rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/ztrint-09a angnes Sⴝ12 9/11/09 2:36 Art: Input-mn “A Gift for Life. Considerations on Organ Donation” Alessandro Nanni Costa INTRODUCTION he Pontifical Academy for Life, the Italian National Transplant Centre and the World Federation of Catholic Medical Associations organized an international Congress on organ donation entitled: “A Gift for life. Considerations on organ donation”, in Rome, November 6 to 8 2008, at the Auditorium della Conciliazione, near the Vatican City. The event had two purposes; on one side, it aimed at deepening the most crucial aspects of organ donation all around the world; on the other side, it was a unique, unprecedented occurrence to present the official position of the Church on this delicate topic. The Congress focused on the issue of organ donation presented by scientists, researchers and ethicists as well as Catholic Associations from all over the world. During the Congress, scientific, legal, ethical and organizational aspects of transplants and donation activity around the world was widely discussed. The first day of the Congress introduced the current transplant system on an international basis focusing specially on the historical evolution of both transplant sciences and organ donation. The crucial and alarming aspect of organ shortage, traffic and organ tourism was also deeply debated. The second day of the Congress was dedicated to ethical and anthropological aspects of organ donation and to all the issues related to the organ-donation-living will, organ allocation criteria and ethics of the transplant organization. Of particular interest were the training paths and pastoral initiatives promoting organ donation culture. During the second day of the event, Congress participants were received by the Holy Father Benedict XVI who presented the Church’s position in favor of organ donation and transplants, defining donation as an admirable act, not just morally licit, because it expresses a genuine testimony of charity. The Holy Father, moreover, underlined the need to respect all conditions that make organ donation T AQ: 1 The author declares no conflict of interest. Transplantation • Volume 88, Number 7S, October 15, 2009 and transplantation legal and to fight any kind of coercion or organ commercialization. Lastly, the Holy Father urged researchers and scientists to increase research to dispel people’s “prejudices and misunderstanding” and disperse their “mistrust and fear”, replacing them with certainty and guarantee. The final session of the Congress, dedicated to the role of mass media in promoting organ donation culture and in influencing people’s perception of it, outlined the need to build an alliance between the world of transplants and media to promote an ethical communication oriented to increasing the actual knowledge of this field among people through correct information and keeping them at a safe distance from a superficial and sensationalistic use of news. More than 500 people registered at the Congress were health and pastoral professionals, donors’ and patients’ associations, Directors of national transplant systems, journalists and patients. All Italian and various international media attended the meeting with the Holy Father Benedict XVI and published news from the Congress as well as the reflections the Holy Father expressed on the subject. Eight years after the international Congress on transplants in 2000, the Congress “A Gift for Life. Considerations on Organ Donation” represented an important occasion to build up a global awareness on organ donation and transplant. The success of the Congress in terms of people registered and media coverage was mainly due to the precious words of the Holy Father and the organizing contribution of the Pontifical Academy for Life and the World Federation of Catholic Medical Associations in generating ethical and cultural considerations on organ donation. The Congress was sponsored by the National Transplant Centre, FITOT, the Non Profit Foundation for the Advancement of Organ and Tissue Transplantation, created by the Veneto Regional Government, and Novartis Pharmaceutics. Transplants have been an integral part of the history of Novartis for 25 years and the group has made a major contribution towards progress in this area, to which it continues to dedicate its commitment to innovation. www.transplantjournal.com | S95 rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/popspeech-09a angnes Sⴝ14 9/10/09 23:41 Art: Input-mn A Message from the Holy Father Pope Benedict XVI ear Brothers in the Episcopate, distinguished Ladies and Gentlemen. Organ donation is a peculiar form of witness to charity. In a period like ours, often marked by various forms of selfishness, it is ever more urgent to understand how the logic of free giving is vital to a correct conception of life. Indeed, a responsibility of love and charity exists that commits one to make of their own life a gift to others, if one truly wishes to fulfil oneself. As the Lord Jesus has taught us, only whoever gives his own life can save it (cf. Lk 9:24). In greeting all those present, with particular thought for Senator Maurizio Sacconi, Minister of Labour, Health and Social Policies, I thank Archbishop Rino Fisichella, President of the Pontifical Academy for Life, for the words he has addressed to me illustrating the profound meaning of this meeting and presenting the synthesis of the Congress’ works. Together with him I also thank the President of the International Federation of Catholic Medical Associations and the Director of the Centro Nazionale Trapianti, underlining my appreciation of the value of the collaboration of these Organizations in an area like that of organ transplants which, distinguished Ladies and Gentlemen, has been the object of your days of study and debate. Medical history clearly shows the great progress that it has been possible to accomplish to ensure to each person who suffers an ever more worthy life. Tissue and organ transplants represent a great victory for medical science and are certainly a sign of hope for many patients who are experiencing grace and sometimes extreme clinical situations. If we broaden our gaze to the entire world it is easy to identify the many and complex cases in which, thanks to the technique of the transplantation of organs, many people have survived very critical phases and have been restored to the joy of life. This could never have happened if the committed doctors and qualified researchers had not been able to count on the generosity and altruism of those who have donated their organs. The problem of the availability of vital organs to transplant, unfortunately, is not theoretic, but dramatically practical; it is shown by the long waiting lists of many sick people whose sole possibility for survival is linked to the meagre offers that do not correspond to the objective need. It is helpful, above all in today’s context, to return to reflect on this scientific breakthrough, to prevent the multiple requests for transplants from subverting the ethical principles that are at its base. As I said in my first Encyclical, the body can never be considered a mere object (cf. Deus Caritas Est, n. 5); otherwise the logic of the market would gain the upper hand. The body of each person, together with the spirit that has been given to each one singly constitutes an inseparable unity in which the image of God himself is imprinted. Prescinding from this dimension leads to a perspective incapable of grasping the totality of the mystery present in each one. Therefore, it is necessary to put respect for the dignity of the person and the protection of his/her personal identity in the first place. D S96 | www.transplantjournal.com With regards to the practice of organ transplants, it means that someone can give only if he/she is not placing his/her own health and identity in serious danger, and only for a morally valid and proportional reason. The possibility of organ sales, as well as the adoption of discriminatory and utilitarian criteria, would greatly clash with the underlying meaning of the gift that would place it out of consideration, qualifying it as a morally illicit act. Transplant abuse and their trafficking, which often involves innocent people, like babies, must find the scientific and medical community ready to unite in rejecting such unacceptable practices. Therefore they are to be decisively condemned as abominable. The same ethical principle is to be repeated when one wishes to touch upon creation and destroy the human embryo destined for a therapeutic purpose. The simple idea of considering the embryo as “therapeutic material” contradicts the cultural, civil and ethical foundations upon which the dignity of the person rests. It often happens that organ transplantation techniques take place with a totally free act on the part of the parents of patients in which death has been certified. In these cases, informed consent is the condition, the subject to freedom, for the transplant to have the characteristic of a gift and is not to be interpreted as an act of coersion or exploitation. It is helpful to remember, however, that the individual vital organs cannot be extracted except ex cadavere, which, moreover, possesses its own dignity that must be respected. In these years science has accomplished further progress in certifying the death of the patient. It is good, therefore, that the results attained receive the consent of the entire scientific community in order to further research solutions that give certainty to all. In an area such as this, in fact, there cannot be the slightest suspicion of arbitration, and where certainty has not been attained the principle of precaution must prevail. This is why it is useful to promote research and interdisciplinary reflection to place public opinion before the most transparent truth on the anthropological, social, ethical and juridical implications of the practice of transplantation. However, in these cases the principal criteria of respect for the life of the donor must always prevail so that the extraction of organs be performed only in the case of his/her true death (cf. Compendium of the Catechism of the Catholic Church, n. 476). The act of love which is expressed with the gift of one’s vital organs remains a genuine testimony of charity that is able to look beyond death so that life always wins. The recipient of this gesture must be well aware of its value. He/she is the receiver of a gift that goes far beyond the therapeutic benefit. In fact, what he/she received, before being an organ, is a witness of love that must raise an equally generous response, so as to increase the culture of gift and gratuity. The right road to follow, until science is able to discover other new forms and more advanced therapies, must be the formation and the spreading of a culture of solidarity that is open to all and does not exclude anyone. A medical transplantation corresponds to an ethic of donation that demands on the part of the commitment to Transplantation • Volume 88, Number 7S, October 15, 2009 rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/popspeech-09a angnes Sⴝ14 9/10/09 23:41 Art: © 2009 Lippincott Williams & Wilkins invest every possible effort in formation and information and to make the conscience ever more sensitive to a issue that directly touches the lives of many people. Therefore, it will be necessary to reject prejudices and misunderstandings, widespread indifference and fear, and to substitute them with certainty and guarantees in order to per- Input-mn S97 mit an ever more heightened and diffused awareness of the great gift of life in everyone. With these sentiments, while I wish each one to continue in his/her own commitment with the due competence and professionality, I invoke the help of God on the Congress’ works and impart to all my warm Blessing. rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/progcong-09a panickes Sⴝ15 9/14/09 17:12 Art: S98 | www.transplantjournal.com Input-mn Transplantation • Volume 88, Number 7S, October 15, 2009 rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/progcong-09a panickes Sⴝ15 9/14/09 17:12 Art: © 2009 Lippincott Williams & Wilkins Input-mn S99 rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/progcong-09a panickes Sⴝ15 9/14/09 17:12 Art: S100 | www.transplantjournal.com Input-mn Transplantation • Volume 88, Number 7S, October 15, 2009 rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/progcong-09a panickes Sⴝ15 9/14/09 17:12 Art: © 2009 Lippincott Williams & Wilkins Input-mn S101 rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/progcong-09a panickes Sⴝ15 9/14/09 17:12 Art: S102 | www.transplantjournal.com Input-mn Transplantation • Volume 88, Number 7S, October 15, 2009 rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/progcong-09a panickes Sⴝ15 9/14/09 17:12 Art: © 2009 Lippincott Williams & Wilkins Input-mn S103 rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/progcong-09a panickes Sⴝ15 9/14/09 17:12 Art: S104 | www.transplantjournal.com Input-mn Transplantation • Volume 88, Number 7S, October 15, 2009 rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/progcong-09a panickes Sⴝ15 9/14/09 17:12 Art: © 2009 Lippincott Williams & Wilkins Input-mn S105 rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/progcong-09a panickes Sⴝ15 9/14/09 17:12 Art: S106 | www.transplantjournal.com Input-mn Transplantation • Volume 88, Number 7S, October 15, 2009 rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/photcong-09 angnes Sⴝ13 9/11/09 2:56 Art: Input-mn Congress Photographs Transplantation • Volume 88, Number 7S, October 15, 2009 www.transplantjournal.com | S107 rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/ztr2748-09a angnes Sⴝ46 9/11/09 4:42 Art: TP201180 Input-mn A Colloquium on the Congress “A Gift for Life. Considerations on Organ Donation” Alessandro Nanni Costa, J. M. Simón i Castellvì, Antonio G. Spagnolo, Nunziata Comoretto, Jean Laffitte, Håkan Gäbel, Francis L. Delmonico, Ferdinand Muehlbacher, Walter Schaupp, Alexandra K. Glazier, Valter D. Garcia, Mario Abbud-Filho, Jose O. Medina-Pestana, Mariangela Gritta Grainer, Pier Paolo Donadio, Anna Guermani, Riccardo Bosco, Francesco Giordano, Blanca Martinez Lopez de Arroyabe, Marco Brunetti, Martí Manyalich, Gloria Páez, Ricardo Valero, Rafael Matesanz, Elisabeth Coll, Beatriz Dominguez-Gil, Beatriz Mahillo, Eduardo Martin Escobar, Gregorio Garrido, and Felix Cantarovich Ethical Principles of Organ Donation MAIMONIDES BIOETHICAL CONSIDERATIONS J. M. Simón i Castellvì Antonio G. Spagnolo and Nunziata Comoretto nce upon a time, a man insulted a physician called Maimonides, and his Jewish religion, within the hearing of the king. The king ordered him to take out the heart of that bad man, but the doctor looked after that poor bad man, gave him food, cured him and even paid for his medicines. His heart though changed. O After some time, once again the king and the doctor met that man. Isn’t this he who insulted you and your religion? Yes, My Lord. Why didn’t you obey my order? I did obey you, My Lord! I have changed his wooden heart and I have given a human and peaceful heart! So, it is possible to operate without a knife, the king said! Rabbi Moshe Ben Maimon, also known as the RAMBAM, was born in the Spanish city of Córdoba in 1135. He was a rabbi, a physician and a philosopher. The medieval Arabic poet Al Said Ibu Sural al Mulk wrote about him: “Galen’s art healed only the body, but Abu Imram’s (Maimonides) the body and the soul”. Maimonides said that it is impossible for the truths arrived at by human intellect to contradict those revealed by God. Saint Thomas Aquinas held him in high esteem. A beautiful daily prayer of a physician is attributed to him. . . . Thou hast created the human body with infinite wisdom. Ten thousand times ten thousand organs hast Thou combined in it that act unceasingly and harmoniously to preserve in the envelope of the immortal soul. They are ever acting in perfect order, agreement and accord. Yet, when the frailty of matter of the unbridling of passions deranges this order or interrupts this accord, then forces clash and the body crumbles into the primal dust from which it came. . . . Almighty God! Thou hast chosen me in Thy mercy to watch over the life and death of Thy creatures. I now apply myself to my profession. Support me in this great task, so that it may benefit mankind! . . . Today, we can discover our errors of yesterday and tomorrow we can obtain a new light on what we think ourselves sure of today. S108 | www.transplantjournal.com n the past half-century, solid organ transplantation has become standard treatment for a variety of diseases, potentially restoring patients with terminal illness to normal life (1). The technique of successful transplant operations has given rise, for both individual and society, to several ethical questions. Some of them are common to those arising from the ethical implications of all developing techniques, such as the weighing of risks involved in early experimentation, the likelihood and degree of success in particular cases, the need for informed and free consent on the part of those involved and the justification of investment in terms of resources and personnel. However, there are some ethical questions peculiar to the concept of transplantation, that is, those related to the transference of organs from an individual to another (2). One of the first moral quandaries in transplantation, in fact, concerns whether it is right to remove a healthy organ from a healthy person (in violation of the Hippocratic aphorism “do not harm”), even if the aim is to save the life of another person. Another is whether or not individuals have the moral authority to mutilate their bodies (3). Currently, the major ethical problems in organ transplantation come out of the shortage of organs, as presently thousands of people are on waiting lists for transplants and their lives are dependent on the recruitment of organs (4). Moreover, the number of people needing transplants is expected to grow in the next decades, especially due to the aging of the baby boomer population and the increase of kidney disease due to hypertension and diabetes (5). The organ shortage has motivated a host of efforts to increase organ supply, some of which are controversial, such as the acceptance of expanded criteria for increasing cadaveric donors pool (for instance, older and sicker donors), donation after cardiac death (so-called nonheart-beating donation) and the increasing number of living organ donors (outside of the living related donation) (6). The purpose of this essay was to explore some of the ethical issues involved in transplantation and particularly I The authors declare no conflict of interest. Transplantation • Volume 88, Number 7S, October 15, 2009 rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/ztr2748-09a angnes Sⴝ46 9/11/09 4:42 Art: TP201180 Input-mn © 2009 Lippincott Williams & Wilkins those connected to recent proposals, which seek to address the scarcity of organs, but at the same time might threaten the applicability of the notion of donation in the context of organ transplantation (2). Bioethics and Self-Giving in Organ Donation The situation of organ donation, both by living and dead donors, is an expression of self-giving to another person, the recipient, characterizing every voluntary transplantation primarily as an interpersonal action (2). To be more precise, the present voluntary procedure of organ donation is based on a call to altruism. The act of organ donation could be seen as giving a gift; the reason is that the giver wants to benefit the recipient, acting freely and nothing being expected in return for the donation (7). The practice of organ donation shares also many elements with the ordinary understanding of charity (that is helping or giving to those in need of something); organ donation indeed has been described as a gift for life. According to the Charter for Health Care Workers (point 85), transplants “are legitimized by the principle of solidarity, which joins human beings, and by charity, which prompts one to give to suffering brothers and sisters. We are challenged to love our neighbor in new ways; in evangelical terms, to love event unto the end (Jn 13:1)” (8). In the perspective of self-giving, the donation of an organ (an inessential organ for the living donor) to someone who is needy is widely recognized as legitimate and laudable (2), a “service to life”, a “particularly praiseworthy example” of gesture of human sharing, “which build up an authentic culture of life” (9). Moreover, in this perspective, the donation after death cannot also be regarded as a moral duty, but exclusively depending on the generosity of donors who are undertaken with the reason of a genuine willingness to help someone who has a particular need and might not be known by the person performing the charitable act. This situation does not exclude that some people perceive organ donation as a moral “duty”, in the same meaning that many people perceive that they have a moral duty to perform acts of charity (7). On the contrary, stressing the current “shortage” of organs for transplantation could give rise to the impression that individuals who are unwilling to make organs available in some vague way are morally responsible for what is perceived as a “social problem”. The central question in transplantation, indeed, is whether or not a human being can be helpful to another one. Therefore, it would be regrettable if society, to solve distressing statistics, would decide to destroy the interpersonal character of transplantation and the aspect of human and voluntary service of another, which is intrinsic to it (2). On this ground, the refusal of organ donation should be necessarily respected. In the same way, it is believed that the family’s wishes about organ removal from the dead relative should be respected—without overriding the wishes of the dead person—as the relatives generally may be the best interpreters of the deceased’s wishes. Based on the concept of self-giving, all organ donations may be permitted only when they represent an altruistic act, meaning that nonfinancial incentives are associated to living or after death organ donation (10). S109 Bioethical Principles in Organ Transplantation The ethics of transplantation are based on the tension between bodily integrity and human solidarity. On one side, bodily integrity should be protected because of its uniqueness, a means by which we live. On the other side, we are also social beings, interdependent for life in human society (10). Several widely accepted bioethical principles are relevant to practices in transplantation. They include nonmaleficence (avoiding harm), beneficence (producing benefit), autonomy (respecting personal choices) and justice (distributing benefits and burdens equitably) (11). These principles require the satisfactions of basic conditions for an organ donation to be ethical. The Beneficence/Nonmaleficence Principle This principle of medical ethics requires a benefit/burden ratio in the perspective of both the donor and the recipient. Serving as an organ donor is not in the donor’s best medical interest as there is not a therapeutic benefit for him. On the contrary, there are some significant medical risks for the living donor, such as the risks of surgery and anesthesia, postoperative bleeding and infections, and pain. Sometimes an additional risk is the temporary, or even permanent, restrictions in social activities because of the donation (5). However, it is well accepted that there are psychologic and emotional benefits (an increased self-esteem) that donors may experience both as living donors and in donation that will be effective after death. Potential psychologic and emotional benefit cannot be extended to those persons with cognitive disabilities: usually this is prohibited by the law and regarded as unethical, because the individual does not understand implications of the operation. Another given reason of benefits to the donor in the case of relative living donor is the fact that the donor will receive more intrafamilial companionship after transplantation has been executed (5). However, there are also data on psychologic risks of serving as a living donor, such as lower self-esteem, a sense of neglect and a lack of expected appreciation after the donation as the attention refocuses on the recipient. Although the vast majority of donors do not regret their decision, cases of donor suicides have been reported. The real direct benefit to the donor is the “moral” benefit; psychologic and emotional benefits may be indirect, as a further positive consequence of a primarily moral benefit. The moral benefit of donation consists of the awareness of a moral good action, regardless of the transplant results or gratitude manifested by the recipient or by the relatives. In the case of a dead donor, such kind of moral benefit of a good action is the only benefit the potential dead donor may experience with regard to donation. The major factor to be considered in nonmaleficence of organ transplantation after death regards the criteria to pronounce the donor death. A debated ethical dilemma is whether it is justifiable to incur the risk of shortening the life of a person in the attempt to improve the life of another one. According to the “dead donor rule”, the subject must be recognized dead before removal of organs (2). The Charter for Health Care Workers states (point 74): “There must be certainty, however, that it is a corpse, to ensure that the removal of organs does not cause or even hasten death” (8). This rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/ztr2748-09a angnes Sⴝ46 9/11/09 4:42 Art: TP201180 Input-mn S110 | www.transplantjournal.com means that “the removal of organs requires that steps to ensure that the subject is actually dead must be duly verified” (9). Until comparatively recent times, it was generally accepted that the cessation of spontaneous breathing and spontaneous heart beat, during a well-defined period of time, indicated the end of an individual. Progress in medicine has made it possible to reverse this cessation and also determine the cessation of all cerebral functions as a significant factor in identifying the onset of