualism running amok under the legal protection of the Fourteenth Amendment and liberty of contract. Their solutions proposed reform under a state whose beneficent powers would repair the damage and restore an equitable harmony of interests to the affected community, a sort of fairness doctrine for the general welfare. The “Best and the Brightest,” however, do not necessarily welcome other advocates in the pursuit of their ideals. In Rabban’s analysis of John Dewey and Herbert Croly as representative spokesmen, individualism from below can seem as dangerous as that from above. Their elitism seemed to announce “do it our way or else.” Listen to Rabban’s comment on Dewey: “He revealed substantial hostility to behavior that did not ultimately contribute to a harmonious community” and “advocated extensive social pressure on people whose values or characteristics did not benefit society” (p. 228). In his The Promise of American Life, Herbert Croly seemed equally apt in discovering philosophic versions of the bad tendency test. As Rabban notes, “Croly devoted substantial attention to the ways in which the American legal system, particularly the constitutional system of individual rights, obstructed the A New Story of Civil Liberty in the United States 207 development of a progressive democracy.” It would be best that “patriotic but inferior people” be led by “able and aggressive leaders” (p. 232–233). Both Dewey and Croly thus concluded that “the amount of liberty which can be left to the individual without endangering the social interest will vary at different times” (p. 242). California Progressives exemplified the potential for repression in such reasoning when confronted by the Industrial Workers of the World (IWW) organizing drives in the fruit, ranching, and farming industries of that state before the war (Preston, 1994: 55–61). Dazzled by their conviction that a progressive United States would have the power to reform the world by its entry into the war, Progressives had little sympathy for pacifists, conscientious objectors, and other radical dissenters. In its Espionage and Selective Service Acts decisions, the Supreme Court was not ready to abandon bad tendency either, and that included Justices Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr., and Louis D. Brandeis. Congress and the trial juries, of course, saw “verbal acts” as incitements to crime, and public apprehension confirmed the remotest possible impact of speech as intended to bring about the prohibited results. Only Learned Hand in his decision in the Masses case (declared nonmailable under the Espionage Act) resisted the tendencies doctrine and believed speech was legal unless it directly advocated incitement to crime, as distinguished from agitation, however intemperate. In traditional historiography, the climactic First Amendment scene now takes place, a revolution in constitutional interpretation of free speech. In 1919, in Justice Holmes’ dissent in the Abrams case, the “clear and present danger” doctrine is advanced as a major reversal of “bad tendency,” giving new substantive protection to speech thereafter. Rabban’s revisionism of that age-old myth, however, asserts “not exactly.” What, then, really did happen? By 1919 disillusionment and dismay had undermined the confidence of Progressives in a beneficent state serving the public interest. Wartime repression and postwar Red Scare hysteria, plus the failure of the Versailles Treaty to support Wilsonian ideals, converted many to the cause of defending individual rights from government attack. More important, Zechariah Chafee had published his famous “Freedom of Speech in Wartime” in the Harvard Law Review (June 1919), an article that used prewar legal theories of free speech while ignoring the entire historical context in which libertarian radicals had contested its judicial suppression. To make the moment even more dramatic, Chafee claimed that there had been no bad tendency cases between the Sedition Act of 1798 and World War I. Chafee’s real contribution represented a constitutional sleight of hand. Holmes had originally announced the clear and present danger test in upholding the conviction in Schenck, an obvious doctrinal commitment to bad tendency since it emphasized the proximity and degree of the words to the possible outcome. Chafee, however, saw the protective possibilities the phrase contained and 208 PRESTON described them in his law review article as well as in conversations with Holmes. The result is history, an account analyzed in lengthy and fascinating detail in Rabban’s final chapters. Although clear and present danger could still have restrictive implications, it opened up further First Amendment defense options. In the balancing act of judicial interpretation, free speech claims would now “weigh very heavily in the scale,” especially since bad tendency’s co-doctrines of indirect causation and constructive intent should not come into play (pp. 320–321). The born-again First Amendment Progressives who helped create “the modern civil liberties movement” (p. 299) changed constitutional interpretation and supported the American Civil Liberties Union as the watchdog of that success. Yet that elite and privileged group lacked the radical commitments of the earlier libertarians to an uncompromising all-out defense of First Amendment freedoms. Neither were they familiar with the heroic struggles that preceded World War I. Rabban seems to regret that loss and the good old days of Theodore Schroeder and The Free Speech League. W. Anthony Gengarelly’s recent Distinguished Dissenters and Opposition to the 1919–1920 Red Scare supports that point of view. His dissenters, described as a “libertarian check” opposing the ravages of government power, also exhibited a “deep-seated loyalty to the republican-capitalist