death. According to the concept of brain death, a person is dead when it has been established that he or she has suffered an irreversible cessation of all brain functions and is incapable of spontaneous respiration (11). At the point when the whole brain death occurs the individual ceases to live, as since that moment there is no integrated functioning of the body as a whole (13). Initially, intensive care units faced the necessity to diagnose brain death to determine when to stop mechanical ventilation, as ventilation of a corpse has no real reason (14). The newly accepted criteria of brain death also consents to the timely removal of transplant organs. As we know, the transplanting time is a crucial factor. Damage from ischemia can irreversibly decrease the quality of organs and it would be unethical to transplant such organs. Living organ donation is most distinguishable from cadaveric donation in that it involves a healthy living person who consents to have a kidney, liver lobe or lung lobe removal. Notwithstanding his or her consent, the removal of an organ from an otherwise healthy patient, for no therapeutic benefit to the patient, constitutes a prima facie harm. It is still unclear whether removal of organs from living donors results in a decrease in life expectancy and in the increase of required medical care. However, it is certain that procurement of organs from living donors results in unneeded surgery, debility and risk of death. Indeed, after the success of cadavers as organ donors, the concern that using the living as donors is unethical has risen. Therefore, living-related donation is the only type of living donation that has traditionally been accepted by the transplant community and society. This is because the familial relationship allows us to make sense of what is otherwise an unusual choice; having a healthy organ removed. Livingrelated donation is allowed on the grounds that it can also be beneficial for the donor because of an existing, close relationship with the recipient. Over time, the paradigm of related donation has been extended, on the same grounds, to living unrelated donation within a relational context, such as close friendship (6). The main benefit to the recipient is a healthy living graft. Risks to the recipient include medical risks of the transplantation procedure and adverse effects of immunosuppression, which include increased risk of infection and malignancies. The requirement for chronic antirejection therapy, the presence of chronic or relapsing viral infections and environmental exposures to many opportunistic pathogens have created a state of increased vulnerability in transplanted patients (15). In the case of living donation, the recipient could experience psychologic and emotional feeling of being indebted; in addition, there is the potential risk of guilt if the donor experiences a significant morbidity or dies (5). Transplantation • Volume 88, Number 7S, October 15, 2009 With regards to the safety of transplantation for the recipient, we are challenged today with the problem of socalled marginal donors. Elderly donors, pediatric donors, diabetic donors, donors with hepatitis B or hepatitis C virus, hypertension and elevated creatinine, donors with long cold ischemia time and nonheart-beating donors are usually considered as marginal donors, that is, their organs are not considered optimal due to age or concomitant diseases (16). However, the chronic shortage of donors has resulted in attempts to use these donors, particularly for critically ill organ recipients, who would not survive without an immediate transplant. At present, there is a lack of uniform criteria concerning which organs ought to be discarded. The results of several studies (17, 18) demonstrate a survival disadvantage among transplant recipients who received a marginal organ, providing support for the position that transplanting organs from marginal donors should be avoided. The Autonomy Principle According to the ethical principle of autonomy, living donors have the right to get all the relevant information concerning the outcome, for both the recipient and himself. In the same way, all citizens should receive all the information about procedures involved in transplantation to give an informed and free consent “to offer during life a part of their body, an offer which will become effective only after death” (19). Before they are allowed to give the consent to organ donation and transplantation, both donors and recipients should be educated about these procedures and counseled at various steps, as well as being informed that it is permissible to withdraw consent at any time before the procedure (5). The Charter for Health Care Workers states (point 90): “In life or in death the persons from whom the removal is made should be aware that they are donors—that is, those who freely consent to the removal”. In this way, organ donation after death offers to the donors the possibility of “projecting beyond death their vocation to love [. . .] a great act of love, that love which gives life to others” (8). Organ donation by a living donor is regarded as a human and generous, even supererogatory, act to save a human being whose life is threatened by disease or whose quality of life is severely impaired. The consent to a potentially hazardous course of action, however, requires to take in account how donation will influence his own future and that of others, such as relatives, who may depend on him. Considering the moral obligation for a living donor to weigh and the foreseeable results of his action for all concerned, it might be argued that consent to such donation should be a shared decision of the donor and those closely related to him (2). One of the major objections to living organ donation is that there is the potential for the prospective donor to be induced or coerced in some way. In such cases, the donation would not be sufficiently voluntary to be called a gift. Conversely, the prospective donor could demand something from the recipient before donating the organ to him or her (7). As the efforts to use altruism for organ donation have met limited success, several recent approaches have been adopted to prompt self-interest in organ donation by financial incentives. Financial incentives are payments, and the living donors (or the family of a deceased donor) become vendors of parts of the human body. Buying and selling human rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/ztr2748-09a angnes Sⴝ46 9/11/09 4:42 Art: TP201180 Input-mn © 2009 Lippincott Williams & Wilkins organs would lead to an increasing objectification of the human body, compromising the respect for the human dignity (20 –22). Therefore, allowing forms of financial incentives to organ sources should not be considered an ethical attitude. In the same way, in the case of deceased organ donors, extensive adoption of presumed consent procedures or legislations to provide a solution to the problem of supply and demand are irrespective of the real willing of the person in life and, therefore, they are ethically inadequate solutions to help some unfortunate members of society (2). Perhaps, altruism alone will not be enough to satisfy the needs of the thousands of patients who are on organ transplant waiting lists, but not all means (i.e., marketing of bodily parts) are ethically acceptable to a certain end (i.e., supply of organs) (10). Especially in living donation, great attention towards psychologic and emotional pressure must be paid. For example, the decision to donate prompted by the emotional wellbeing that the donor may experience from receiving many warm appreciations by relatives could be regretted after the donation if the attention refocuses on the recipient. Organ donation must primarily be based on a moral decision rather than on a psychologic enthusiasm. The Justice Principle The justice principle requires that equity and fairness in the organ allocation system must be guaranteed. The growth in living organ donation, welcomed by many as an answer to the shortage of cadaveric organs donated for transplantation, gives rise to a number of serious ethical challenges regarding just and fair allocation of organs. In the United States, for instance, the current growth has been driven by several factors, including direct appeal by waiting list patients through media or pay-commercial websites that allow patients to advertise their need in the hope that a sympathetic person will make a directed donation of the required organ. This kind of non-related directed donation, also called “altruistic living donation”, opens doors to the market of organs. In fact, in the case of living directed acquaintance donation, there is the realistic fear of financial compensation. Especially, commercial efforts fostered by websites enable the recipient to find his or her own donor through high financial incentive, effectively buying an organ. Moreover, this type of donation also gives rise to the social justice concern of recipients unfairly jumping the waiting list through direct solicitation. Furthermore, advertising through news or media outlets or through commercial websites, even if there is no clandestine financial incentive, enables donors to select recipients in a biased fashion, based on race, ethnicity or social status (6). However, we should remember that the present expanding gap between the numbers of patients needing organs for transplantation and the number of organs available is not due to a shortage of potential donors. By far, the most common reason for non-donation is denial of consent by the donor’s family, which may be due to stresses surrounding death, misperceptions about the results of transplantation, mistrust of the medical community in general, doubts that the allocation system is equitable and the lack of understanding of brain death, leading to suspicion that the brain dead patient is not really dead (13). As death is still a taboo in western societies, people usually do not stop and consider the issue of organ donation, unless they lose a close relative and in a short S111 time and stressful context they are asked to make a choice about organ removal from the deceased’s body, to which they have often come to totally unprepared, as they have not thought through the issue sufficiently. People may refuse to donate their organs or their relatives’ organs because of incorrect belief about brain death (for example, that the person is not “wholly” dead) or transplantation procedures (e. g., fairness of organs allocation); they do not know enough to feel to consent to it. Educational campaigns to increase organ donation and transplantation should consider correction of people’s false belief and promotion of public information and clear discussion about what is involved in organ donation and transplantation. Moreover, educational programs should include education for social solidarity and education on the more troublesome-specific aspects of organ donation and transplantation. Gift-giving concept, that is giving organs as a gift, implies voluntarism and altruism in organ donation. This feature of organ donation should always be present in current organ donation awareness campaigns and during counseling sessions with relatives of potential organ donors. Educational efforts also primarily include schools and universities as the best target to form a renewed personal and social conscience on the importance of organ donation for transplantation and to state the background for a clear and responsible personal choice. Education on organ donation should focus on the high moral value of helping another human being through donation, and not merely on the emotional participation to the suffering of an individual. As we know, moral ideals and convictions are more steady and durable than the emotional or psychologic feelings, which could easily change to their opposite, simply due to the changing of emotional circumstances in the situation. In our opinion, education is the only ethically feasible way to guarantee the respect for responsible choices of each person in the society and, at the same time, to effectively promote the recruitment of organs. The law is a means (although not the only one) to increase the supply of organs; it sets the context, not only legally but also socially and ethically in which transplantation is performed and regarded. The law works well only when doctors incorporate, through education, the ethical and social view expressed by the law into their consciousness and practice. As the attitude of the medical profession towards organ transplantation could be a factor in inhibiting the supply of organs, this would not be significantly increased by simply changing the law to an opting out principle (4). Conclusions Organ donation is a noble act of human solidarity, therefore, the medical community and society should support this highly valued gift. However, donation remains a personal decision made by the donor being well informed and after expressing the consent. In the respect of the human dignity of the donor, this act should preserve the life of the donor or integrity of the organ system. Although this donation should be encouraged, the sale of organs should be regarded as a reductive, materialist and instrumental use of the person and, therefore, always forbidden. rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/ztr2748-09a angnes Sⴝ46 9/11/09 4:42 Art: TP201180 Input-mn S112 | www.transplantjournal.com In our opinion, voluntary gift-giving organ donation is the only morally permissible procurement procedure, as it is the only procedure preserving the respect of the donor. Organ donation should be accepted only when performed voluntarily (i.e., organ procurement procedures do not assume that someone should feel obliged to donate his or her organs) and when motivated by altruism. An analogy between organ donation and acts of charity may be a better way of promoting organ donation. The society should maximize the availability of organs for transplantation, eliciting informed and free choice on organ donation. Financial incentives are a form of coercive organ acquisition because they attempt to encourage or force people to do something that they would not otherwise be inclined to do. In the past, some authors (1) identified apathy of the medical profession as the main cause of the lack of organ donors. As organ donation and transplantation usually struggles to cope with difficult ethical questions, we suggest a role for bioethicists on organ transplantation services. Bioethicists can educate staff on the application of ethics to clinical practice of organ donation and transplantation, thus increasing ethical awareness among the medical profession (23). Donation as a responsible choice should be based on information, education and accurate consideration of the reasons for making a personal decision. References 1. 2. 3. 4. 5. 6. 7. 8. 9. 10. 11. 12. 13. 14. 15. 16. 17. 18. Calne RY. Transplantation. J Med Ethics 1975; 1: 59. Mahoney J. Ethical aspects of donor consent in transplantation. J Med Ethics 1975; 1: 67. Jonsen AR. The birth of bioethics. New York, Oxford University Press 1998, p 202. Kennedy I. Kidney transplants: A reply to Sells. J Med Ethics 1980; 6: 29. Ross LF, Thistlethwaite JR Jr; Committee on Bioethics. Minors as living solid-organ donors. Pediatrics 2008; 122: 454. Aulisio MP, DeVita M, Luebke D. Taking values seriously: Ethical challenges in organ donation and transplantation for critical professionals. Crit Care Med 2007; 35: S95. Gerrand N. The notion of gift-giving and organ donation. Bioethics 1994; 8: 127. Pontifical Council for Pastoral Assistance to Health Care Workers. Charter for Health Care Workers. Vatican City, Pontifical Council for Pastoral Assistance to Health Care Workers 1995. Spagnolo AG, Sgreccia E. Religious views on organ and tissue donation: Roman Catholic Church. In: Chapman JR, Deierhoi M, Wight C, eds. Organ and tissue donation for transplantation. London, Arnold 1997, p 27. Ghods AJ, Savaj S. Iranian model of paid and regulated living-unrelated kidney donation. Clin J Am Soc Nephrol 2006; 1: 1136. Sade RM. Cadaveric organ donation. Arch Intern Med 1999; 159: 438. The Pontifical Academy of Sciences. Why the concept of brain death is valid as a definition of death. Vatican City, The Pontifical Academy of Sciences 2008, p 6. Price DP. Organ transplant initiatives: The twilight zone. J Med Ethics 1997; 23: 170. Machado C, Korein J, Ferrer Y, et al. The concept of brain death did not evolve to benefit organ transplants. J Med Ethics 2007; 33: 197. Qamar AA, Rubin RH. Poorer outcomes for recipients of heart allografts from HCV-positive donors. JAMA 2006; 296: 1900. Abouna GM. Organ shortage crisis: Problems and possible solutions. Transplant Proc 2008; 40: 34. Charlton M. Liver biopsy, viral kinetics, and the impact of viremia on severity of hepatitis C virus recurrence. Liver Transpl 2003; 9: S58. Gasink LB, Blumberg EA, Localio AR, et al. Hepatitis C virus seropositivity in organ donors and survival in heart transplant recipients. JAMA 2006; 296: 1843. Transplantation • Volume 88, Number 7S, October 15, 2009 19. 20. 21. 22. 23. John Paul II, to the participants at the First International Congress on the Transplant of Organs, June 20, 1991 in Insegnamenti XIV/I (1991) 1712. Manga P. A commercial market for organs? Why not. Bioethics 1987; 1: 321. Joralemon D, Cox P. Body values: The case against compensating for transplant organs. Hastings Cent Rep 2003; 33: 27. Matas AJ. Design of a regulated system of compensation for living kidney donors. Clin Transplant 2008; 22: 378. Wright L, Ross K, Daar AS. The roles of a bioethicist on an organ transplantation service. Am J Transplant 2005; 5: 821. SELF-GIVING AND ORGAN DONATION: AN ANTHROPOLOGICAL PERSPECTIVE Jean Laffitte he University of Osaka in Japan recently unveiled a robot with human features that are incredible. This robot, which is female in appearance, carries out elementary movements, such as moving its lips, its eyelids, its arms and its torso. It has a silicon skin, which conceals a series of sensors that ensure the movement of the various parts of its body. With its promising prospects, robotics is attracting increasing interest on the part of writers and directors who often offer visions of worlds populated by these beings, which are similar to humans and are only distinguished, with difficulty, from men in flesh and blood. The famous film by Ridley Scott, Blade Runner, comes to mind. In the final part of this film, it appears that the protagonist, a replicant, is capable of feelings and sensations that are typically human (regret, sadness, pity, etc.). One could at this point easily imagine, to come to the subject of this article, a replicant who, needing a spare part to replace a part of his own damaged body, receives one from another replicant, thereby creating a kind of organ donation between machines. But even if this were possible, this approach would anyway be completely different from what takes place between humans through the experience of organ donation. I am referring above all to the symbolic and anthropological value that this kind of experience, which brings into play solidarity, altruism, suffering, a sense of one’s own death and that of other people, has for man. Although it takes place in practical terms within the sphere of medicine, the donation and acquisition of an organ is not only a medical act. It constitutes an experience that goes beyond the mere clinical and technical fact and incorporates symbols and values of an anthropological, ethical, social and also theological order. To be understood in its complexity, organ donation, which is present in nearly all contemporary cultures, therefore requires, greater examination at the level of the anthropological structure of what a gift is. Naturally, the anthropological approach determines the conception that one has of a gift, as a result of which different anthropological approaches determine different conceptions of the idea of a gift. Some anthropological visions are not compatible with each other because they lead to contrasting practical conclusions. In the first part of my article, I will try to illustrate briefly certain specific anthropological models to see what meaning they attribute to a gift. Then, after expounding and T The author declares no conflict of interest. rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/ztr2748-09a angnes Sⴝ46 9/11/09 4:42 Art: TP201180 Input-mn © 2009 Lippincott Williams & Wilkins clarifying the perspective of this article, I will explore the meaning that a gift acquires according to this point of view. This will lead us to examine a particular form of a gift, namely “self-giving”. I will then go on to examine the modality and the conditions that are required, so that one can see the donation of an organ as a true and authentic “gift”. At this point, it will be necessary to distinguish, at an anthropological level, between the donation of an organ from a living person and the donation of an organ from a cadaver. At the level of donation from a living person, many anthropological meanings are involved: the perception of one’s own body, physical deformation, the wish to be truly useful and so forth. But when one is dealing with donations ex cadavere, other high symbolic meanings can come into play: the idea of one’s own death, the mourning of family relatives and the expression of a last will, to give only a few examples. At these fundamental levels, one immediately realizes that the categories of analysis are not first of all those of science, technology, or, in part, of the art of medicine. From a scientific point of view, indeed, the removal of an organ always has the same value. It is for this reason that it was believed useful, during the planning stage of this congress, to propose an anthropological approach to the subject of organ donation as well. Materials and Methods Self-Giving and Its Anthropological Characteristics The Anthropological Models of Reference In the vast contemporary cultural scene, it is possible to identify some of the major currents of thought that offer different solutions to bioethical problems in general and, on the basis of which, different interpretations are given of organ transplants. Based on the classification drawn up by Anthony Fisher1 of the great dominant moral systems of contemporary culture, we may distinguish four principal anthropologies. Each one generates different positions with regards to organ donations: individualism (which is linked to various forms of ethical subjectivism and relativism), utilitarianismconsequentialism, communitarianism and deontologism of a Kantian imprint. Individualism In an individualistic vision of the world, the characteristic element is the free choice of the individual, as long as the rights and freedoms of other people are respected. This means that everything that is freely chosen by an individual and which does not injure the autonomy and the life of other individuals should be seen as right. Thus in the legislative and political field, the state should guarantee the highest freedom of action for its citizens in matters that concern personal existence. One understands that in the field of organ donation, this is translated into the need for every person to be able to choose whether to donate his organs, to sell them or to completely reject their donation. The body is thus seen as private property, an object that can be disposed of according to one’s own free will. Questions that are ethically difficult are often ignored. In the absence of anthropologically founded criteria, in the individualistic approach, the explicit consent of the 1 Fisher A. Contrasting ethical approaches to organ transplantation and xenotransplantation. Text presented to the Post-graduate Course in Bioethics at the St. Thomas University of Manila on 4 February 1999. S113 donor is fundamental—a consent that eliminates all doubts about the real wish of the subject to donate his organs. The tendency is for presumed consent or the consent of third parties not to be allowed. For this reason, the system of opting-in is privileged. Utilitarianism-Consequentialism According to this approach the legitimacy of an action is ascertained by a precise assessment of consequences or by the greatest utility, by which between two possibilities the one which has the greatest number of positive consequences and which reduces to the minimum the negative consequences is chosen. Therefore, the fundamental criterion of choice, independently of the intentions of the agent subject, is a result of the means used and the purpose of the action. This model sees efficiency and efficacy as the criteria of the practical action. The donation of organs thus seems a positive act in that its consequence is a high probability of saving human lives. Opting-out is the most effective system for this purpose given that it is what assures the greatest number of transplants. This approach, although it involves various risks and is subject to various criticisms, is today widespread because of the mentality that underlies it. It is widely accepted in various sectors of learning (science, economics, etc.) and inherent in the logic of feasibility and results. Communitarianism Contrary to the individualistic interpretative model, communitarianism privileges relations between people and identities in the community and it needs the fundamental element for the legitimacy of choices. The common good has precedence over private interests; the ethos of public service is exalted. In the field of the donation of organs, although this vision does not theorise an explicit duty on the part of the citizen to engage in the donation of organs, it evokes a sort of social responsibility, which has the individual participating in the common good through the donation of organs, if this does not involve, for the person concerned, an excessive damage. For this reason, the system of opting-in is privileged. The Deontologism of a Kantian Imprint Of a clear Kantian imprint, deontologism places emphasis on the importance of moral rules and on responsibility that is morally ascertained and of universal range. This system stresses a sense of duty being understood as the need to adapt to objective moral rules, which are independent of circumstances and other elements external to the action that is performed. The objectivity of the rule given by the Kantian maxim, “treat your neighbor always as an end and never as a means” is formalized, by what is known as positive law. In this approach, the system of opting-in, in the policies for the removal of organs, respects the principle of the nonexploitation of the donor. One can, thus, dispose of one’s own body but with the limit imposed by the need to not cause damage to the living donor. An Alternative Vision Faced with the four models which have just been listed, a conception based on a Christian vision of the world and of the person seeks to organize medical ethics that come from a long Hippocratic tradition of ethics of virtue. This conception is accompanied by a rediscovery of natural law in the classic sense of the word (and not the physicistic caricature rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/ztr2748-09a angnes Sⴝ46 9/11/09 4:42 Art: TP201180 Input-mn S114 | www.transplantjournal.com that is often made of it). This is a system of thought that places at the center of the analysis the authentic good of the person and his full realization. The approach is not only located in being a good person but in becoming one; in becoming a person of virtue. Within the context of organ donation, the question that is raised is whether this constitutes a true good for the person? The good end of donation, without a doubt, encounters the need to do good, but it also implies the need to avoid evil, which presupposes, for example, a prohibition on suppressing one life to help another or carrying out a removal of organs or parts of the bodies of people who are not consentient. The needs of other people, in this approach, are not dealt with through the violation of the true moral good of the donor. The end does not justify the means. The donation of organs, therefore, is also seen in the perspective of the full realization of the donor who, through the decision to donate an organ, achieves a good that helps to make him better (compassion for the infirmity of the recipient, the engagement of proportionate and ethically legitimate means). Results From Altruism to Giving In the broadest and most common meaning of the word, altruism (from alter, other) designates a form of moral quality characterized by the interest that a person expresses for the good of another. It seems that the term was used for the first time in 1854 in the Positivist Catechism of the French philosopher, Auguste Comte. This approach marks out the human species. Over recent decades, some scientists have studied various animal species and have been able to observe forms of social relationships that are believed to include behavior analogous to altruistic behavior. The development of such behavior, according to the kin selection theory, is said to be an important element in the evolution of species. However, in none of these animal species can one observe cooperation between individuals who are not genetically correlated (1) in the form that one can observe in humans. Altruism can take the form of a certain reciprocity, which has positive or negative characteristics. The positive characteristics concern the predisposition to reward the other for cooperative behavior, whereas the negative characteristics concern the propensity to impose sanctions for the violation of the rules of cooperation. However, the form of altruism that is of interest to us in this article is that which acquires its highest moral value when the interest in, and action for, the other are disinterested; not conditioned by the logic of a return, in other words when they are completely freely given. Affirmation of the possibility of free giving is not a philosophical or religious prejudice, even though various sociologists call into question the possibility of a completely disinterested form of altruism. In the view of these scholars, what is at play are different forms of gratification, such as, self-fulfilment and self-esteem, the satisfaction of a sense of justice and social reputation. The human altruistic approach in a positive sense takes the name of giving and was already present in Greek philosophy with the concept of kharis. As the verb khairein (to rejoice), from which it comes, indicates, the term kharis refers to a reason for joy and by extension a favor; a gift. Giving is the action that benefits a recipient of a kharis produced by a sub- Transplantation • Volume 88, Number 7S, October 15, 2009 ject and expressed by an object. Because everything that exists comes from a supreme source, which for the Greeks was the gods, then everything that makes the heart of men rejoice was a divine gift. In the poet Homer, in the playwrights (Sophocles in particular) and in Socrates, we have this idea of a supreme and original gift, a divine favor made over to humans and an expression of divine filia. The gift, in as much as it characterizes the lives of all the members of the polis, establishes the constitutive ties of the koinonia; it is to do with the common good and in this sense it is not extraneous to the moral sphere. It does not bring with it the need for a “counter-gift” (we would then be in another logic, that of dosis-antidosis), but makes the donor appreciated; it generates gratitude. In the Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle, we already have an entire philosophy of the gift, which is totally extraneous to the logic of an exchange of interests. The gift would never cease to be at the heart of philosophical thought. The kharis becomes gratia, a term that has different meanings in profane and sacred contexts. In the Latins, and above all in Seneca, we find a theorisation of the gift in its most oblative meaning, of the gift that each person can make to his neighbor as he can to a stranger. Seneca (2) in De Beneficiis comes to say that the practice of gifts (beneficia) constitutes the most powerful tie of human society. Not only does he say that a gift has a beauty in itself but also adds that to give without hoping for something in return is the very essence of a gift. To give, for Seneca, defines the essential of our relations and constitutes the heart of a moral relationship. To the extent of which his vision sees in giving a unilateral act, in which the stoic sees the highest moral expression, we have the first break with the traditional conception of the ceremonial or ritual gift. For this reason, some people have seen in Seneca, the father of modern individualism (3). Within the context of the sacred, gratia expresses the gift that God makes to his creature. It designates not only the spiritual capacity that is conferred on the human soul (spiritual grace), which is made capable of wanting and doing what pleases God, but also the Gift that God makes of Himself, the Holy Spirit. In the Christian tradition, a distinction is thus made between Created Grace and Increated Grace. In the first meaning, we find the idea of what the tradition of the Old Testament designated with the term “hén”, a generous gift of God to his people. In this article, it is not appropriate to analyze the three forms that this act of divine benevolence can take (election, covenant and law). However, it is significant that the conception of a radical, transcendent, unconditional and merciful gift by the God of Israel seems an exceptional case in the eyes of the historians of religions. What interests us is that in revelation was unveiled the beauty of the free giving of a generous gift that knows that it cannot be repaid. Until modern times, nobody would contest the coherence of a divine justice that cannot be measured with the criteria of simple human justice: proportion, measure and ratio. The Calling Into Question of the Gift Today, reflection on gifts is characterized by two antagonistic currents— one which affirms the possibility of a disinterested gift and another which denies this. The first is represented above all by Christian tradition. It has shown how freely given gifts consolidated human societies. In the Catholic family, a gift enters in the constitution of communion rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/ztr2748-09a angnes Sⴝ46 9/11/09 4:42 Art: TP201180 Input-mn © 2009 Lippincott Williams & Wilkins and can generate the development of an ethos of giving. Man, created in the image and likeness of God, is linked to other men because of a common origin; from this shared dignity derives the fact that biological and family relationships are expanded to a form of transfigured and spiritual kinship, that makes the whole of the human species a family, in which the need for altruism is born. The so-termed communion of saints refers to a society in which love is offered and received as a gift; in the Protestant family the concept of religious ethics of brotherhood, to take up the famous phrase of Max Weber (4), makes every relationship with the other a personal relationship. The communitarian experience of brotherhood marks a necessary step toward the constitution of a society in which in the future a universal goodness is established, where every man can be seen as the recipient of an oblative love. The second modern current tends toward a negation of the possibility of a gift as it is understood in Christian tradition. A gift is certainly recognized as a relationship of solidarity between he who gives and he who receives and also a relationship of the superiority of the giver over the receiver. In the famous study by Mauss (5), we encounter the most elaborate sociological and anthropological reflection of what a gift is. In the view of Mauss, many societies are structured around an economics and a morality of the gift due to the fact that personal relationships in these societies are predominant. Individuals and groups have an interest in showing that they are disinterested. Men are led to make gifts because the act of giving imposes an obligation on the recipient. Why, then, is he who receives led to reciprocate? In the view of the author, because beliefs exist according to which the things that are offered have a soul that leads them to return to the person who has given them. In this way, Mauss thinks that he has solved the enigma of what a gift is (6). I will not explore here the legacy of a vision, which in the end denies the true ability of man to be generous through a truly freely given gift. However, the fact remains interesting, that despite the suspicion cast on one of the most essential elements of every human society, the author recognizes the existence of a form of symbolism in a gift that has been made. This will allow us to examine how the gift of a human organ is the bearer of symbolic values even though it has the capacity to be the fruit of a totally disinterested act. The study of the structure of what a gift is did not end with the work of Mauss or other authors who denied the possibility of free giving (the sociological school of Durkheim, for example). Some currents of modern philosophy have retrieved the gift (moral phenomenology, Jewish or Christian personalism). The dialogic structure of man has been explored and the terms solidarity and responsibility have become philosophical concepts (Ebner, Buber, Jonas and Levinas). Some have seen in the gift an original datum of the nature of man (Claude Bruaire). However, in this article, I cannot explore the specific contribution of these representatives of personalism. Discussion Organ Transplant as an Expression of a Gift It is now appropriate to examine the two forms of organ transplantation on the basis of the source of the organ— cadavers or living people. S115 Ex Cadavere Organs In the case of the removal of organs ex cadavere, we have two very different modalities for the expression of consent. Indeed, consent can be given either by the person himself before his death or by a family relative when a person dies, without having expressed beforehand any indication on the question. From the point of view of the anthropological value of the gift, it is important to identify the subject who gives the gift. In the case of the direct consent of the individual, this consent can be expressed in different ways: through a classic will and testament, through so-called prior treatment directives (on which the Italian National Bioethics Committee has expressed its view) (7), through the compilation of specific forms that are then kept in data banks created for this purpose, or orally, but in a repeated, and somehow verifiable, way. The direct expression of consent to the donation of organs is what most expresses the meaning of the gift in its most authentic form as an intimately matured and freely chosen choice. In this, there comes into play the view that the person has of his body and his death, and thus implies a previous acceptance and a full awareness of the limits of his own existence. In the case of consent expressed by a family relative after the death of another family relative, the view of the body of the dead person and above all of a person to whom another was especially close, a body which, in the imagination, still represents a link with the deceased person, acquires importance. In the case of consent expressed by a family relative, the value of “giving oneself”, of donating oneself, remains intact because to consent to the removal of organs, an act of profound acceptance of the death of one’s relative, is necessary. One consents to the “physical deformation” of the cadaver of the loved person, which is still perceived as the presence of his being, a center of meanings, of experiences and of affective and existential ties. Dominion over this feeling toward the lifeless body of a loved person is made possible by awareness of the need of another person, by a perception of a greater good, perceived as such. However, this process is very arduous and often generates reticence on the part of the family to consenting to a donation. The idea that one can manipulate the body of the deceased person is, at times, felt as a lack of respect during the crucial moment of the first working out of mourning. The cadaver after a certain fashion, is perceived as still “belonging” to the family. This idea, paradoxically, is less strong when one proceeds, for example, to the cremation of a cadaver. This is seen as a ritual act which attests definitively to the death of the person and does not obstruct the working out of mourning by the family relatives. On May 15, 1956, Pius XII, when addressing the Association of the Donors of Corneas and the Italian Union of the Blind, laid stress on a suitable sensitization of family relatives: “it is necessary to educate the public and to explain with intelligence and respect that to consent expressly or tacitly to interventions that violate the integrity of a cadaver in the interest of those who suffer does not offend the piety because of the deceased if the reasons are particularly important. rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/ztr2748-09a angnes Sⴝ46 9/11/09 4:42 Art: TP201180 Input-mn S116 | www.transplantjournal.com Despite this, this consent can constitute a suffering and a sacrifice for the near relatives, but this sacrifice brings the aurora of merciful charity toward brethren who suffer” (8). At times, doubts are raised about the validity of consent to donation granted by a family relative given the fact that the deceased did not express this readiness when he was still alive. This demonstrates the importance of sensitizing people to expressing their own wishes on the matter in an explicit way and preferably in written form. Tacit consent to donation is applied in some legislation. This article does not include in its aims an examination of the questions and issues connected with presumed consent, which will be analyzed elsewhere during this congress. At an anthropological level, as was illustrated at the beginning of this article, some models come to see the cadaver in juridical terms as res communitatis, justifying its use for social purposes independently of the direct consent of the person involved or his family relatives. For example, in the view of Childress, there are four ways of acquiring human organs: donation, abandonment and sale are the first three; and he invites a development of the fourth, which he calls “societal appropriation” (9). In this article, I cannot dwell on the special difficulties that a family could encounter in consenting to the donation of certain specific organs, for example, the heart or a part of the encephalon, even though this last possibility is still purely theoretical. It is sufficient to say that the anthropological meaning linked to the donation of these organs is made up of the fact that symbolically the brain refers to the spiritual and intellective personality of the subject, whereas the heart refers to the person in his totality. In definitive terms, the problem concerns the question of the symbolic location of the existence of the person. The metaphysical nature of the question deserves a specific analysis. Organs From Living People In medical practice, certain forms of donation by the living, which involve a rather reduced risk for the donor and the recipient, are by now widespread. Such is the case with blood and bone marrow. The donation of blood, in particular, is by now seen as a routine medical action and today involves a large number of people. With regards to the donation of bone marrow, conversely, the procedure is much more complex and the number of donations is notably lower, above all because of the difficulties that are encountered in finding a donor who is compatible with the patient at the immunological level. In the removal procedures, as well, there is a substantial difference compared with blood donation. To donate the bone marrow involves hospitalization and total or local anesthesia, otherwise, the action would be rather painful. In these forms of donations and in others, such as kidney donation, the donation of a part of the liver or lung, the value of self-giving; of giving a part of one’s body for the good of other people and without any condition or personal benefit, emerges with especial force. In addition, donations of this kind are, in some cases, carried out without there being any personal link between the donor and the recipient, as a result of which the person who decides to donate does so simply because of the value present in the act in itself, independently of the actual person who is the recipient of this gift. Transplantation • Volume 88, Number 7S, October 15, 2009 The donation of an organ seeks to eliminate a deficiency in another person. Obviously, this is a good for the recipient, a good for his health, but it is also a deeper good. Indeed, the recipient becomes the recipient of an altruistic and generous act in which he discovers and sees confirmed the fact that his recovery and his health, is an authentic good for society. With regards to the donor, he too discovers a good: he finds in the physical good of the other his moral good, and for this reason, he wants to achieve it. We are beyond simple justice. There is a beauty in the gift that cannot be reduced to the beauty of justice. The gift is doing good (a beneficium, Seneca would say). Indeed, in the concept of justice is implicit the meaning of exchange, of proportion between two greatnesses that must be commensurable (indeed to explain this logic Aristotle (10) has recourse to a clearly mathematical argument).2 Justice consists in giving to someone what is due to him. Referring to distributive justice, that is to say to justice in the public sphere, Aristotle (11) asserts that what is just is proportional . . . whereas the unjust is what violates proportion.3 In the gift, instead, this logic disappears in that the principle of asymmetry between the donor and the recipient, and apparently therefore, the principle of disproportion between the gift made and what is gained from it belongs to the very nature of the gift. The gift comes first. It cannot be derived. Man finds in self-giving a good. This good belongs to the category of fundamental goods (to use a phrase of John Finnis [12]), that is to say goods that cannot be explained. They are “first principles that cannot be demonstrated because they are evident”.4 It is interesting to note than among the seven fundamental goods, Finnis also perceives that of sociability or friendship, which we may consider to be at the basis of the concept of a gift: there is the value of that sociability, which in its weakest form is achieved by a minimum of peace and harmony among men, and which runs through the forms of human commu2 “For proportion is equality of ratios, and involves four terms at least . . . e.g. ‘as the line A is to the line B, so is the line B to the line C’; the line B, then, has been mentioned twice, so that if the line B be assumed twice, the proportional terms will be four); and the just, too, involves at least four terms, and the ratio between one pair is the same as that between the other pair; for there is a similar distinction between the persons and between the things. As the term A, then, is to B, so will C be to D, and therefore, alternando, as A is to C, B will be to D. Therefore also the whole is in the same ratio to the whole; and this coupling the distribution effects, and, if the terms are so combined, effects justly. The conjunction, then, of the term A with C and of B with D is what is just in distribution, and this species of the just is intermediate, and the unjust is what violates the proportion”. 3 “For the justice which distributes common possessions is always in accordance with the kind of proportion mentioned above (for in the case also in which the distribution is made from the common funds of a partnership it will be according to the same ratio which the funds put into the business by the partners bear to one another); and the injustice opposed to this kind of justice is that which violates the proportion”. 4 Finnis, following St. Thomas Aquinas, places the self-evident fundamental goods in a close relationship with the nature of man: “The fundamental forms of good, understood by the practical intellect, are what is good for human beings with the nature that they have. The Aquinate observes that practical reasoning does not begin knowing this nature from the outside, as those he proceeded defining it with observations and judgements of a psychological, anthropological or metaphysical character, but experiencing his own nature, so to speak, from inside, in the forms of his own inclinations’ (p. 37). rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/ztr2748-09a angnes Sⴝ46 9/11/09 4:42 Art: TP201180 Input-mn © 2009 Lippincott Williams & Wilkins nity until it reaches its strongest form in the flourishing of full friendship. Some forms of cooperation between one person and another are only instrumental to the achievement by each of them of their own individual goals. Friendship, however, implies that one acts out of love for one’s friends’ well-being. We may observe that, for this author, the fundamental forms of good grasped by the practical intellect are what is good for human beings given their nature. In the human heart, there is a natural inclination to do good, which is realized in the gift of oneself, without expecting a return. The gift of organs belongs to the structure of a gift: at the outset, we have a life that we experience spontaneously as a gift. We observe first of all that the phrase “self-giving” is not a phrase with a literal meaning but an analogical one. Self-giving has two meanings. The first is, for example, the one that we find in the Constitution Gaudium et Spes of the Second Vatican Council: “man . . . cannot fully find himself except through a sincere gift of himself” (13). In this context, the phrase designates the offering of one’s own life in imitation of the gift of his own life that Christ made to men; in the second meaning, self-giving refers to the object of the gift. The object of the gift can take many different forms, for example, one can give one’s own time, offer one’s readiness to help, give one’s most fundamental personal goods, make available to the other one’s own freedom or take on risks for another person. In the case of transplants, the object of the gift refers to a part of the body (14).5 This part, after a certain fashion, can be assimilated to an exterior good, given that the donor does not cease to be himself after donating his kidney or a lobe of his liver. The phrase is ambiguous, because here we find a medical perspective that specifies first of all the position of the recipient. I cannot analyze here what ultimately founds the medical act, but I will observe that a medical doctor, when he exercises his art, does so in respect of the unity of the organism and of the patient. So, how can we define the act of giving an organ? One chooses to forgo one’s own physical integrity to the extent that this act can save the life of another person. Thus, we have a proportionate good; proportionate because we have in the donor and the recipient the same nature. The measure of the legitimacy of self-giving is the health of the other. Thus, it is not an irrational and romantic act, but it is a concrete and realistic act. It is to be inscribed within a strictly medical finality. How can a transplant be the expression of a gift in the sense that I have given to this word? This is not a religious or philosophical stance, a priori. It is in this way that men naturally perceive their lives: the life that we have precedes all consciousness of self and thus every personal stance towards this original fact. This life can be expressed in various ways in self-giving, the gift of organs is one of the possible concrete expressions of this self-giving. For John Paul II, the decision to offer, without recompense, a part of one’s body possesses the characteristics of love: “Here precisely lies the nobility of the gesture, a gesture which is a genuine act of love. It is not just a matter of giving away 5 “every organ transplant has its source in a decision of great ethical value: «the decision to offer without reward a part of one’s own body for the health and well-being of another person»”. S117 something that belongs to us but of giving something of ourselves, for “by virtue of its substantial union with a spiritual soul, the human body cannot be considered as a mere complex of tissues, organs and functions. Rather, it is a constitutive part of the person who manifests and expresses himself through it”” (14). In this approach, what is an organ? It is the instrument of the gift, not in itself but in service to the whole of an organism. In the biological life of a man, the whole is not the mere addition of the organs: we have a psychosomatic unity; it is the body of the recipient, in its own unity, that is ultimately in the transplant that has been carried out; the cause of the practical outcome (success) of the gift. An adequate counterparty does not exist. In the world of interpersonal relations, which Levians loved to characterize with the phrase “asymmetrical reciprocity”, the gift of an organ can only be corresponded by the gift of gratitude; it is the free giving of the gift that generates gratitude. I will not here take into consideration the donations connected with human sexuality and procreation, such as that of ovocytes or sperm, which can be made for research purposes or within the field of heterologous artificial fertilisation. The fact that this kind of donation raises specific ethical problems requires a more detailed analysis, but this would place my article outside its purpose. In the case of the donation of organs by a living person, the approach of the recipient is also important. He adopts a sense of responsibility toward the organ that has been received, being aware that the donor has had to accept a decrease in his own state of health. This sense of responsibility can have a particular relevance in social behavior at risk. A subject who is addicted to alcohol and is suffering from hepatic cirrhosis and receives the transplant of a lobe of the liver from a living donor, for example, could adopt a prudent and responsible lifestyle that does not damage the organ that has been received. We have been able to see that the gift corresponds to a profound and fundamental tendency in the heart of man. Like every value, it may be not understood, and certainly, it is not compatible with a certain utilitarian vision that considers man a fundamentally selfish being. I believe that the true gift exists and that it naturally corresponds to an aspiration that is very deep in the human being. The gift of an organ is ethically justified when the subject has expressed his own consent to the donation. But in the process that leads to the decision to donate an organ, another level of reflection emerges, which is that of its anthropological meanings. In this article, an attempt has been made to emphasize this. If one wants to encourage this kind of gift, efforts must be directed toward informing and educating people. The body of a man cannot be seen as an object or as a good to be exchanged. It conserves its dignity even after the death of the person. Only the form of donation allows the body to be used without denying the meanings of which it is the bearer. I would add, to end this article, that the act of donating an organ is always a strong and natural symbolic expression of a love. I would like to evoke, even though with a certain straining to which I willingly confess, the way in which the Apostle St. Paul rendered homage to the love that the Galatians demonstrated towards him: “For I bear you witness that, rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/ztr2748-09a angnes Sⴝ46 9/11/09 4:42 Art: TP201180 Input-mn S118 | www.transplantjournal.com if possible, you would plucked out your eyes and given them to me”. References 1. AQ: 12 2. 