system” and remained “wedded to property, order, and power.” The “libertarian check,” he concluded, “provides only limited control over a more pervasive problem” (Gengarelly, 1996: 350; 363; 366). II Rabban has expertly analyzed the intellectual and legal transformation of “rights consciousness” with a focus on one major campaign, the 21 IWW free speech fights between 1909 and 1913. However, what about the role and impact of other major groups of activists? Does that history not also contribute to our understanding of free speech and its relation to the First Amendment? Although Rabban describes the judicial hostility and the bad tendency doctrine, leaving the impression of continuous repression through legal process, perhaps there was another hidden history, with different dimensions of success and failure, in the years between 1870 and 1920. Perhaps the legal theorists ignored it. In the history of free speech, as Rabban himself acknowledges, legal theory, elite advocacy, and defense organizations are not the only significant players. There must also be vigorous, resilient, even heroic individuals and organizations willing to make a stand on behalf of their rights. Sometimes, but not always, their struggles will define the reality and substance of constitutional protections. Their confrontations with authority, however, may be resolved without either constitutional redress or doctrinal reform. The Populists and the immigrant Left, individually and as organizations, used and expanded the constitutional rights of free speech, free press, and free association. In doing so, they greatly extended civil liberties. Yet their tidal waves A New Story of Civil Liberty in the United States 209 of protest inevitably elicited challenges from the entrenched interests of the day, whose campaigns successfully terminated the further exercise of those rights. Lawrence Goodwyn’s Democratic Promise: The Populist Moment in America described the vast extent of that agrarian uprising. Forty thousand Alliance lecturers propagandized and recruited the faithful in a five-year campaign through 43 states and territories. At the same time, well over 1,000 Alliance newspapers with their own National Reform Press Association spread the party’s principles, attacking conservative economics and corporate intimidation. Populists also forged an interracial coalition. In terms of free speech, free press, equal rights, voting rights, and mass insurgency, it was unique. In opposition to the Populists, the mainstream press, the universities, and the churches corroborated the status quo by cultural propaganda. Race demagogy, corporate threats to workers, political fraud, terrorism against Populist lecturers and newspapers, and the impact of corporate money ended the 1896 agrarian drive for electoral success. Almost immediately, the whole Populist organization, including the free speech and newspaper network, disintegrated with a chilling effect on further activist agitation. The stilling of dissent had taken place outside the realm of the courts and legal theory. In The Immigrant Left in the United States, edited by Paul Buhle and Dan Georgakas, the authors rebut the stereotypes of ethnic mentalities as alien to the democratic and republican norms of the national tradition. Practicing “Americanism” on arrival, they took the First Amendment at face value, creating a large immigrant network of newspapers, journals, and lecturers with an immense assortment of associational activities as well. Their foreign language federations within the Socialist Party typified a responsible politics with an international flavor, while they fought to redress their grievances and bargain collectively as union members. Yet the stereotype of their separatism and un-Americanism held sway. Despite having internalized the values of their adopted country, the country demanded assimilation by way of its program of Americanization. The melting pot often meant coercive conversion to Anglo culture, with nativist violence and government deportation as backup threats. In the case of immigrants, their very diversity also seemed dangerous. As the Progressives insisted, community harmony required restrictions on the rights of individuals, whether aliens or not. The search was for homogeneity and cohesion. Both immigrants and radicals learned that rights often gave way to rites, speech itself would be judged by the behavior of the speaker, the tone of the speech, and the degree to which it was deemed constructive and socially beneficial. Other Americans whose lives were confined and coerced by company towns, Pinkerton detectives, blacklisting, anti-Tramp Acts punishing the crime of unemployment, agrarian peonage, segregation, lynching, and state and federal troops may have been conditioned to accept their status in society without speaking out in response or recognizing their First Amendment rights. 210 PRESTON Yet the years before World War I surely represent one of the great eras for a variety of profound and vigorous free speech movements. However restrictive the courts and the legal philosophy, First Amendment activists pursued their dreams only to find themselves marginalized and their dissent stamped out by opposition weapons that had nothing to do with litigation or the constitutional doctrines involving speech. One wonders whether that ongoing lurid history of repression sank into the consciousness of libertarian radicals and what they thought about it. Did they ponder the costs? Robert J. Goldstein in his Political Repression in Modern America: From 1870 to the Present has assessed the damage. By the end of the 1920s, official suppression had destroyed four radical union movements, isolated and disrupted two major radical political parties, and denied effective organizing power to the labor