3. 4. 5. 6. 7. 8. 9. AQ:13 10. AQ:14 12. 13. AQ: 15 14. AQ: 16 Fehr E, Fischbacher E. The nature of human altruism. Nature 2003; 425: 785. Seneca LA. De Beneficiis, I, IV, 2. Henaff M. Le prix de la vérité. Le don, l’argent, la philosophie. Paris, Seuil 2002, pp 337. Weber M. L’Ethique protestante et l’Esprit du capitalisme. Paris, Flammarion 2000. Mauss M. Essai sur le don. Paris, Quadrige 2007. Godelier M. L’énigme du don. Paris, Flammarion 2008, pp 19. Comitato Nazionale per la Bioetica. Dichiarazioni anticipate di trattamento. Presidenza del Consiglio dei Ministri, Dipartimento per l’informazione e l’editoria, 2003. Pope Pius XII. Allocution to the donors of corneas and to the Italian Union of the blind (14 May 1956). Acta Apostolicae Sedis 1956; 48: 464. Kreis H. The question of organ procurement: Beyond charity. Nephrol Dial Transplant 2005; 20: 1303. Aristotle. Nicomachean Ethics, Book V. Finnis J. Legge naturale e diritti naturali. Torino, Giappichelli Editore 1996, pp 93. Second Vatican Council. Pastoral Constitution Gaudium et Spes. Acta Apostolicae Sedis 1966; 58: 1025. Pope John Paul II. Address to the 18th International Congress of the Transplantation Society (29 August 2000). Acta Apostolicae Sedis 2000; 92: 826. THEORETICAL ASPECTS OF INFORMED CONSENT IN ORGAN DONATION AND TRANSPLANTATION Håkan Gäbel heoretical aspects cannot be entirely separated from legal and ethical aspects, but the title relieves me of the task to discuss in detail all legal and ethical issues. To my mind, ethical and theoretical deliberations lead to legislation, which may be implemented in different ways and which may or may not be followed. In national transplant acts, the autonomy of the individual and the possibility to decide for himself on matters regarding organ or tissue donation and transplantation ranges on a scale with many steps, from total autonomy to no autonomy. There are differences between donation and transplantation and there are good summaries of transplant legislation in Europe (1, 2). T Some Definitions: Informed and Presumed Consent and the Need for Surrogate Decision Makers Informed Consent Informed consent is a process where you are told (or get the information in some other way) about the possible risks and benefits of the treatment. You are informed of the risks and benefits of other options, including not getting treatment; you have the chance to ask questions and get them answered to your satisfaction; you have had the time (if needed) to discuss the plan with family or advisors; you are able to use the information to help make a decision that you think in the best interest and finally you communicate that decision to your doctor or treatment team. There are several distinct and separate elements of informed consent as outlined in “How informed is informed The author declares no conflict of interest. Transplantation • Volume 88, Number 7S, October 15, 2009 consent?” (3): competence, voluntariness, disclosure, recommendation, understanding, decision and authorisation. The elements disclosure and recommendation are in the realm of the medical profession. One wonders how detailed the information should be? Can it always be factual and neutral or is it biased? Is the information always understandable? The information and the recommendations given by the medical professionals to the patient (the “decision maker”) and his or her proxy form the basis for their deliberations. Some of the elements such as competence, voluntariness, understanding, decision making and authorisation are in their realm. When it comes to decision making, we are all more or less competent. We may have a clouded consciousness because of a medical condition or advanced age, we may be sedated or even unconscious when our opinion on treatment is asked for. We might not have been informed enough and prompted to give consent to treatment when we were not fully competent and our proxies are now asked to be our deputies. Presumed Consent “Presumed consent is a fiction. Without the actual consent of the individual there is no consent: Many see presumed consent as synonymous with contracting out . . ..” The underpinning message of the system to which conflation of these terms refer is something like this: “unless you make it clear during your lifetime that you would refuse to donate organs on death, we will presume that you consent to organ removal, even though you do not actually consent” (4). Informed consent and presumed consent can be expressed in many ways. The Swedish Transplant Act that does not regulate transplantation but only donation is stated as follows: Material intended for transplantation can be procured from a deceased person having consented to the procedure (informed consent). Or else material for . . . can be procured unless the deceased had objected in any way (presumed consent). And moreover, relatives have to be informed about the intended procedure and about the option to veto the procedure. Thus, the transplant act has also introduced the family or significant others as surrogate decision makers. Proxies or Surrogate Decision Makers Because very few have either given a valid informed consent or paid attention to the option to object to donation, there is obviously a need for proxies or surrogate decision makers. Legislation on proxies varies from state to state, and, in some states, there are no rules at all. The proxies, substitutes or deputies may be of several kinds. For minors, the parents are most often the legal guardians, according to the Convention on the Rights of the Child (5). Most often spouses, other relatives or significant others can act as proxies. Temporarily medical professionals can act as proxies in the best interest of their patients especially in life threatening situations—most patients want to survive. Most often there can be many deputies and sometimes they do not agree as to what is in the best interest of the person in question. rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/ztr2748-09a angnes Sⴝ46 9/11/09 4:42 Art: TP201180 Input-mn © 2009 Lippincott Williams & Wilkins I doubt very much that the proxies are fully aware of how they are supposed to act: “Certainly one would like to know more about how surrogates are chosen, on what grounds they make their decisions; how they feel about this responsibility, how well they succeed in following the guidelines currently in place” (6). Do they act in the best interest of their principal— the best interest standard? What is actually in the best interest of a critically ill, dying patient or of an already dead person? Is there a living will or registered will to be a donor as on a donor card or a registration on a donor register? Do the deputies always follow the will—the precedent autonomy standard or advance directive principle? Another alternative for the deputies would be to try to imagine what the principal would have decided taking all the current circumstances into account—substituted judgment standard (6). Most often the standards for decision making are intermingled and also influenced by what a reasonable or virtuous person would do. Consent for Live Organ Donation and for Transplantation Despite the shortcomings of informed consent, (7) it can be argued that informed consent is the sine qua non for human subjects’ research and live organ donation. In these circumstances, the subject or patient is healthy and volunteers to carry the risks of the procedure in the interest of science, as in human subjects’ research or in the interest of the recipient as in live organ donation. But how much and how detailed is the information given to the potential living donor. There seems to be room for improvement. “More prospective studies are needed to improve the process of informed consent in this population (live organ donors)” (8) and “As dependence on living organ donation increases best practices for informed consent, donor evaluation and uniform risk conveyance need to be established” (9). According to the Vancouver forum (10, 11), which addressed the care of the live lung, liver, pancreas and intestine organ donation, the potential donor must have a cognitive capacity sufficient to make the decision to donate, the decision must be voluntary and the donor must receive and understand relevant and sufficient information about the procedure. A similar forum on the care of the live kidney donors had previously arrived at a similar consensus (12). Considering the information given by other speakers (K. Laouzbdia-Sellami, F. Delmonico, V.D. Garcia and L. Noel) at this International Congress, in the session on Organ Donation, the need for organs and the question of trafficking organs can be questioned as well as whether most living donors meet the prerequisites for giving an informed consent. There are regrettably many exploited living donors in some parts of the world. Before we subject live donors to risks and use their organs, we need to increase the availability of organs and tissues from deceased donors at no risk to them. It is a deplorable fact that deceased organ donation is not a realistic option in many parts of the world. “It is now evident that live donors are the sole source of organs for transplantation in many societies” S119 (10, 11). It is a major task for the transplant community to make deceased organ donation a possibility everywhere. Informed consent also seems to be the best consent option for the transplantation of organs. The questions once again arise: How much information? How detailed should the information to the recipient be? How competent is he or she when the information is given? Should information also be given on the donor and the quality of the graft? There are regulations in place, as in European Union (EU)-directives, intended to prevent the transmission of infectious or malignant diseases, but there are also suboptimal or extended criteria donors, donors of advanced age having died from cerebrovascular disease where the function of the graft may not be ideal. How to inform the recipients about the quality of the graft? (13) “As our list for extended donor pool kidneys grows, we must devise a standard means of true informed consent” (14). Can we accept that the patient, who is offered a kidney transplant from a marginal donor, turns down that offer? In fact, does the patient give the opinion that “this kidney is not good enough for me”— but maybe for someone else? Or is it a medical obligation to decide what is good enough to be transplanted and what is not? Consent for Deceased Organ Donation In an ideal world, mostly everyone would take a stand on postmortem donation, after adequate information, and communicate his or her stand. There would be good systems for recording the wishes or preferences of individuals (donor cards or registries)— be they in favor of or opposed to— informed or presumed consent. There would be a good system of proxies in the event there was no information and proxies would always honor the wishes of the deceased if known. But we do not live in an ideal world. What constitutes adequate information on deceased organ donation? Of course it has to be factual and neutral, but how detailed? Should it include the care of the critically ill and the possibility that the treatment is futile, but given to make organ donation a possibility of nontherapeutic ventilation, or the Exeter protocol (15, 16). It should of course cover brain related, as well as circulatory criteria, of death because many countries now and again procure organs from donors after cardiac death. No doubt the information has to be similar regardless of the pattern of consent— be it informed or presumed consent. Is it appropriate to convey the message of the great need of organs for transplantation? How should the information be given and how do we make sure it reaches everyone? We live in an information society with an abundance of information. In giving information on deceased organ donation we would compete with other interested parties at a great expense. It can be questioned if it is reasonable to inform the entire population in detail about deceased organ donation, with special problems regarding minors and those with restricted autonomy or who are less competent, on issues that will affect, at most, 60 per million population (PMP)? It can be argued that it would be better to give general information on donation and transplantation to create a society where donation is considered the norm, vide infra, and to concentrate on rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/ztr2748-09a angnes Sⴝ46 9/11/09 4:42 Art: TP201180 Input-mn S120 | www.transplantjournal.com informing and caring for the family of the dying or deceased potential donor. Most pay lip service to deceased organ donation, but few take action and make their wishes known to their relatives, with donor cards or on donor registers. In Sweden, for example, 66% of the population has discussed organ donation with their relatives (EU average 41%), 81% would be willing to donate their own organs and 74% would donate the organs of a deceased relative (EU averages 56% and 54%, respectively). Ninety-five percent support the use of donor cards in Sweden (EU average 81%); however, only some 30% carry donor cards (17). Interestingly enough, there is an inverse relationship between the percentage of donor card holders and the number of deceased organ donation PMP. In the Netherlands, Sweden and Spain, more than 40%, some 30% and some 5% of the population, respectively, carry donor cards. The number of donors PMP are as follows: 12 PMP in the Netherlands, 15 PMP in Sweden and 35 donors PMP in Spain. In many states national organ donor registers have been introduced to allow citizens to register their attitudes to deceased organ and tissue donation (18). The registers are all different and dependent on the transplant act in the country. In some countries with informed consent legislation there are donor registers where you can only register as a donor. In countries with presumed consent legislation there can be non-donor registers accepting only objections to donation. There are also combined registers where you can register either an acceptance or a refusal to donate. Despite costly efforts to increase enrolment on national donor registers, too few have registered to make them really useful. To be sure, many registrations would be desirable in donor registers, whereas few would be desirable in nondonor registers. In some of the combined registers as in the Netherlands and Sweden, where you can either register as a donor or object to donation, some 20% to 40% of the population has registered, and in non-donor registers, as in France, only some per thousand have registered. Moreover, the legal status of a registration as an informed consent can be questioned. “The websites and consent forms for public enrolment in organ donation do not fulfil the necessary requirements for informed consent. The websites predominantly provide positive reinforcement and promotional information rather than the transparent disclosure of organ donation process” (19). Donor registers have not lived up to the expectation that they would, by themselves, increase the number of deceased donors (18). Presumed Consent Versus Informed Consent for Deceased Organ Donation There is an ever ongoing discussion on the merits of presumed consent versus informed consent for deceased organ donation. Most recently the issue was brought up in the United Kingdom. It can be argued what is preferable—informed consent or presumed consent (20). “Presumed consent for organ donation—Is an ethical and effective way of dealing with organ donation shortages”. The organ donation taskforce is currently conducting an inquiry into the practical, ethical, legal and societal implications of presumed consent. Transplantation • Volume 88, Number 7S, October 15, 2009 Is presumed consent the answer to organ shortages? Yes It would be good for those who support donation, because they have to make no effort to ensure their wishes are followed; good for those who oppose donation, because their wishes will be formally recorded and must be followed; and good for the families, because they are relieved of the burden of decision making . . . Good for those who need a transplant . . . (21). No Systems of opting out do not ensure higher rates of donation than opting in systems. Strategies to encourage people to donate and public education seem to help and are independent of whether people have to opt in or out (22). The Lords committee comes down against presumed consent for organ donation. “The system of presumed consent would be ineffective without the numbers of skilled staff and a coordinated system needed to deal with the greater volume of donor organs that this might generate”. Baroness Howard, House of Lords, declares: “All parts of the National Health Service (NHS) must accept organ donation as a usual—not an unusual— event and (must accept) that many more, and better trained, medical staff should have the role of providing organ donation services” (23). The House of Lords and Baroness Howard touch on the importance of skilled staff and a coordinated system needed to deal with the greater volume of donor organs that presumed consent might generate. The necessity of skilled staff was brought up by other invited speakers at the congress (R. Matesanz and M. Manyalich). Why not provide the additional staff and the coordinated system needed? All arguments considered I think there may be a case for presumed consent, but it must be properly implemented as suggested by the House of Lords and Baroness Howard. As mentioned earlier, most individuals support donation, but few have made their support known, and if they have done so, surrogate decision makers do not always follow the wishes of the deceased. Religions Support Transplantation In Transplants—Ethical Eye (24), there is information on the views of the major religions (Catholicism, Protestantism, The Orthodox church, Judaism, Islam, Buddhism and Agnostic ethics on transplantation). Suffice to give here the views of the Catholic Church and Judaism. John Paul II has appeared at meetings with transplant professionals on (at least) two occasions. To the participants of the Society for Organ Sharing, June 20, 1991, he said: “Above all, this form of treatment is inseparable from a human act of donation. In effect, transplantation presupposes a prior, explicit, free and conscious decision on the part of the donor or of someone who legitimately represents the donor . . .”. And: “It is obvious that vital organs can only be donated after death, but to offer in life a part of one’s body, an offering which will be effective only after death, is already in many cases an act of great love, the love which gives life to others”. rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/ztr2748-09a angnes Sⴝ46 9/11/09 4:42 Art: TP201180 Input-mn © 2009 Lippincott Williams & Wilkins On the visit of His Holiness, John Paul II at the XVIII International Congress of the Transplantation Society, Rome, August 29, 2000, he said: “Here it can be said that the criterion (of death) adopted in more recent times for ascertaining the fact of death, namely the complete and irreversible cessation of all brain activity, if rigorously applied, does not seem to conflict with the essential elements of sound anthropology”. Judaism is especially interesting because it acknowledges that donation is permitted despite the fact that: “Under Judaic law removing organs from a human body after death conflicts with three rules: No benefit must be derived from a dead body; A dead body must not be mutilated; The body must be buried”. The reason for this being that “Saving lives is regarded as a Mitzvah (a religions commandment)”. The statement of the Holy Father Benedict XVI is published elsewhere in this supplement. All things considered, presumed consent seems better suited for deceased organ donation than informed consent. It offers a good way to initiate the discussion with the relatives of the deceased who are to honor the wishes of deceased. The question in the title of an article, “How presumed is presumed consent?” was answered; not very or not at all. “It is evident that, regardless of the law, be it opting in or opting out, presumed consent or presumed non consent, the family is almost always consulted. The family has the preferential right of interpretation. Their interpretation of the attitude towards organ donation by the deceased is usually not contested” (25). There May Be Alternatives to Informed and Presumed Consent for Deceased Organ and Tissue Donation Who should actually give the informed consent to, or use the option to veto, as in presumed consent, deceased organ donation. Who owns the dead body? Whose organs are they anyway? (26). Is it immoral to require consent for cadaver organ donation? Emson (27) believes so; “In my opinion any concept of property of the human body either during life or after death is biologically inaccurate and morally wrong” and “I believe that the right of control over the cadaver should be vested in the state as representative of those who may benefit from organ donation”. “In fact, the human being has only the usufruct of his body. The usufruct being the right to enjoy the use and the advantages of another’s property short of the destruction or waste of its substances” (26). After death, the substances making up our bodies will be given back to nature and recirculated in the eternal cycle after decomposition, cremation or donation of some organs and or tissues. As Mårten Werner (1918 – 1992), former chaplain to the King of Sweden, said: “To give a gift for life—through donation after my death—It would be a blessing”. Custodianship and Conditional Societal Appropriation Moore, the Chairman of the Department of Surgery at the Peter Bent Brigham hospital in Boston, where transplantation originated in the 1950s, saw already in the 1980s the end of voluntarism when it comes to deceased organ donation and asked “would our society accept some sort of statutory or mandated transfer of ownership of those organs from S121 the family to some social agency, such as the city, town, country or state?” (28). He suggested that the concept of ownership be replaced with the concept of custody and “once in the custody of that organ bank, the organ bank must discuss with the family (the recent custodians) what disposal they would like to make and, if possible, gain their voluntary assent (not consent) to donate”. Moore was far sighted in anticipating that it might be difficult to implement a system where the custodianship of the organs is taken over by an organ bank. Troug (29) suggests rightly, that in consent to organ donation, there is a need to balance conflicting ethical obligations. According to the amended Uniform Anatomical Gift Act (2006), physicians must continue the use of life-sustaining treatments for dying patients until the organ procurement organization (OPO) can determine whether the patient’s organs are suitable for transplants, even if the patient has an advance directive in place stating that such treatment is not wanted. Critical care physicians voiced their ethical concerns, and the Uniform Anatomical Gift Act was again amended in 2007 stating that the attending physician should consult with the patient or surrogate as early as possible to determine and follow the patients’ wishes, even if doing so resulted in the loss of transplantable organs. Of course, the informed consent process should, as Troug suggests, consist of a balanced discussion of the available options and counseling to help patients or their relatives to reach the choice that is best for them. According to Troug, further tensions remain because the OPO representative, the designated requestor and the clinicians face conflicting obligations. “The growing transplant waiting lists oblige us to strive to increase the supply of transplantable organs, but our commitments to respecting the rights of our patients and their families require the consent obtained by people who are, in turn committed to being fully transparent, fair and even-handed”. According to the comments in the same issue of The New England Journal of Medicine by Luskin and Delmonico, there is a confluence between the ethical commitments that Troug outlines: “that the desires of people who want to donate organs are respected and that the consent process is informed and voluntary” (30). The New England organ bank and other OPOs apply a consent process of dual advocacy. “By supporting the family’s right to make a choice that is based on complete information, including the positive impact that the gift will have on others and the solace derived from organ donation, dual advocacy recognizes that those requesting donation must also consider the needs of the donor family”. It is of the utmost importance who discusses organ donation with the relatives. In an interesting study where physicians of 25 deceased patients and 20 relatives were interviewed (31), half the physicians experienced conflicts regarding prerequisites of procuring organs and dealing with relatives. The physicians were characterized as being pro-donation, neutral or ambivalent based on their handling of the discussion on organ donation. The relatives felt that the neutrals were opposed to donation. Only physicians with a pro-donation approach received acceptance for donation. rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/ztr2748-09a angnes Sⴝ46 9/11/09 4:42 Art: TP201180 Input-mn S122 | www.transplantjournal.com Transplantation • Volume 88, Number 7S, October 15, 2009 Routine Recovery “Routine Recovery of Cadaveric Organs for Transplantation: Consistant, Fair, and Lifesaving” (32) is only the most recent of Aaron Spitals suggestions to improve deceased organ donation (33, 34). In 1996, he suggested that we give mandated choice for organ donation a try. “The plan would require all adults to record their wishes about posthumous organ donation and would consider those wishes binding” (33). He now suggests that “since many families deny organ recovery from recently deceased relatives”, another approach would be superior and “this is rarely discussed: routine recovery of all transplantable organs without consent”. But the families have to be involved and consulted because they will always have to be informed about the imminent or actual death of a close relative. They will have to be well cared for and they are the interpreters of the wishes of the deceased—the last will— but not themselves decision makers. Moreover, they are the only ones who can give the information necessary to evaluate the suitability of the potential donor. As a comment to the families not being themselves decision makers, reference is to Kreiss (35) and his suggestion for conditional societal appropriation. “Based on this concept, society may declare that after a person’s death, internal vital organs— but not the entire body— can be procured . . .. Conditional societal appropriation does not require anyone’s permission . . .. However in order to acknowledge the concept of autonomy . . . society . . . should accept individual, and not family refusal to donate”. Reciprocity is of course similar to the golden rule— one should do to others as he would have others do to him (Mt 7:12 and Lk 6:31). On a wider scale, society expects citizens to reciprocate and citizens expect society to handle matters respectfully and fairly. A Communitarian Approach Another approach to facilitate deceased organ donation is suggested by Amital Etzoni of the Kennedy institute of Ethics (36). It would be the communitarian approach: “. . . it seeks to make organ donation an act people engage in because they consider it their social responsibility, something a good person does, akin to volunteering”. Amital Etzoni takes exception to altruism as did Moore (vide ante). “It cannot be stressed enough that the reference here is not to altruism, which critics correctly point out often is an insufficient motive for action . . .. Rather reference is to making organ donation a part of one’s sense of moral obligation, something one cannot look in the mirror or face friends without having lived up to”. References Reciprocity Nadel and Nadel (37) contend “that a reciprocity policy could dramatically increase donations and thereby decrease associated deaths”. Under the policy, those who committed to donate organs would be granted preference in the event that they later required a transplant. The authors suggest that the individuals would continue to record their commitments in a manner they currently do or in registries and would receive preferential treatment should they need a transplant. The authors see some problems: most people are not sufficiently motivated to commit to donate, some are apathetic or reluctant to contemplate their own mortality and still others prefer to be buried intact for personal or religious reasons (although all major religions permit, if not encourage, life-enhancing donations). Final Remarks With due respect for the transplant acts, be it informed or presumed consent or any combination of these principles, would any or all of those other alternatives for deceased organ donation discussed earlier create a society where donation is the norm? No doubt some conditions have to be met for everyone to unconditionally accept to be a donor after death: medical professionals must proceed in a manner compatible with respect for the dead person’s dignity, allocation of organs and tissues must be fair and ethical. Moreover, commercialism is not acceptable. The ethics of organ allocation were discussed in a session of this meeting. Unfortunately, transplantation is not yet free from trafficking and commercialism. It is a challenge for the transplantation community to live upto the legitimate claims we can insist on to accept donation on the day we die. It can be argued that at the present time, the emphasis is on the autonomy and the interests of the individual to decide for himself on deceased organ donation at the expense of the common good. Organ and tissue donation is in the best interests of the donors, of those who are left behind and of those who need a transplant. 1. 2. 3. 4. 5. 6. 7. 8. 9. 10. 11. 12. 13. 14. 15. Gevers S, Janssen A, and Friele R. Consent systems for post mortem organ donation in Europe. Eur J Health Law 2004; 11: 175. Meeting the organ Shortage. Available at: http://www.coe.int/t/dg3/ health/Source/organshortage_en.doc. Accessed November 2008. Merion RM. How informed is informed consent? Transplant Proc 1996; 28: 24. Erin CA, Harris J. Presumed consent or contracting out. J Med Ethics 1999; 25: 365. Convention on the Rights of the Child. Available at: http:// www2.ohchr.org/english/law/crc.htm. Accessed November 2008. Linus Broström. The Substituted Judgment Standard Studies on the Ethics of Surrogate Decision Making. Thesis. Faculty of Medicine, Lund University 2007. Neill C. Manson, Onora O‘Neill. Rethinking informed consent in bioethics. NY, Cambridge University Press 2007. Valapour M. The live organ donor’s consent: Is it informed and voluntary? Transplant Rev (Orlando) 2008; 22: 196. Parekh AM, Gordon EJ, Garg AX, et al. Living kidney donor informed consent practices vary between US and non-US centres. Nephrol Dial Transplant 2008; 23: 3316. Barr ML, Belghiti J, Villamil G, et al. A report of the Vancover Forum on the care of the live organ donor: lung, liver, pancreas, and intestine data and medical guidelines. Transplantation 2006; 81: 1373. Pruett TL, Tibell A, Alabdulmajeed A, et al.The ethics statement of the Vancover Forum on the live lung, liver, pancreas, and intestine donor. Transplantation 2006; 81: 1386. Ethics Committee of the Transplantation Society. The consensus statement of the Amsterdam Forum on the Care of the Live Kidney Donor. Transplantation 2004; 78: 491. Sells RA. Informed consent from recipients of marginal donor organs. Transplant Proc 1999; 31: 1324. Panico M, Solomon M, and Burrows L. Issues of informed consent and access to extended donor pool kidneys. Transplant Proc 1997; 29: 3667. Feest TG, Riad HN, Collins CH, et al. Elective ventilation of potential organ donors. Lancet 1990; 335: 1133. rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/ztr2748-09a angnes Sⴝ46 9/11/09 4:43 Art: TP201180 Input-mn © 2009 Lippincott Williams & Wilkins 16. 17. 18. 19. 20. 21. 22. 23. 24. 25. 26. 27. 28. 29. 30. 31. 32. 33. 34. 35. 36. 37. Riad H, Nicholls A. An Ethical debate: Elective ventilation of potential organ donors. BMJ 1995; 310: 714. Europeans and organ donation Fieldwork October–November 2006 Publication May 2007 Special Eurobarometer 272D/Wave 66.2—TNS Opinion & Social. Gäbel H. Organ donor registers. Curr opinion Organ Transplantation 2006; 11: 187. Woien S, Rady MY, Verheide JL, et al. Organ procurement organizations internet enrollment for organ donation: Abandoning informed consent. BMC Med Ethics 2006; 7: 14. Editorial. Presumed consent for organ donation—Is an ethical and effective way of dealing with organ donation shortages. BMJ 2008; 336: 230. English V. Is presumed consent the answer to organ shortages? Yes. BMJ 2007; 334: 1088. Wright L. Is presumed consent the answer to organ shortages? No. BMJ 2007; 334: 1089. Yadav S. Lords committee comes down against presumed consent for organ donation. BMJ 2008; 337: a698. Transplants Co-ordinated by Sir Peter Morris Council of Europe Publishing 2003 General SANCO and coordinated by Directorate General Communication. Gäbel H. How presumed is presumed consent? Transplant proc 1996; 28: 27. Kreiss HM. Whose organs are they, anyway? Proceedings of a conference, 2007. Emson HE. It is immoral to require consent for cadaver organ donation. J Med Ethics 2003; 29: 125. Moore FD. Three ethical revolutions: Ancient assumptions remodelled under the pressure of transplantation. Transplant Proc 1988; 20(supp 1): 1061. Troug RD. Consent for organ donation—Balancing conflicting ethical obligations. N Engl J Med 2008; 358: 1209. Luskin R, Glazier A, Delmonico F. Organ donation and dual advocacy. N Engl J Med 2008; 358: 1297. Sanner MA. Two perspectives on organ donation: Experiences of potential donor families and intensive care physicians of the same event. J Crit Care 2007; 22: 296. Spital A, Taylor JS. Routine recovery of cadaveric organs for transplantation: Consistent, fair, and lifesaving. Clin J Am Soc Nephrol 2007; 2: 300. Spital A. Mandated choice for organ donation. Time to give it a try. Ann Intern Med 1996; 125: 66. Spital A, Erin CA. Conscription of cadaveric organs for transplantation: Let’s at least talk about. Am J Kidney Dis 2002; 39: 611. Kreiss HM. The question of organ procurement: Beyond charity. Nephrol Dial Transpl 2005; 20: 1303. Etzioni A. Organ donation: A communitarian approach. Kennedy Inst Ethics J 2003; 13: 1. Nadel MS, Nadel CA.Using reciprocity to motivate organ donations. Yale J Health Policy Law Ethics 2005; 5: 293. THE CONCEPT OF DEATH AND ORGAN DONATION Francis L. Delmonico definition of death was established in the United States in 1980 by the National Conference of Commissioners on Uniform State Laws that formulated the Uniform Determination of Death Act (UDDA) (1). The UDDA states that “An individual who has sustained either irreversible cessation of circulatory and respiratory functions, or irreversible cessation of all functions of the entire brain, including the brain stem is dead”. This definition was approved by the American Medical Association in 1980 and by the American Bar Association in 1981 (2). Today, all 50 states and the District of Columbia follow the UDDA as a legal and medical standard of death. The UDDA criteria for brain death assesses the function of the entire brain; both the cerebral and brainstem. The conceptual significance of assessing the brainstem function is A The author declares no conflict of interest. S123 to assure that an individual breathing spontaneously is not declared dead. In the definition of irreversible coma by the Ad Hoc Harvard Committee in 1968, the concept included an absence of spontaneous respiration (3). My personal interest in this topic dates to a period of my medical school education that culminated in a project analyzing the opinion of physicians regarding the concept of death (4). At the time, the concept of death was in transition and controversial, but there was a clear leadership from individuals, such as pioneering transplant surgeon, Dr. David Hume. Dr. Hume wrote: “there is only one definition of death; irreversible brain damage. Cessation of heart beat does not constitute death unless it has caused irreversible brain damage; (and) to diagnose irreversible brain damage there must be no spontaneous respirations” (personal communication). These observations were later corroborated by Dr. William Sweet in the New England Journal of Medicine when he wrote: “it is clear that a person is not dead unless his brain is dead. The time-honored criteria of stoppage of the heartbeat in circulation are indicative of death only when they persist long enough for the brain to die” (5). More recently, Shemie (6) has clarified the paradigm for donation and death by emphasizing a required absence of circulation (as stipulated by the UDDA; and thus, not just heartbeat) by underscoring the vital function of the brain as a criterion of life. “Where extracorporeal machines or transplantation can support or replace the function of organs such as the heart, lung, liver or kidney, the brain is the only organ that cannot be supported or replaced by medical technology” (6). Challenging the Concept of Death as Determined by Evaluating Neurologic Function Byrne et al (7) have rejected brain death as constituting death contending that “cessation of the entire brain function, whether irreversible or not, is not necessarily linked to total destruction of the brain or the death of the person”. Byrne evidently thinks of death in terms of a disintegration and “destruction of the unity of a single organism”; and philosophically constituting a separation of the soul from the body. Philosophical contentions, however, do not address legal, medical, ethical and practical necessities. No one knows when the soul separates from the body, but a precise time of death must be specified for obvious legal, medical and social reasons, for example, so that proper disposition of the body with burial and estate and property transfer, etc, can be exercised (6). In an intensive care unit setting, it becomes unethical to impose futile clinical treatments to a comatose individual, if the function of the entire brain is irreversibly lost. Treatment can be concluded, because there is no obligation or responsibility to provide useless resuscitative or supportive technology. What is the practical alternative? For many years, Truog (8) has also objected to the determination of death by neurologic evaluation (and by circulatory function). He has recently written in the New England Journal of Medicine that “arguments about why these patients should be considered dead have never been fully convincing. The definition of brain death requires a complete absence of all functions of the entire brain yet many of these patients retaining essential neurologic function, such as regulated secretion of hypothalamic hormones” (9). The rebuttal to this rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/ztr2748-09a angnes Sⴝ46 9/11/09 4:43 Art: TP201180 Input-mn S124 | www.transplantjournal.com assertion has been given by Shemie (personal communication): “the release of antidiuretic hormone from the hypothalamus is not considered to be essential neurologic function; rather, neurologic function is determined by an absence of consciousness, receptivity and responsiveness, spontaneous movement, spontaneous breathing and an absence of brainstem reflexes”. Brain death does not require every brain cell to be nonviable. The Ad Hoc Harvard committee convened by Dr. Beecher was confronted by patients with a clinical condition that fulfilled the criteria of an irreversible loss of neurologic function but could be interminably supported by a mechanical respirator. For Truog (and Shewmon [10]), however, these patients are not considered dead, because they can be supported indefinitely beyond the acute phase of their illness. It is well known, however, that despite the irreversible loss of brain function, the remainder of the body can be maintained by mechanical support; for example, even by patients who become brain-dead during pregnancy yet successfully have their fetuses brought to term. The clinical condition still constitutes the death of the mother and a viable fetus by continued mechanical support until birth (6). Challenging the Concept of Death as Determined by an Absence of Circulation Again in the New England Journal of Medicine, Truog and Miller (9) and Veatch (11) assert that donation after cardiac death (DCD) is not acceptable; that is, the recovery of organs after the determination of death by circulatory and respiratory criteria. Troug suggests that the recovery of the heart after DCD is “paradoxical”, because “the heart of patients who have been declared dead on the basis of the irreversible loss of cardiac function have in fact been transplanted and successfully functioned in the chest of another”. Veatch is similarly not convinced that the donor is dead: “if someone is pronounced dead on the basis of irreversible loss of heart function, after all, it would not be possible for heart function to be restored in another body” (11). Both Veatch and Troug misinterpret the UDDA, which, precisely stated, applies to an individual who has sustained irreversible cessation of circulatory and respiratory functions. It is not a matter of the cessation of heartbeat or heart function but an irreversible cessation of circulation in the donor. The consequence of the absence of circulation is based on the function of the brain. An irreversible loss of blood flow (circulation) to the brain results in an irreversible loss of neurologic function; the UDDA definition of death. Bernat (12) has written, in the same New England Journal group of articles, that circulation, not heartbeat, is the critical function that must be lost using circulatory-respiratory tests to determine death. Patients are not declared dead when on heart-lung machines during cardiac surgery, on extracorporeal machine oxygenation (ECMO) awaiting heart transplantation (even if they never receive a heart), or carrying artificial hearts because, despite an absence of heartbeat, circulation is continuously maintained. Regarding donation after cardiac death or nonheart-beating donation, “whether the asystolic heart is subsequently left alone, removed and not restarted, or removed and restarted in another patient is irrelevant to the circulatory status of the just-declared dead patient” (12). Transplantation • Volume 88, Number 7S, October 15, 2009 Defining Cessation and Irreversibility For the determination of death by the irreversible cessation of circulatory and respiratory functions in a controlled setting of organ donation (that is after the withdrawal of futile treatment-controlled DCD in the hospital setting), cessation and irreversibility should be defined. Cessation is recognized by clinical examination that detects the absence of responsiveness, heart sounds, pulse and respiratory effort (13). The medical circumstances of DCD may require the use of confirmatory object of tests, such as electronic monitoring or an absence of pulse pressure as determined from an arterial catheter. Bernat et al. (13) has introduced the concept of permanency to confirm irreversibility with the following formulation: an “irreversible” loss of function means that the function cannot be restored by any known technology. “Irreversible is an absolute condition that implies impossibility (with currently available technology) and does not rely on intent or action. In contrast, a permanent loss of function means that the function will not be restored, because it will neither return spontaneously, nor will it return as a result of medical intervention because physicians have decided not to attempt resuscitation. “Permanent” is a contingent condition that admits possibility and relies on intent and action. The two conditions are causally related. All functions that are irreversibly lost are also permanently lost (but not vice versa) and in DCD death determinations, functions that are lost permanently, quickly and inevitably become lost irreversibly” (13). The National Conference on Donation after Cardiac Death accepted this formulation that the irreversible loss of circulation is confirmed by the observation that circulation will not resume spontaneously and circulation will not be restored on medically and ethically justifiable grounds. Irreversibility is recognized by persistent (permanent) cessation of functions during an appropriate period of observation (13). The Duration of an Absence of Circulation The Institute of Medicine recommend a period of 5 min in witnessing the cessation of circulation by the patient care team—independent of the organ recovery or transplant team— before the patient is declared dead (14). The National Conference on Donation after Cardiac Death subsequently accepted a recommendation by the Society of Critical Care Medicine to wait at least 2 min (and at most 5 min) after the initial observation of asystole (13, 15). In an adult, there has been no experience of the resumption of circulation in a DCD circumstance after 2 min. The reason to wait at least 2 to 5 min is to attest to the irreversibility of the absence of circulation (and the consequences of that permanent absence of circulation on the function of the brain). The reason not to wait longer is to enable recovery of organs with an expectation that the organs could function successfully after transplantation. It should be noted, however, that with withdrawal of futile treatment regularly being done in the intensive care units preceding death, data could be prospectively collected to determine the period in which the absence of spontaneous resumption of circulation prevailed. The Denver Protocol Boucek et al. has presented four cases of the recovery and transplantation of hearts from infants: “when cardiocir- rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/ztr2748-09a angnes Sⴝ46 9/11/09 4:43 Art: TP201180 Input-mn S125 © 2009 Lippincott Williams & Wilkins culatory function ceased, the first patient was observed for 3 min before death was declared and the organ-donation process initiated. On the basis of recommendations of the ethics committee, for the other two donors the observation period was shortened to 1.25 min” (16). Bernat (12) has criticized this approach: “What minimum duration of asystole ensures that autoresuscitation will not occur is an empirical question that can be answered conclusively only after observing many hundreds of patients”. The Use of Extracorporeal Machine Oxygenation Protocols administering ECMO to the donor after the determination of cardiac death have become controversial. Bernat (12) has written in the companion article in the New England Journal of Medicine specifically addressing the issue of ECMO. He notes: “If ECMO adequately provided circulation and oxygenation to the donor’s entire body, it would retroactively negate the death determination by preventing the loss of circulation and respiration from becoming permanent or irreversible, potentially “reanimating” the heart and preventing the progression to brain destruction on which the circulatory criterion of death is predicated” (12). These protocols attempt to circumvent heart reanimation or resumption of brain circulation by the placement of a catheter in the diaphragmatic aorta. In those instances in which heart recovery may be intended after DCD, ligation of the carotid arteries has been considered. Restoring circulation by ECMO after the declaration of death by a reversible cessation of circulation is contradictory to the death declaration. To accomplish a declaration of death by an absence of neurologic function in this setting by either the insertion of a balloon catheter in the thoracic aorta or the ligation of the carotid artery is unacceptable, because it becomes the active causation of an absence of neurologic function. If that approach was to be ethically permissible, why not ligate the carotid artery antecedent of the absence of circulation? The Use of Heparin in DCD Protocols The administration of heparin at the time of the withdrawal of life sustaining treatment is the current standard of care and a key component of DCD best practice. The longterm survival of the transplanted organ may be at risk if thrombi impede circulation to the organ after reperfusion. The omission of heparin could negatively impact organ recovery and hinder the acceptance of recovered organs for transplantation. The use of heparin has been considered controversial on the basis of theoretical concerns that it may hasten the death of the donor (17). There is no evidence that heparin would cause sufficient bleeding after the withdrawal of treatment to be the cause of death. Although heparin may prevent clotting in a patient who is actively bleeding, it is unlikely to cause bleeding in a head-injured patient who is not actively bleeding. It should not be overlooked that the event of demise is the withdrawal of life support that affects the loss of circulation and respiration (and not the use of the heparin). Finally, the principle of double effect asserts that an action that produces a good effect and a bad effect might be permissible if the good effect is intended and the bad effect is merely foreseen but unintended. The Dead Donor Rule and Organ Donation Robertson (18) wrote more than a decade ago that the retrieval of organs for transplantation should not cause the death of a donor. This rule has since been the ethical axiom of organ donation, thus, no organ recovery should precede the declaration of death. Despite the contentions of Truog and Miller (9), there is no support within the organ donation community to rescind the dead donor rule. The public trust in organ donation hinges on a trust that medical professionals will prioritize the care of the dying patient over any other objective, however noble or good. One could readily anticipate a societal skepticism if medical professionals present the following approach to the family of a dying patient (as prescribed by Troug): “your family member has a devastating neurologic injury but is not dead. If you consent to the removal of organs now before the determination of death, it will result in the death of your family member and it would enhance the possibility of successful transplantation of organs”. The rejection of that scenario is evident in the recent trial of a transplant surgeon that was accused of hastening the death of an individual in the recovery of organs (19). Church Position In the address of John Paul II to the Transplantation Congress in Rome, 2000, he noted: “. . . it is helpful to recall that the death of the person is a single event, consisting in the total disintegration of that unitary and integrated whole that is the personal self. It is a well-known fact that for some time certain scientific approaches to ascertaining death have shifted the emphasis from the traditional cardiorespiratory signs to the so-called neurological criterion. Specifically, this consists in establishing, according to clearly determined parameters commonly held by the international scientific community, the complete and irreversible cessation of all brain activity (in the cerebrum, cerebellum and brain stem). This is then considered the sign that the individual organism has lost its integrative capacity” (20). For those who are involved in the transplantation of organs from the deceased, this Papal testimony is reassuring of a moral propriety that can be defended medically—the valid concept of death by neurologic criteria (21). References 1. 