movement for some 60 years. III In Rabban’s last chapter, he recognizes parallels between today’s debates about the First Amendment and those of the Progressive Era. Once again critics (largely on the Left) charge that hate speech has attacked the well-being of minorities and that corporate speech has subverted the meaning of democratic politics. Both can undermine the harmony of the community, increase inequality among citizens and groups, and violate the goal of equal protection under the law. Campus speech codes have attempted to correct this phenomenon, but have been declared unconstitutional; the Supreme Court has upheld “the equal right of rich and poor to express themselves by spending money on political campaigns” (p. 387). Hate speech has, of course, been a perennial contender for restrictive regulation. The propaganda and disinformation during World War I was just the beginning. Nazi total radio took it to a totally new dimension as the weapons of choice against groups and nations it wished to attack or marginalize. By the end of World War II, the technology of hate and deception and the evil undercurrents of slander and defamation had contaminated relations among peoples and destroyed morale around the globe. In 1946, the Hutchins Commission on Freedom of the Press considered that the free market in all media arenas did not naturally prevent “large numbers [from being] deceived, injured, or degraded” and condemned the distortions of rancorous malignity or the degradation of culture (Preston, Herman, Schiller, 1989: 26–31; 52–53). At the same time, the concept of group libel surfaced to protect from malicious defamation any group, class, or race. In 1952 the Supreme Court upheld group libel in Beauharnais v. Illinois, but during litigation over the right of American Nazis to march in Skokie, Illinois, in 1977 and 1978, it seemed that Beauharnais no longer applied. Yet the world is out of step with the United States on this issue. According to Samuel Walker’s study, Hate Speech: The History of an American Controversy, almost every other country as well as several international human rights declarations “prohibit the expression of offensive racial, religious, or ethnic A New Story of Civil Liberty in the United States 211 propaganda” (Walker, 1994: 4–5). The ACLU and the NAACP, however, have opposed group libel legislation because they have realized that the principal strategy for advancing group rights came to be the expansion of constitutionally protected individual rights (Ibid.: 16). No battle for civil liberty necessarily stays won. Hence the ACLU’s call for eternal vigilance. In Rabban’s illuminating narrative there is talk of turning points and breakthroughs, of the transformation of a “rights consciousness,” of First Amendment advances. Yet I cannot resist the metaphor of the shell game and the location of the pea, or perhaps the smile on the face of the Cheshire Cat. This is not to deny constitutional progress, but to recognize the shifting sands on which it stands. Bad tendency is an example. Although exorcised from much judicial decisionmaking, it spread like a toxic tumor to other arenas to restrict speech. Intelligence agencies, legislative investigations, and loyalty-security hearings featured the bad tendencies of their suspects through doctrines of guilt by association and anticipatory criminality. In the surveillance of suspect subversives, even innermost thoughts were considered appropriate clues. Rabban admits that during the Cold War, the Supreme Court retreated to a restrictive interpretation of speech, discarding the protections “clear and present danger” were supposed to uphold. In the conspiracy indictments of Communists, speech twice removed from action became criminal. Have the American people become more ardent supporters of free speech? Rabban believes a First Amendment constituency developed. Yet often it seemed the pieties indicating its standing cloaked a desire to violate its meaning. During McCarthyism, polls suggested most individuals would not sign the Declaration of Independence. A perhaps apocryphal quote from Lyndon Johnson when antiVietnam War protests challenged his policies represents the majority attitude: “I believe in the right to dissent, but I do not believe it should be exercised.” Rabban has concluded that “substantial doubts can more generally be raised as to whether any constitutional standard, however protective its language, can safeguard speech in times of crisis” (p. 379). Senator Thomas J. Walsh of Montana had an answer to that after World War I. “It is only in such times that the guarantees of the Constitution as to personal rights are of any practical value,” he said. “In seasons of calm, no one thinks of denying them” (quoted in Preston, 1994: 275). REFERENCES Buhle, Paul and Don Georgakas 1996 The Immigrant Left in the United States. New York: State University of New York Press. Gengarelly, W. Anthony 1996 Distinguished Dissenters and Opposition to the 1919–1920 Red Scare. Lewiston, N.Y.: Mellen. 212 PRESTON Goldstein, Robert Justin 1978 Political Repression in Modern America: From 1870 to the Present. New York: Two Continents/Schenkman. Goodwyn, Lawrence 1976 Democratic Promise: The Populist Moment in America. New York: Oxford University Press. Preston, William, Jr. 1994 Aliens and Dissenters: Federal Suppression of Radicals, 1903–1933. Second Edition. Urbana: University of Illinois Press. Preston, William, Jr., Edward S. Herman, and Herbert I. Schiller 1989 Hope and Folly: The United States and UNESCO. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Walker, Samuel 1994 Hate Speech: The History of an American Controversy. Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press. Whipple, Leon 1952 The Story of Civil Liberty in the United States. New York: DaCapo Press.