2. 3. 4. 5. 6. 7. 8. Uniform Determination of Death Act. 12 Uniform Laws Annotated 320. 1990 Supp. President’s Commission for the Study of Ethical Problems in Medicine and Biomedical and Behavioral Research, Defining Death: A Report on the Medical, Legal and Ethical Issues in the Determination of Death. Washington: Government Printing Office 1981, pp 73. Ad Hoc Committee. A definition of irreversible coma: Report of the Ad Hoc Committee of the Harvard MedicalSchool to Examine the Definition of Brain Death. JAMA 1968; 205: 337. Delmonico FL, Randolph JG. Death: A concept in transition. Pediatrics 1973; 51: 234. Sweet W. Brain death. N Engl J Med 1978; 299: 410. Shemie SD. Clarifying the paradigm for the ethics of donation and transplantation: Was ‘dead’ really so clear before organ donation? Philos Ethics Humanit Med 2007; 24: 18. Byrne PA, O’Reilly S, Quay PM. Brain death–An opposing viewpoint. JAMA 1979; 2242: 1985. Truog RD. Is it time to abandon brain death? Hastings Cent Rep 1997; 27: 29. rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/ztr2748-09a angnes Sⴝ46 9/11/09 4:43 Art: TP201180 Input-mn S126 | 9. 10. 11. 12. 13. 14. www.transplantjournal.com Truog RD, Miller FG. The dead donor rule and organ transplantation. N Engl J Med 2008; 359: 674. Shewmon DA. Chronic “brain death”: Meta-analysis and conceptual consequences. Neurology 1998; 51: 1538. Veatch RM. Donating hearts after cardiac death—Reversing the irreversible. N Engl J Med 2008; 359: 672. Bernat JL. The boundaries of organ donation after circulatory death. N Engl J Med 2008; 359: 669. Bernat JL, D’Alessandro AM, Port FK. Report of a national conference on donation after cardiac death. Am J Transplant 2006; 6: 281. Ethics Committee, American College of Critical Care Medicine; Society of Critical Care Medicine. Recommendations for nonheartbeating organ donation. A position paper by the Ethics Committee, American College of Critical Care Medicine, Society of Critical Care Medicine. Crit Care Med 2001; 29: 1826. Transplantation • Volume 88, Number 7S, October 15, 2009 15. 16. 17. 18. 19. 20. 21. Institute of Medicine, National Academy of Sciences. Nonheart-beating organ transplantation: Medical and ethical issues in procurement. Washington, DC, National Academy Press 1997. Boucek MM, Mashburn C, Dunn SM, et al; Denver Children’s Pediatric Heart Transplant Team. Pediatric heart transplantation after declaration of cardiocirculatory death. N Engl J Med 2008; 359: 709. DuBois JM, Delmonico FL, D’Alessandro AM. When organ donors are still patients: Is premortem use of heparin ethically acceptable? Am J Crit Care 2007; 4: 396. Robertson J. The dead donor rule. Hastings Center Rep 1999; 29: 6. Doctor Cleared of Harming Man to Obtain Organs Jesse McKinley. New York Times, San Francisco, December 18, 2008. http://www.cin.org/pope/organ-transplant-cloning.html. Delmonico FL, Murray JE. A medical defense of brain death. Ethics Medics 1999; 24: 1. Current Considerations in Organ Transplantation and Organ Donation HISTORICAL DEVELOPMENT, REGULATION, RESULTS, AVAILABILITY, AND ACCESS Ferdinand Muehlbacher Regulation, Results, Availability, and Access It all began with the dream of mankind to be able to replace deceased organs to prolong life or quality of life. According to a legend, the saints Cosmas and Damian transplanted the leg of a black donor to a male recipient who had lost his leg. Today, this would be a “Composite Tissue Transplantation”. In reality, however, the first successful kidney transplantation in an autologous setting was carried out by Ullmann (1) in 1902, when he took a kidney out of a dog and transplanted it to the neck of the same animal. He was able to demonstrate that a kidney that was removed, flushed and transplanted to another site in the same animal was able to produce urine. He did not observe any immunologic reactions because the system was autologous. Carrel (2) developed vascular surgical techniques, which were fundamental for both vascular and transplantation surgery. He was awarded the Nobel Prize in 1912 for his pioneering work in vascular surgery. During the following years, many attempts were made to transplant kidneys to uremic patients. The donors were in most cases animals and the transplantation site was usually the cupidal area on the upper arm. All these transplantations failed immediately and doctors had no explanation for these acute rejections. In parallel, Landsteiner (3) described the agglutination reaction in human blood, which led to the discovery of the A-B-O blood system, which is still a basic principle in current organ transplantation. Landsteiner was awarded the Nobel Prize for his discovery of the A-B-O blood system in 1930. The real explanation for the failure of all the early kidney transplantations came from Gibson and Medawar (4), who described the immunologic nature of skin rejection in 1943. The same group published a landmark article in 1953 (5), a protocol which created specific tolerance by creating The author declares no conflict of interest. chimerism (6), a system which is still followed today to create donor-specific tolerance (7, 8). Transplant surgeons who were aware of the immunologic nature of rejection did not have a strategy to prevent rejection, but they nevertheless tried to develop a feasible transplantation site for kidney transplantation. David Hume transplanted kidneys in the subcutaneous region of the thigh, whereas René Küss, a urologist from Paris, designed the operation technique, which is used in most kidney transplantations today: the iliac fossa of the recipient. In addition, Küss tried to lessen rejection by selecting a biologically related donor-recipient combination: a mother donated one of her kidneys to her 17-year-old son. Despite this close relationship (haploidentical), the transplant failed several weeks after transplantation and the patient died (9). A total circumvention of the immunologic barrier was achieved in a transplantation between identical twins on December 23, 1954, by John Merrill and Joseph E. Murray at the Peter Bent Brigham Hospital in Boston. Strategies to overcome the immunologic barrier are as follows: • Special donor-recipient constellations • Identical twins • Human leukocyte antigen (HLA) matching • Immunosuppression • Radiation • Chemical • Biologicals • Tolerance induction A further strategy to prevent immunologic rejection became possible because of the discovery of the HLA system by Dausset, Jon Van Rood and Bernard Amos, and in consequence the selection of the best possible donor-recipient combination. This led to “HLA matching”, a concept which has been confirmed by thousands of patients to date and is still valid as an allocation principle (10). Joseph Murray, the surgeon who performed the first successful kidney transplantation in identical twins, investigated the feasibility of total body irradiation (TBI). His colleague, John A. Mannick, was the first to demonstrate long-term survival in renal transplantation in dogs after rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/ztr2748-09a angnes Sⴝ46 9/11/09 4:43 Art: TP201180 Input-mn © 2009 Lippincott Williams & Wilkins TBI and methotrexate, an agent used in the treatment of cancer (11). Küss and Jean Hamburger competed with Murray and Merill in Boston, step-by-step, from identical twin transplantation to non-related transplantation with various body irradiation protocols (e.g. TBI). Calne (12) was the first to develop a drug called 6-mercaptopurine as a successor of methotrexate. In parallel, Thomas Starzl and coworkers (13), in Denver, applied steroids for rejection treatment and thus had a protocol in hand, which enabled him to achieve longterm graft survival in a few cases. With the same immunosuppressive method, liver transplantation was developed by Starzl in Denver, Colorado in 1963 and by Sir Roy Calne in Cambridge, England in 1968. Calne was one of the first to develop a derivative of 6-mercaptopurine, azathioprine, in the clinical setting, which along with steroids became the standard immunosuppression in the 1970s. Henry Bismuth in Paris and Rudolph Pichlmayr in Hannover were also pioneers in the development of liver transplantation on the European continent, but they all suffered from a low-level immunosuppressive drug regimen. The first long-term survivers of liver transplantation were observed in Denver, Colorado, when Thomas Starzl turned to pediatric liver transplantation, enabling several children who had previously suffered from biliary atresia to survive for more than a year. Heart transplantation was pioneered by Norman Schumway and Richard Lower in the 60s. The first clinical heart transplantation was performed on December 3, 1967, by Christian Barnard in Capetown, South Africa (14). First Regulatory Attempts As early as 1978, the European Council issued the resolution (78/29), which was adopted by the Committee of Ministers of the Council of Europe on May 11, 1978, as well as an explanatory memorandum. In this resolution, the European Council laid down basic rules of organ transplantation and organ donation and proposed to adopt a presumed consent regulation, which was finally introduced to national legislation in 13 member states of the European Council. In 1978, Borel (15), from the research laboratories at Sandoz in Basel, Switzerland, discovered the immunosuppressive properties of cyclosporine A, which was then developed for clinical use by Calne and coworkers and became available in 1983 for clinical use for all organ transplantations. The availability of this new drug led—along with several other cofounding factors—to an explosive development of liver transplantation. Many transplantation centers developed rapidly. In Europe, the number of transplantations increased from a few hundred to 5000 per year within the next 20 years. But it became clear that there was a limitation to this development because organ availability was limited. Living donation in liver transplantation was developed first by Broelsch (16) in Chicago, but most of the experience in living donor liver transplantation was made in Japan in the following years, due to the lack of deceased donors for cultural reasons. S127 Current Standard With the available techniques for kidney, liver, heart, lung and pancreas transplantation and with immunosuppressive agents of the calcineurin inhibitor type, such as cyclosporine A and tacrolimus, solid organ transplantation became a standard all over the world. In 2006, 96,828 solid organ transplants were carried out in 93 countries of the world; of which, 65,511 kidney transplantations, 20,366 liver transplantations, 5313 heart transplantations, 3051 lung transplantations and 2559 pancreas transplantations are recorded and published in the Transplant Newsletter (17). Transplantation in Europe developed according to the diverse health care systems of the countries involved. Ways of gaining donor consent, procurement logistics, tasks and performance of transplant coordinators, financing system and, of course, the legal framework in the various countries, differ greatly. Despite all the diversity, a substantial amount of organs are procured in the European countries, however, with greatly varying degrees of success. The top runner in the last 20 years is Spain with 34 donors per million inhabitants; the lowest donor rate is found in Romania and Bulgaria at 1.7 and 1.3 donors per million, respectively. There is much work ahead of us, if we are to improve organ donation in these new member states of the European Union. The Effect of Modern Transplantation Medicine Survival The top runners in patient survival are recipients of live-donor kidneys, with 95% of the organs surviving for at least 1 year and 90% for 5 years. Heart and liver recipients have survival rates of 82% for 1 year and 70% for 5 years, respectively. Lung recipients show similar results at 1 year, but only 55% for 5 years. This number will improve in the near future because lung transplantation is the “youngest branch” of organ transplantation and there is still a learning curve to account for (18) (Fig. 1). Comparing survival rates of patients on dialysis with the normal population shows a 30% to 40% chance of survival, dependant on age. Kidney transplantation raises the rate of patient survival immediately to 60%, in higher ages to 70%. It is important to note that not even successful renal F1 C O L O R FIGURE 1. Percentage of graft survival throughout the years (1985–2006). rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/ztr2748-09a angnes Sⴝ46 9/11/09 4:43 Art: TP201180 Input-mn S128 | www.transplantjournal.com transplantation can normalize survival chances in the population suffering from end-stage renal disease (19). The transplant operation itself increases the risk of death by a factor of 2.84. The risk breaking-even point is at 106 days, and in the long term the risk of death compared with patients on dialysis is reduced to 32% (20). Similar observations were made in a cohort of heart transplant recipients who were compared with stable heart failure patients, in which the operative risk reduces the survival rate within the first 3 years to 80%. But in the long term, after 10 years, the survival rate of patients with successful heart transplantations is in the order of 70% versus 47% in stable heart failure patients. Quality of Life As for quality of life, patients on dialysis are kept alive, but many of them suffer from dietary restrictions, fluid intake restrictions, deterioration due to comorbidities, such as vascular diseases, and sometimes hemodynamic effects around the dialysis procedure. Kidney transplantation returns them to an almost normal life. A quality of life survey carried out in heart transplant recipients shows that the physical complaints encountered preoperatively almost disappear in the course of the following 10 years. A similar observation can be made with psychologic and emotional complaints, which improve dramatically after heart transplantation (21). The improvement in the quality of life is best seen in daily clinical practice (22). Is Transplantation Available to Everybody? With regards to kidney transplantation, the top running countries show a kidney transplant frequency between 40 and 55 per million per year for both deceased donor organs and live donor organs. In these countries, waiting time is in the range of 1 to 2 years, whereas in countries with transplant frequencies of only 35 per million per year, the average waiting time increases up to 6 years. With transplant rates in the order of 10 to 15 per million per year, waiting times become unacceptable, with many patients never receiving a kidney. In addition, renal transplantation is a highly efficient way of treating patients suffering from end-stage renal disease. In Austria, for instance, the number of patients suffering from kidney failure rose from 2500 in 1987 to 8000 in 2007. This increase is explained by the extended life expectancy in the general population, and, as a matter of fact, the higher numbers are due to patients beyond the age of 65 years. Almost 50% of this population have successfully undergone renal transplantation, whereas the number of patients on dialysis eligible and suitable for transplantation has remained constant at approximately 800 during the last 11 years. Patients on dialysis not suitable for transplantation have a very short life expectancy of only a few years. Death on the waiting list is an additional concern at the Vienna Transplantation Centre; 23% of patients awaiting liver transplantation die on the waiting list because of a lack of alternative treatment for chronic liver failure. Similarly, death on the waiting list in heart transplantation is approximately 15%, whereas death on the kidney waiting list is under 5%, because of the possibility of renal replacement therapy on dialysis. Transplantation • Volume 88, Number 7S, October 15, 2009 Is There Equal Access to Transplantation Treatment? Seven countries in Europe (Germany, Belgium, the Netherlands, Luxembourg, Austria, Slovenia and Croatia) are intensively cooperating in organ allocation in a foundation called Eurotransplant. These countries, with a combined population of 120 million inhabitants, maintain common waiting lists for organ allocation, with varying levels of organ exchange. For kidneys, all organs are distributed through the computer program in the Eurotransplant headquarters in Leiden, the Netherlands, whereas nonrenal organs are allocated either through a national waiting list or through agreed protocols within the center. However, the mandatory exchange of acutely needed organs all over the Eurotransplant area is served first, if an appropriate organ is available. This applies to combined transplantations, and in the case of kidney programs, also to highly immunized patients. There are, however, certain prerequisites to maintain this system, one of them being 100% of prospective donors reporting to the central office in Leiden. This office finally decides either on the level of the center or on that of the individual patient, who is to receive which available organ, according to agreed upon algorithms. Problems and Side Effects Organ transplantation is a full success story and there is a common saying that “organ transplantation is a victim of its own success”. With a high success rate, the demand increases and is only limited by organ availability. In addition, for the time being, all organ transplant patients need immunosuppressive medication in order to achieve pharmacological tolerance to avoid acute or chronic organ rejection. The available drugs effectively suppress rejection, however, they have severe side effects, which are in part harmful to the newly transplanted organ, or may otherwise affect other organ systems. Finally, they generally increase the risk of developing new malignant diseases. Recipients of heart or lung transplants have a 25% to 30% risk of developing a malignant tumor within 10 years. In liver and kidney recipients, the risk is in the order of 15%, in live donor kidney recipients 8%, probably reflecting the total amount of immunosuppressive agents consumed (18, 23). A possible way to avoid these side effects can be the development of true transplantation tolerance, a top priority project at many transplantation centers all over the world with— until now—mixed success, but with potential clinical application in the next 10 to 20 years. Summary Organ transplantation has been established as the standard treatment for end-stage organ failure within the last 40 years and has reached a high level of performance to improve life expectancy and quality of life. Current strategies yield acceptable results, but organ shortage and the pharmacological immunosuppression currently applied are still the major limitations of its success story, which started just 100 years ago. References 1. Ullmann E. Experimentelle Nierentransplantation. Wien Klin Wochenschr 1902; 15: 11. rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/ztr2748-09a angnes Sⴝ46 9/11/09 4:43 Art: TP201180 Input-mn S129 © 2009 Lippincott Williams & Wilkins 2. 3. 4. 5. 6. 7. 8. 9. 10. 11. 12. 13. Carrel A. The transplantation of organs. N Y Med J 1914; 99: 839. Landsteiner K. Über die Aggultinationserscheinungen normalen menschlichen Blutes. Wien Klin Wochenschr 1901; 14: 14. Gibson T, Medawar PB. The fate of skin homografts in man. J Anat 1943; 77: 299. Billingham RE, Brent L, Medawar PB. “actively acquired tolerance” of foreign cells. Nature 1953; 172: 603. Kingsley CI, Nadig SN, Wood KJ. Transplantation tolerance: Lessons from experimental rodent animals. Transpl Int 2007; 20: 828. Wekerle T, Kurtz J, Ito H, et al. Allogeneic bone marrow transplantation with co-stimulatory blockade induces macrochimerism and tolerance without cytoreductive host treatment. Nat Med 2000; 6: 464. Fehr T, Sykes M. Clinical experience with mixed chimerism to induce transplantation tolerance. Transpl Int 2008; 21: 1118. Küss R, Teinturuier J, Milliez P. Quelques essais de greffe de rien chez l’homme. Memoires de l’Academie Chirurgique 1951; 77: 755. Dausset J. Iso-leuco-anticorps. Acta Haematol 1958; 20: 156. Mannick JA, Lochte HL Jr, Ashley CA, et al. A functioning kidney homotransplant in the dog. Surgery 1959; 46: 821. Calne RY. The rejection of renal homografts. Inhibition in dogs by 6-mercaptopurine. Lancet 1960;1: 417. Marchioro TL, Axtell HK, Lavia MF, et al. The role of adrenocortical steroids in reversing etablished homograft rejection. Surgery 1964; 55: 412. 14. 15. 16. 17. 18. 19. 20. 21. 22. 23. Barnard C, et al. Human heart transplantation. S Afr Med J 1967: 1257. AQ: 26 Borel JF, Feurer C, Gubler HU, et al. Biological effects of cyclosporin a; a new antilymphocytic agent. Agent Actions 1976; 6: 468. Broelsch CE, Whittington PF, Emond JC, et al. Liver transplantation in children from living related donors. Surgical techniques and results. Annal Surg 1991; 214: 428. Transplant Newsletter vol. 13, Nr. 1. November 19, 2008. Collaborative Transplant Study. Available at: http://www.ctstransplant. org/. Kramar R, Oberbauer R. Österreichisches Dialyse und Transplantregister, ÖDTR, Jahresbericht 2007 der Österreichischen Gesellschaft für Nephrologie. Wolf RA, et al. N Engl J Med 1999: 1762. AQ: 27 Bunzel B, Laederach-Hofmann K, Grimm M. Survival, clinical data and quality of life 10 years after heart transplantation: A prospective study. Z Kardiol 2002; 91: 319. Kousoulas L, Neipp M, Berg-Hock H, et al. Health-related quality of life in adult transplant recipients more than 15 years after orthotopic liver transplantation. Transpl Int 2008; 21: 1052. Gaumann A, Schlitt HJ, Geissler EK. Immunosuppression and tumour development in organ transplant recipients: The emerging dualistic role of rapamycin. Transpl Int 2007; 21: 207. Legal Considerations of Organ Donation in Various Countries AUSTRIA Walter Schaupp A Presumed Consent Policy Deceased organ donation and transplantation has been regulated in Austria as part of the 1982 Federal Hospitals Act (1). First of all, it is important to notice that the respective sect. 62 refers to the “removal of organs and parts of organs” of deceased persons with the intention of transplantation. Questions of living donation, organ allocation or other possible use of cadaveric organs and tissues beyond transplantation are not covered by this law. In sect. 62, Austrian law prescribes a clear cut opting-out or presumed consent policy. The original German notion is “die enge Widerspruchslösung”, which literally means “narrow objection-solution”: every deceased person is a potential organ donor as long as he or she, or his or her legal representative, has not made a declaration at the time of living, explicitly refusing the use of his or her organs for transplantation. Family members do not have the right to object. (An “extended objection-solution” [“erweiterte Widerspruchslösung”] would extend the right to object to family members). Compared with the original draft, the existing version of sect. 62 represents a notable progress in strengthening the right of individuals to dispose of their own deceased body. The working group had proposed to allow organ removal without any restriction whenever this could “save the life” or “restore the health of another person”. Juridically, this would have represented a kind of “emergency regulation” (“Notstandsmodell”). The proposed formulation: “It is allowed to remove organs or parts of organs of deceased persons for transplantation, in order to save the life or to restore the health of another person”, has been amended by adding the clause “the The author declares no conflict of interest. retrieval is not allowed if there is a declaration at hand to the physicians by which the deceased person or, before his or her death, the legal representative, has expressly refused organ donation” (3). Other relevant topics of sect. 62 are as follows: determination of death by an independent physician, prohibition of commercialization, anonymity of donors and recipients, reference and respect for the human body and obligation for physicians and health institutions to consult the opting-out register before every planned explantation. Objection to Postmortem Organ Removal According to the Austrian law, a legally valid objection can be made in three ways: (1) Oral, for instance to relatives who later testify to the physician; (2) Written, for instance by a short written declaration of will, carried with the identification papers or enclosed within the clinical records; (3) Registration in the central opting-out register at the Austrian Federal Institute for Health Affairs (Österreichisches Bundesinstitut für Gesundheitswesen [ÖBIG]). Physicians are obliged by law to consult the central register before every planned explantation (sect. 62 e), but they will also respect any written statement at hand and any testified will of a deceased person. However, they are not obliged to search actively and extensively for a possible objection. The Opting-Out Register In 1995, a central nationwide opting-out register was established, which is currently maintained by the aforementioned Austrian Institute for Health Affairs (ÖBIG). To be recorded, one has to order a form, fill it in, sign and submit it back. The objection can be revoked at any time. For the time being, foreigners (non-residents) can also have their name recorded in the register. Collective registrations, however, are not accepted (4). Although the register had been imple- rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/ztr2748-09a angnes Sⴝ46 9/11/09 4:43 Art: TP201180 Input-mn S130 | www.transplantjournal.com mented in 1995, an explicit legal obligation for physicians and health institutions to consult the register had not been formulated before 2004 (4). Within 2007, 2087 persons have had their names recorded in the register; at the end of December 2007, there had been a total amount of 14,992 entries, 13,595 of them residents and 1397 non-residents. The residents registered amounted to 0.18% of the Austrian population (ÖBIGTransplant 2008, 29). By November 2008, the number of registrations had risen to 18,180, which accounts for 0.22% of the Austrian population. Special Donor Groups Minors In principle, there is no limitation of age with respect to organ removal. Newborns and minors (under the age of 16 years) are potential donors as long as their legal representative has not objected to donation. To be valid, such objection has to be made before the death of the child. At a practical level, however, there are two important age limits: for persons under the age of 14 years, legal representatives have full authority to object. Between the age of 14 and 16 years, a minor can recall the objection to donate made by his legal representative if he is psychologically competent; his personal objection would also be respected in the case of a missing objection from his legal representative (3). Non-residents Austrian Transplantation Law is implemented according to the principle of territoriality. This means that nonresidents, such as tourists from other countries, are regarded as potential organ donors. If they want to prevent the removal of their organs, they have to carry a written statement with them, which will be respected. As mentioned earlier, they also have the possibility to have their name entered in the central opting-out register. Other Limits to Organ Removal Respect for the Visible Integrity and Dignity of the Deceased Body If no objection has been made by the deceased donor, the law allows for the removal of “individual organs or parts of organs” only if the visible integrity and the dignity of the deceased body is not violated: “the removal must not result in a deformation of the body which violates the respect for the dead body” (sect. 62 a-1). According to the current legal interpretation, this clause is consonant with the explantation of individual organs, with multiorgan-donation and with the removal of tissues for transplantation (skin, heart valves and corneas). As the annotations to sect. 62 a-1 suggest, in cases of doubt, considerations regarding the life and the health of the potential recipients should prevail. A point of discussion has considered whether the removal of body parts such as hands are also covered by the presumed consent policy. Some are of the opinion that if the visible integrity of the body is severely distorted, consent of the relatives (or of the deceased person) should be guaranteed. Other Purposes than Transplantation The use of procured organs for other purposes than transplantation such as research or pharmaceutical interests, Transplantation • Volume 88, Number 7S, October 15, 2009 is not allowed under the presumed consent policy of sect. 62 a. Organs that are removed but then discarded have to be buried. Acting against this policy would constitute an infringement of sect. 190 of the Austrian Criminal Law (“Disturbing the peace of the dead”). There is a similar problem with respect to the usage of organs retrieved in the course of a routine postmortem autopsy. In contrast to a more liberal attitude in the past, legal consensus is growing that any usage of such organs beyond diagnostic purposes would require the explicit consent of the deceased person or, at least, of family members (3). Living Donation At the present time, there is no explicit legislation on living donation. The legal assessment follows common principles of positive Civil and Criminal Law. First, the retrieval of an organ from a living person, according to sect. 90, Crimincal Law (2), constitutes a severe act of bodily injury. Therefore, personal and informed consent is mandatory in each case of living donation. Exceptions are tolerated only in the case of minimal bodily interventions, such as the donation of bone marrow by a minor sibling. The intervention must not be “contra bonos mores”, which in this context means that no vital organs must be removed irrespective of a given consent. There is no restriction of living donation to genetically or emotionally related persons as in German law. Non-related donation and exchanged donation are allowed and practiced (3). Communication With Family Members in Cadaveric Donation As we have seen, Austrian Law does not oblige physicians to inform the family members of a deceased donor and it would also allow organ removal if the family members object to the procedure. Acting according to these principles, however, has shown to be counterproductive for transplantation medicine. In some cases, it has deeply offended the feelings of family members and provoked reactions in the public sphere. As a consequence, ÖBIG-Transplant (Austrian Federal Institute for Health Affairs, Department of Transplantation) released internal guidelines, some years ago (5), which among others, wanted to harmonize diverging policies and attitudes within the transplantation community with respect to the problem of how to deal with family members in the course of deceased organ donation. The main concerns of these guidelines are: (1) If family members are present, they should be informed and should be brought to accept the donation procedure; (2) If they are informed but continue to object, no explantation should take place; (3) In the case of a child or a non-resident, extreme caution is recommended and organs should only be removed in accordance with family members (5). This policy will probably result in a slight decrease in the organ donation rate (about 10%) (Ferdinand Muehlbacher, Vienna, personal communication, November 2008). On the other hand, it will surely strengthen and promote public trust in transplantation medicine. Discussion One could doubt if the Austrian model takes the idea of a basic societal consent to routine organ donation seriously enough. The right to presume such a basic consent requires certain standards of public awareness of the problem, rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/ztr2748-09a angnes Sⴝ46 9/11/09 4:43 Art: TP201180 Input-mn © 2009 Lippincott Williams & Wilkins discussions, deliberation processes and information about the possibilities to object to donation. Many Austrian citizens are neither aware of the possibility to object nor of the way of how to object. The law does not require concrete efforts of public information and education. The low percentage of registrations in the opting-out register certainly reflects this situation and cannot be interpreted exclusively as a result of a high rate of reflected positive judgements on organ donation. Conversely, this situation is outweighed, to a certain extent, by high transplantation rates. Moreover, the experience of the author as a university teacher shows that students, when informed about the legal and medical aspects of organ transplantation in Austria, would typically wonder about the fact that they have not been confronted with the problem earlier, but they would not oppose the Austrian solution in principle. Discussion of the concept of brain death for instance is much more sensible and regularly provokes deeper controversy than debates on the moral adequacy of the current opting-out system. In summary, the Austrian opting-out system will only be successful and ethically justifiable in the long run if three vital conditions are guaranteed: (1) Ongoing sensibility in the communication with relatives and respect of their feelings and wishes. The cited ÖBIG-Transplant guidelines can be seen as a move in the direction of an “extended opting out policy” (“extended objection-solution”), which also gives a right to object to family members; (2) Better public information and education to enable reflected attitudes and judgements on organ donation on a collective and on an individual level; (3) No commercial or research use of removed organs and tissues under the existing presumed consent policy. The original justification for the existing presumed consent policy has been the direct and immediate life (and health) saving intention of transplantation medicine. In research and pharmaceutical contexts, health interests are present but not in such an urgent and pressing way. References 1. 2. 3. 4. 5. Austrian Federal Hospitals Act (Österreichisches Krankenanstalten und Kuranstaltengesetz; KAKuG). Austrian Criminal Law (Österreichisches Strafgesetzbuch; StGB). Kopetzki, Christian: Organgewinnung zu Zwecken der Transplantation. Eine systematische Analyse des geltenden Rechts, Vienna 1988. “Koordinationsbüro für das Transplantationswesen. ÖBIG-Transplant: Jahresbericht 2007, Wien Mai 2008.” (http://www.goeg.at/media/ download/berichte/TX-JB_2007.pdf). ÖBIG-Transplant: Internal Guidelines 5 & 6 (Legal Principles; Communication with Family Members (Leitfaden 5 u. 6: Rechtliche Grundlagen; Kommunikation mit den Angehörigen), 2005. UNITED STATES Alexandra K. Glazier xplicit consent is the fundamental legal principle underlying organ and tissue donation in the United States. Accordingly, the United States maintains a true “opt-in” system for donation. There are, however, differences in the legal constructs supporting consent to deceased organ donation as compared with living donation. Consent is achieved in the deceased donation context under a legal framework of gift E The author declares no conflict of interest. S131 law, whereas consent for living donation relies on the informed consent doctrine. The following is a summary overview of gift law principles with respect to consent for deceased donation in the United States and an examination of the significant legal and practical differences that exist between gift law (consent for deceased donation) and the framework of informed consent (consent for living donation). Deceased Donation: The Law of Anatomical Gifts The donation of an organ from a decedent is considered an “anatomical gift” under US law (1). The legal origins of this began in 1968 when the Uniform Anatomical Gift Act (UAGA) first defined organ donation through a gift law construct. Today, the UAGA has been adopted as law—with some variation—by all 50 states and the District of Columbia (2). Under US law, gifts of any type must fulfill three basic elements to be legally recognized: (a) There must be donative intent; (b) The gift must be physically transferred or delivered; and (c) The gift must be accepted (3). Once all three criteria are met, the gift is complete and enforceable under the law. Although a gift is distinguishable from a contract in several important ways (including, most notably, the lack of payment), gift law is firmly rooted in legal principles of property. To “give” is understood under US law to mean “the act by which the owner of a thing voluntarily transfers the title and possession of the same from himself to another person without consideration” (4). The law of anatomical gifts follows the general law of gifts. An anatomical gift under the UAGA requires: (1) Donative intent expressed by the donor or donor’s family; (2) Recovery of the organ on the donor’s death; and (3) Acceptance of the anatomical gift by a donee. An anatomical gift is the voluntary and uncompensated transfer of an organ from the donor to the recipient. The legal requirement of donative intent is met under the UAGA through a “document of gift”, which is simply the documentation of consent to the donation. By consenting to donation, the donor expresses an intent to make an anatomical gift after death. A legally binding document of the gift can be through a donor registry, donor card or other signed document (5). Alternatively, if a potential donor has not made his own decision regarding donation, then the donor’s family, in a specified order, may consent to anatomical gifts to be recovered after the donor’s death (6). Under the UAGA, an anatomical gift is “conditional” on the death of the donor. Accordingly, once consent exists and after the donor has died, the gifted organs may be surgically recovered, transferred and accepted by a qualified third-party for the specified purpose (in most instances transplantation or research) (7). The recovery and subsequent transplantation of donated organs thereby fulfills the second and third criteria of the donation as a legally valid gift. Notably, the anatomical gift law construct for deceased donation in the United States does not incorporate an informed consent standard, as that term is understood under the law. Although surprising to some given that informed consent is a pinnacle legal doctrine of health care, the law clearly views deceased donation as anatomical gifting and not as a healthcare decision for the donor. The informed consent doctrine fundamentally requires the consenting party to make a decision regarding a proposed healthcare treatment rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/ztr2748-09a angnes Sⴝ46 9/11/09 4:43 Art: TP201180 Input-mn S132 | F1 www.transplantjournal.com or procedure through a facilitated understanding of the attendant risks and benefits. There are, however, neither risks nor benefits of donation to the deceased donor. Furthermore, the legal duty to obtain informed consent is borne out of the doctor-patient relationship. The decision to donate organs, however, may (and often does) occur completely outside of such a fiduciary relationship. For example, an individual may decide to consent to organ donation by signing a donor card in the privacy of his home or by registering as a donor during the driver’s license renewal process. This consent event could be months, years or even decades before the donor’s death. Criticisms of the US donor registry system often focus on the lack of informed consent. The process of registering as a donor is not, however, designed to meet legal informed consent standards. Rather, the act of registering as a donor fulfills the legal requirement of documenting the donor’s intent to make an anatomical gift and to voluntarily transfer organs to another. Some have argued that the informed consent standard for human subject research in the United States (which is established by regulation and applies only to living individuals) should be used as a model for consent to deceased donation (8). Informed consent in the human subject context, however, focuses on the subject’s understanding of the risks and benefits of participation in the research. These considerations are not relevant in the deceased donation context, because organ donation occurs after the donor’s death, thereby eliminating the experience of either risks or benefits. Gift law accommodates these realities of deceased donation. As with other types of gifts, a person may choose to inform themselves or remain uninformed but the legal ability to make an anatomical gift remains. Outside of the gift law context, other post-death decisions (such as burial or cremation) are similarly not required to meet an informed consent standard. In fact, individuals may sign advanced health care directives (including “do not resuscitate”) without any legal requirement that these significant decisions meet an informed consent standard. Most agree that potential donors or donor families should be directed to information that may assist in the donation decision making. It is nonetheless important to understand donor registries and other donation consent practices in the United States within the legal constructs of anatomical gift law. It is worth noting that consent to organ donation after cardiac death (DCD) is a unique circumstance that incorporates legal concepts from gift law as well as the informed consent doctrine. The potential DCD donor may have already made an anatomical gift conditional on death, but there must be a decision to withdraw support preceding the donation of organs after the donor’s death. The withdrawal of support requires informed consent from the patient’s legal surrogate even if the patient had previously consented to organ donation. For this reason, DCD necessitates attention to both legal principles (Fig. 1). The result is an interesting combination along the continuum of legal principles of consent for deceased donation, which is founded in anatomical gift law, and the informed consent principles that govern consent to living donation, as discussed further later. This is not surprising; DCD falls under the deceased donation category as the dead donor rule remains paramount in the United States (even if clinical debate exists over appropriate time intervals before death dec- Transplantation • Volume 88, Number 7S, October 15, 2009 FIGURE 1. Legal constructs of donation after cardiac death in the United States. laration). But, DCD also requires coordination with end of life decisions to withdraw support separate and aside from the donation itself. Although some have raised concerns that DCD oversteps legal boundaries of organ donation, the reality is that DCD cannot proceed without appropriate consensus from the care providers and the donor’s family. The convergence of these events (withdrawal of support and subsequent deceased donation) draws on both legal constructs. As a practical matter, this requires obtaining informed consent for the withdrawal of care and any premortem interventions and consent for an anatomical gift. Living Donation Living organ donation fundamentally involves a healthcare decision (surgical explant) with risks and benefits to the living donor. The law recognizes a fiduciary duty formed by the special relationship between the transplant surgeon and the living donor. This fiduciary duty gives rise to the legal obligation on the part of the surgeon to obtain informed consent before performing the surgical recovery of the donated organ. As a result, the legal principles underlying consent for living donation are firmly grounded in the informed consent doctrine, which establishes the patient’s right to provide or withhold consent for health care options after understanding the risks and benefits. This informed consent standard in living donation has been the subject of recent regulation (9). This reliance on the informed consent doctrine for consent to living donation should not, however, limit the legal understanding of the donated organ as a gift. Although no reported legal opinions yet exist in the United States, the legal status of the donated organ is likely to be understood as an anatomical gift regardless of the fact that the donor was living at the time that the gift was made. In the context of donated research tissue from living subjects, courts have held that even though the excision of the tissue may require informed consent under the human subject regulations, once given, the tissue may be properly understood as a donation subject to gift law (10). Similarly, the donation of an organ from a living donor requires informed consent but once removed, the organ may be properly categorized under the law as an inter vivos gift. Such a gift should be legally enforceable after delivery to and acceptance by the transplant recipient. This analysis would preclude an assertion of rights by the donor over a donated organ once the organ has been transplanted into the rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/ztr2748-09a angnes Sⴝ46 9/11/09 4:43 Art: TP201180 Input-mn © 2009 Lippincott Williams & Wilkins recipient. The gift status of a donated organ, regardless of whether the donor was living or deceased, provides the transplant recipient with consistent legal authority to continued possession of the transplanted organ. References 1. 2. 3. 4. 5. 6. 7. 8. 9. 10. Uniform Anatomical Gift Act (“Anatomical Gift” includes deceased donation of organs and tissues). 2006. Available at: http://www. anatomicalgiftact.org. Uniform Anatomical Gift Act (2006). Rubenstein v. Rosenthal, 140 A.D. 2d 156, 158 (1988). Black’s Law Dictionary 338 [ed 6]. 1991. Uniform Anatomical Gift Act, Section 2 (6). Uniform Anatomical Gift Act, Section 9. Uniform Anatomical Gift Act, Sections 11. 45 C.F.R. §46.102(f) and §46.116. 45 C.F.R. §482.102.(b). Washington University v. Catalona, 437 F. Supp. 2nd 985 (E.D. Mo. 2006); see also Greenberg v. Miami Children’s 264 F. Supp. 2nd 1064 (2003); Moore v. Regents of the University of California, 793 P2d 479. 1990. ITALY Alessandro Nanni Costa F1 The Role of Society The organ donation transplantation process implies a massive effort and engagement both by health professionals and by society itself. In fact, among the different medical fields, transplantation may be the only one that depends on peoples’ decision to give; to be solid for those who suffer. Therefore, society is the major protagonist of this delicate process, because without donation there can be no transplant. Society is formed by individuals who might decide to be prodonation. Once this happens, society becomes a source, the unique source, of donors, but the donor pool would not be helpful at all to the suffering if there was not a well organized, safe and highly skilled team of health professionals all over the country. This team is our national transplant network, whose management is assured by the National Transplant Centre (CNT) coordination, with the necessary support of interregional and regional transplant organizations. Transplantation brings the patient back to normal life and into society, thus the transplant system is a means to close the life cycle of people who had to stop their usual activities because of an organ severe insufficiency. This cycle is graphically represented by the Italian CNT logo (Fig. 1). People holding hands stands for a united society where everyone has understood that giving means to receive. Among us, there are transplanted people (the one with the red spot) who are necessary rings of the whole human chain. The red line symbolises the transplant network activity, which binds people by closing the chain. S133 value of the Italian network is the activity, follow-up and survival data publication per transplant center (Fig. 2). Italy is, in fact, the only European country who publishes such a detailed activity. By doing so, transparency is total and data are easily comparable by experts and by the general public. Electronic data processing and analyses are performed by the Transplant Information System (1) located at the CNT, where electronic entries inserted by transplant operators all over the country are collected and processed. Final data include yearly figures on the number of transplants performed (pediatrics and adults), percentage of follow-up reported, and organ and patient survival after transplant (Fig. 3). Analysis of the data collected also makes it possible to receive international, external evaluation about transplantation in italy, as shown by the excellent results published by the collaborative Transplant Study (Fig. 3). F3 Donation: A Topical Issue The Italian transplant network is not only engaged in improving transplant outcomes, but also strongly involved in spreading donation culture among citizens at all social levels, by promoting yearly donation campaigns along with the Ministry of Health, organizing congresses on major topics and by enriching the website (2) with activity data, news and useful information for patients and their families. The Italian transplant network would not reach citizens and patients without the necessary collaboration provided by volunteers’ and patients’ national associations whose presence among citizens is widespread and consolidated throughout the years. The most powerful means of spreading donation culture is to reach the youngest and make them discuss the topic at home with their families. This is why the CNT and the Ministry of Health entered universities, as well as primary and secondary schools with dedicated tools and projects. The aim of CNT and of the whole Italian transplant network was twofold: on one side to promote and spread donation culture to raise the number of donors, on the other side to take care of patients waiting for a transplant, as well as of their families, and of their post-transplant conditions through a periodic follow-up to bring them back to normal life and reintegrate them into society. Taking Care of Patients: A Priority Every medical field requires an accurate care of the patient and his family, but maybe transplantation needs to go a little further. There is in fact a double aspect; a donor giving Gaining Trust: A Daily Challenge Organs, cells and tissues are a public asset, therefore, transparency is the primary goal of allocation procedures and of the network’s activity in general. Transparency is the basic parameter to obtain the trust of people and patients. The Italian transplant network achieves this ambitious goal by providing and publishing monthly up-to-date waiting lists and donation transplantation activity data, but the added The author declares no conflict of interest. F2 C O L O R FIGURE 1. The Italian National Transplant Centre logo. rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/ztr2748-09a angnes Sⴝ46 9/11/09 4:43 Art: TP201180 Input-mn S134 | www.transplantjournal.com Transplantation • Volume 88, Number 7S, October 15, 2009 C O L O R FIGURE 2. Quality data regarding patient and graft survival in Italian heart transplant centers. All quality data are available on www.trapianti.ministerosalute.it. FIGURE 3. Comparison between Italian and European data on percentage of graft survival. an organ and a recipient receiving it. Both patients and their families must be taken care of with extreme attention on both physical and psychologic aspects, directly in hospital. All patients need adequate information (where to go, whom to talk with and what to expect). The patient’s family religious belief must be totally respected; there must be a comfortable reading room and specific rooms for meetings between the family and health professionals, especially when they have to discuss the donating option. This means that in each hospital, specific reception structures and dedicated space should be created to receive patients and their families in the most proper way. Particular attention must be paid to patients waiting for a transplant. Information on enrollment onto waiting lists must be provided in the clearest way and the physical and psychological care of the patient must be a priority. Patients have the right to information on the transplant type they are undergoing, waiting list time expectation, outcomes and obviously, possible risks. A National Prompt Network Organizing the donation-retrieval-transplant process is a crucial issue, because it requires specific management, a solid health organization and strict operational protocols and procedures (4, 5). As far as the Italian Transplantation is concerned, the management is lead by national, interregional and regional institutions and each time a transplant is performed about 150 people, of at least 10 different medical équipes, are involved and working together. The Italian transplant system is, for sure, a quality model for all health sectors and organizations (6). Moreover, it can avail itself of the expertise of “second opinion” advice from a group of five health professionals, who are available 24 hours a day, 365 days a year (one legal physician, one histopathologist, one infectivologist and two CNT physicians). These practitioners can be contacted by transplant centers and regional transplant coordinators through encoded procedures for particularly complex cases. The toughest issue in this specific medical field is the allocation of a scarce good i.e. an organ. It is of absolute importance for transparency and ethics to be the protagonists of this daily challenge. Physicians and the system must respect ethical aspects, clinical and therapeutic needs, the rights of the donor and recipient, as well as perform in total objectivity and equity. Categories such as emergency and pediatric patients are to be prioritised. During the last few decades, transplantation underwent major changes on both a technical and organizational level, especially after the approval of the Italian “Transplant Law” (7). Innovation and development are, thus, two keywords of transplantation progress and research can be identified as one of the most important driving forces for this fields’ activity. Transplantation and Sport: New Approaches to an Old Topic Donor and volunteer associations have a long established and well-built experience in organizing sporting activities for transplant patients such as marathons, soccer matches and ski competitions. The CNT recently decided to start up a dedicated research and activity line with the vision of sport as a propelling force for: Physical rehabilitation Self enhancement of the patient Reintegration into society Psycho-emotional rebirth rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/ztr2748-09a angnes Sⴝ46 9/11/09 4:43 Art: TP201180 Input-mn © 2009 Lippincott Williams & Wilkins Positive image communication Strong impact on media Healthy lifestyle: “more sport, less pills!” Given these positive spin-offs for the patient and his or her social environment, the CNT has so far organized two yearly meetings where transplanted sportsmen, sports physicians and transplant researchers met in an open scientific seminar followed by a world renowned international biking competition (Maratona dles Dolomites), held in the Italian Dolomites each summer. Self-Donating: A Christian Value The congress “A gift for life. Considerations on organ donation” was an unprecedented chance to explore the ethical and Christian value of self-giving, solidarity, physical and emotional sharing of ourselves. There are many crucial hints in the Holy Bible on the concept of renewing one part of our mortal body to give others the chance of surviving. The concept of distributing bread, which stands for life, is the materialization of the giving of a gift to many people allowing their rebirth. The analogy with organ donation, particularly with multiorgan donation is astonishing: LUKE 22, 17–19 22:17 “And he took a cup and, having given praise, he said, Make division of this among yourselves”. 22:19 “And he took bread and, having given praise, he gave it to them when it had been broken, saying, This is my body, which is given for you: do this in memory of me”. EZEKIEL 36, 26 36:26 “I will give you a new heart and put a new spirit in you; I will remove from you your heart of stone and give you a heart of flesh”. References 1. 2. 3. 4. 5. 6. Italian National Transplant Centre website. Transplant Information System (SIT). Available at: https://trapianti.sanita.it/statistiche/. Italian National Transplant Centre website. Available at: www.trapianti.ministerosalute.it. Italian National Transplant Centre. Normativa italiana su donazione, prelievo, e trapianto di organi e tessuti. Raccolta delle principali normative nel settore della donazione e del trapianto, Vol I. Rome, Italian National Transplant Centre 2005. Italian National Transplant Centre. Linee guida e protocolli della rete nazionale trapianti, Vol II. Rome, Italian National Transplant Centre 2007. Fishman J. World Health Organization. Report on the review process of the national transplantation programme in Italy (Italian version). Trapianti 2008; 12: 37. Italian law reference, Legge 1° aprile 1999, n. 91. “Disposizioni in materia di prelievi e di trapianti di organi e di tessuti.” Gazzetta Ufficiale 1999; 87. LATIN AMERICA Valter D. Garcia, Mario Abbud-Filho, and Jose O. Medina-Pestana atin America refers to the countries in the American continent and has a population of 550 million inhabitants. The official languages derive from Latin, mainly Spanish, Portuguese and French. Apart from Guyana and Suriname, L The authors declare no conflict of interest. S135 all other countries in South and Central America, Cuba, Haiti, Dominican Republic in the Caribbean and Mexico in North America are Latin American countries. These countries have striking geographic, ethnic, cultural and socioeconomic disparities. The gross domestic product varies from U.S. $2800 per capita in Nicaragua to U.S. $14,300 in Chile. Guatemala has the lowest human development index (0.689) and Argentina, the highest (0.869). The population ranges from 3.2 million inhabitants in Panama to 190 million in Brazil (Table 1) (1, 2). These characteristics may account for the strong discrepancy in the number of solid organ transplantation and organ donation, as well as in the access to the deceased donor organ pool among the different Latin American countries. As socioeconomic inequities and low human development index have been associated with nonuniform access to solid organ transplantation and ethically reproved practices of organ commerce, organ trafficking and transplant tourism (3), we examined the overall rates of living and deceased solid organ donation and transplantation in Latin America and its regulations and legal aspects. Organ Donation The number of transplantations performed with deceased donors is relatively small in Latin America when compared with countries from different regions of the world (4). Retrospective analysis of the epidemiology of brain death in Brazil has shown that the number of potential donors that are formally notified of the local organ procurement organization vary from 78 to 105 per million of population (pmp) (5). However, the actual rate of donation in Brazil did not surpass 7 donors pmp. The rate of identification of potential donors is high in Uruguay and Puerto Rico (50 pmp), intermediate in Argentina, Brazil, Colombia and Cuba (20 – 40 pmp) and low in Chile, Venezuela, Mexico and Peru (less then 20 pmp). Even so, the number of transplantations performed with deceased donors in Latin America, during the year of 2007, was low when compared with the number of potential donors notified during the same period. Puerto Rico, Uruguay and Cuba performed more than 18 transplantations pmp with deceased donors, Argentina performed 12 pmp and the remaining countries less than 10 pmp (Table 2). A year by year analysis showed that the transplantation activity with deceased donors increased only 0.75 pmp in the last 5 years, indicating that urgent interventions are needed to increase the actual rate of deceased donation (6 –12). The reasons for such a low effective rate of donation might be due to an inadequate number of organ procurement organizations. The lack of appropriate training by the health care professionals dealing with the family members of the potential donors may also play a critical role (5, 13). The rate of familiar refusal to donate ranges from 10% to 80% among Latin American countries. It has remained steady, around 33%, in Brazil, decreased from 62% to 36% in Uruguay and increased from 46% to 80% in Peru over the last 7 years. The 2007 overall rate of familiar refusal was 35% in Latin America, 15% in Cuba and 80% in Peru. However, other family related reasons can explain the low rates of effective donations (13). The system of donation can also contribute to increasing the donation rates, but the final result varies among dif- T1 T2 rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/ztr2748-09a angnes Sⴝ46 9/11/09 4:43 Art: TP201180 Input-mn S136 | www.transplantjournal.com Transplantation • Volume 88, Number 7S, October 15, 2009 TABLE 1. Demographic data and 2007 cumulative activity of solid organ transplantation among Latin American countries Organ transplanted Country Inhabitants (thousands) GDP per capita (US $) HDI Kidney Liver Heart Argentinaa Boliviab Brazilb Chileb Colombiaa Costa Ricaa Cubab Dominican Republica Ecuadora El Salvadorb Guatemalab Hondurasb Mexicob Nicaraguab Panamaa Paraguaya Perua Puerto Ricob Uruguaya Venezuelab Total 40.3 9.1 190 16.2 44.3 4.1 11.4 9.4 13.7 6.9 12.7 7.5 108.7 5.6 3.2 6.7 28.6 3.9 3.4 26.9 552,6 13,100 4400 9500 14,300 7400 11,100 11,000 6600 7400 6000 5100 4300 12,400 2800 10,700 4000 7600 18,400 10,800 12,800 8630c 0.869 0.695 0.800 0.867 0.791 0.846 0.838 0.779 0.772 0.735 0.689 0.700 0.829 0.710 0.812 0.755 0.773 — 0.852 0.792 0.797d 11,322 712 50,281 5234 7236 1415 4167 543 916 459 815 — 24,680 11 325 202 2433 1342 1248 3710 117,329 2,600 6 7895 653 975 40 226 — 1 — — — 754 — — — 35 — 28 42 13,246 1201 1 2288 188 464 14 130 — 9 — — — 228 — — 11 34 105 99 1 4773 a Countries that adopt the presumed consent for living organ donation. Countries that adopt the informed consent for living organ donation. c Latin America mean GDP per capita. d Latin America mean HDI. GDP, gross domestic product; HDI, human development index. b ferent countries adopting a specific system. Spain, France, Italy and Austria have passed the presumed consent for solid organ donation and all theses countries have high (⬎20 pmp) deceased donor rates. These numbers are contrasted by Britain where the rate of refusal to donate peaks 40%. Britons must register as a donor. Although lawfully established in many countries, the presumed consent does not always improve living donation yields. Greece has a presumed consent system and low deceased donor rates; United States, conversely, ranks pretty high adopting an informed consent system. Social and cultural factors represent critical barriers to deceased organ donation. Brazil formally moved from an informed to a presumed consent system of donation in 1998 as an effort to improve the deceased organ donor pool. One year later, 48% and 59% of newly issued identification cards and drivers licenses, respectively, had registered the people refusing to donate (14). At present, the presumed consent system of donation is lawfully established in Argentina, Colombia, Costa Rica, Dominican Republic, Ecuador, Panama, Paraguay, Peru and Uruguay. All other Latin American countries only legitimise the informed consent system (Table 1). Solid Organ Transplantation The 2007 cumulative activity of solid organ transplantation among Latin American Countries is shown in Table 1. The total number of kidney transplantations was 117,329 (13,246 livers, 4773 hearts, 782 lungs and 1672 pancreas). In 2007, 8743 kidneys (48% from living donors), 1710 livers (11%), 363 hearts (Table 2), 247 pancreas and 86 lungs were transplanted in Latin America, which represent, respectively, 13.4%, 8.4%, 6.5%, 9.6% and 2.8% of the transplants performed worldwide. Kidney transplantationactivityincreased177%from1991to2007representing a mean annual improvement of 7.5%. There is a broad range of variation in kidney transplantation rates among Latin American countries. The overall activity in 2007 was 16 (range 0 –31) kidney transplants per pmp representing only 26% of the Latin American waiting list. Uruguay, Argentina and Puerto Rico have the highest rates of kidney transplantation, overcoming 20 transplants pmp a year. Thus, although steadily increasing, the number of kidney transplants performed in Latin America is far beyond the countries need. Liver transplantation was performed in nine countries at a rate of 3.1 pmp a year. The number of surgeries increased at a rate of 10% a year from 1992 to 2007, representing 157% improvement during this period. Even so, only 12% of the waiting list has been supplied. Accordingly, heart transplantation increased at a rate of 6% in the same period, with 1.5 transplants pmp in 2007, supplying 10% of the waiting list. Pancreas and lung transplantations had a poor performance in 2007 rating 0.5 and 0.16 transplants pmp, respectively. Only 15% and 2.6% of patients waiting for these organs successfully underwent transplantation (6 –12). rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/ztr2748-09a angnes Sⴝ46 9/11/09 4:43 Art: TP201180 Input-mn S137 © 2009 Lippincott Williams & Wilkins TABLE 2. Number of solid organ transplants performed by Latin American countries in 2007 and type of donors Kidney Liver Heart Country Total pmp LD (%) Total pmp LD (%) Total pmp Argentina Bolivia Brazil Chile Colombia Costa Rica Cuba Dominican Republic Ecuador El Salvador Guatemala Honduras Mexico Nicaragua Panama Paraguay Peru Puerto Rico Uruguay Venezuela Total (mean) 867 72 3456 283 758 38 16.6 59 51 38 138 4 2132 — 31 28 80 95 102 345 8753 22.0 7.3 18.2 17.9 16.1 8.4 14.8 6.5 3.9 5.5 10.4 0.5 20.1 — 9.9 3.8 2.8 24.4 30.9 12.6 15.8a 17.3 68.5 50.5 23.5 8.1 52.4 10.1 98.5 79.5 100 74.0 100 75.1 — 36.4 86.8 21.5 9.4 5.8 46.0 48.0 268 — 1,014 79 193 — 39 1 — — — — 103 — — — — — 4 10 1,710 6.9 — 5.5 4.8 4.1 — 3.4 0.1 — — — — 0.9 — — — — — 1.2 0.4 3.1b 7.8 — 14.7 — — — — — — — — — 11.8 — — — — — 25.0 60.0 11.1 83 — 158 16 60 1 7 — — — — — 15 — — 2 4 13 4 — 363 2.1 — 0.9 1.0 1.3 0.2 0.6 — — — — — 0.2 — — 0.3 0.1 3.3 1.2 — 0.7c a Latin America mean kidney transplantation pmp. Latin America mean liver transplantation pmp. c Latin America mean kidney transplantation pmp. pmp, per million of population; LD, living donors. b Solid Organ Demand and Supply The waiting lists for solid organ transplantation grow ever longer as ageing, high-risk cardiovascular disease and chronic disease population increases. According to the World Heath Organization, only 1 in 10 people in need of a new kidney manages to get one. The problem has been made worse by a fall in strokes and head traumas in recent years (the main sources of organs for transplantation). Different strategies have been developed and applied in different countries to increase the supply of solid organs for transplantation. Kidney waiting lists have been shortened by allowing paired organ exchange donations (15), accepting older donors than previously (16) and transplantation with living unrelated donors (17). Although honorable, these practices raise profound ethical debate and are not taking place in Latin American countries. Living unrelated donation is unlawful in Argentina and Uruguay. Brazilian law allows living unrelated donation from spouses but since 1997 judicial authorization is required for other unrelated donors (18). Thus, the number of transplants with organs from living unrelated donors remains steadily low (19). In 1998, a new law determined that living unrelated donation must also have an approval from the hospital ethics committee and state health secretary. All other countries accept spouses with restrictions to other living unrelated donors. The issue of giving financial incentives to living, solid organ donors has deserved publication in the nonmedical media (20). The Iranian system of officially sanctioned compensated living organ donation has eliminated the country’s kidney transplant waiting list. The government’s approach turns the illegal commerce to a state of regulated kindness. Apart from the ethical aspects, Iranians are not allowed to donate solid organs to a non-resident alien and no longer go abroad for kidney transplantation (21). The problem of underground organ harvesting and paid cross-countries transplantation with the strong negative impact in the living donation programs were pointed out in a special article recently published in The Economist magazine (20). These illegal practices do not only take place in undeveloped countries. In the United States, an investigation carried out by the Los Angeles Times found that four Japanese criminals received solid organ transplants from deceased donors at a Medical Center of University of California Los Angeles; in New York, an ex-dental surgeon was jailed for stealing bones, skin, arterial valves, ligaments and other tissues from corpses. The trade in human organs is illegal in Latin America, and every country has specific legislations to address this issue. In addition, many Latin American countries pose different restrictions to perform transplantations on non-resident aliens. Argentina and Uruguay do not allow transplantations in non-resident aliens. Chile only allows foreigners who have been living in the country, for at least 5 years, to receive an organ for transplantation. In Colombia, non-resident aliens can receive an organ for transplantation if there is not a rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/ztr2748-09a angnes Sⴝ46 9/11/09 4:43 Art: TP201180 Input-mn S138 | www.transplantjournal.com Colombian citizen in need. Other countries, including Brazil, have no specific legislations and allow, at present, solid organ transplantations in alien recipients accordingly to the policy in operation for the Brazilian citizens. Although Latin America is considered a potential target for organ commerce, much of the mass media reports regarding illegal activities of transplant tourism and the recruitment of donors to go abroad for living organ donation were never officially supported. Most of the debate is based on misinterpretation of old Latin American social problems, such as the significant rates of infant prostitution and illegal adoption, officially recognized by the World Health Organization. Awful malpractices such as murder or kidnapping of children for organ removal and forced organ removal have never been confirmed. Occasional and nonsystematic episodes of unlawful solid organ commerce and transplantation have been identified. The World Health Organization has indicated Colombia as a possible destination for transplant tourism in Latin America, but precise data about this illegal activity are not currently available. From 2001 to 2003, 14 people living in the Brazilian northeastern state of Pernambuco were recruited to travel to South Africa to sell their kidneys (22). These episodes characterized people trafficking but not organ trafficking. The public ministry identified and jailed the criminals and the court of justice judged and condemned them. So far, no other similar situations have been observed. In summary, the great majority of the countries in Latin America perform kidney transplantations, with a few countries performing a small number of other transplantations. The potential donor rate is low (less than 40 pmp in most of the countries) and the rate of refusal to donate is high, resulting in low deceased donor transplantation activity. The great majority of the countries have specific legislations on organ transplantation. Organ commerce is forbidden and occasional irregularities are promptly investigated by the public ministry and testified by the society. Thus, the perspective is that the programs of solid organ transplantation among Latin American countries stand on ethical principles established by international societies and the World Health Organization (23). References 1. Transplantation • Volume 88, Number 7S, October 15, 2009 2. 3. 4. 5. 6. 7. 8. 9. 10. 11. 12. 13. 14. 15. 16. 17. 18. 19. 20. 21. 22. 23. World population data sheet. 2006. Available at: http//www.prb.org/ pdf06/06WorldDataSheet.pdf. Accessed 2008. Human development report 2007/2008. 2008. Available at: http:// hdrstats.undp.org/countries/. Accessed 2008. Levine D. Kidney vending: “Yes!” or “No!.” Am J Kidney Dis 2000; 35: 1002. Medina-Pestana J, Duro-Garcia V. Strategies for establishing organ transplant programs in developing countries: The Latin America and Caribbean experience. Artif Organs 2006; 30: 498. Pestana J, Vaz M, Delmonte C, et al. Organ donation in Brazil. Lancet 1993; 341: 118. Instituto Nacional Central Único Coordinador de Ablación e Implante. 2008. Available at: http://www.incucai.gov.ar/. Associação Brasileira de Transplante de Órgãos. 2008. Available at: http://www.abto.org.br/. Corporacion del Trasplante. 2008. Available at: http://www. trasplante.cl/. Centro Nacional de Trasplantes. 2008. Available at: http://www. cenatra.salud.gob.mx/. Instituto Nacional de Donacion y Trasplante de Celulas Tejidos y Organos. 2008. Available at: http://www.indt.edu.uy/. INFOMED Red de Salud de Cuba. 2008. Available at: http://www. sld.cu. Garcia V, Medina-Pestana J, Santiago-Deolpin E. Latin America Transplantation Report. São Paulo: Lado a Lado Comunicação e Marketing; 2007. Morais M, Felício H, da Silva R, et al. Multiorgan donation in an organ procurement organization: Evaluation of the causes of nondonation. Transplant Proc 2002; 34: 453. Garcia V, Ianhez L, Medina-Pestana J. História dos Transplantes no Brasil. In: Garcia V, Abbud-Filho M, Neumann J, et al, eds. Transplante de Órgãos e Tecidos. São Paulo, Segmento Farma Editora 2006, pp 27. Delmonico F, Arnold R, Scheper-Hughes N, et al. Ethical incentives– not payment–for organ donation. N Engl J Med 2002; 346: 2002. Remuzzi G, Cravedi P, Perna A, et al. Long-term outcome of renal transplantation from older donors. N Engl J Med 2006; 354: 343. Futagawa Y, Waki K, Gjertson D, et al. Living-unrelated donors yield higher graft survival rates than parental donors. Transplantation 2005; 79: 1169. Legislação sobre o Sistema Nacional de Transplantes. 2008. Available at: http://dtr2001.saude.gov.br/transplantes/legislacao.htm#. Accessed December 9, 2008. Abbud-Filho M, Garcia V, Campos H, et al. Do we need living unrelated organ donation in Brazil? Transplant Proc 2004; 36: 805. Organ Transplants. The gap between supply and demand. The Economist 2008. Ghods A, Savaj S. Iranian model of paid and regulated living-unrelated kidney donation. Clin J Am Soc Nephrol 2006; 1: 1136. F G. Tráfico de órgãos abastecia Europa e Africa. Folha de São Paulo, 2003. Steering Committee of the Istanbul Summit. Organ trafficking and transplant tourism and commercialism: The Declaration of Istanbul. Lancet 2008; 372: 5. Different Views of the Organ Donation Experience THE RECIPIENT Mariangela Gritta Grainer My husband Aldo had a liver transplant over 7 months ago. Our experience was a complex, hard and extraordinary one, which cannot be expressed in a few minutes. We thought we would try to give you the answer to a question: Why and what were the elements that decided the positive outcome of the illness, which was already in a desperate state? The author declares no conflict of interest. 1. A fruitful balance was found between the ethical and the technical scientific aspects. Our experience is proof that it is not only possible, but also necessary, to combine ethics and science, especially when questions such as life and death, which are often confused, are being faced. 2. The ethic of giving (suggested in the title of this conference) showed its power here. We were able to develop it further because of the extraordinary team we found at the transplant clinic of Padova, lead by Dr. Umberto Cillo. 3. Talent, professional attitudes, the ability to listen and manage relationships. A team, who knew how to take responsibility for decisions at every moment, even when it was decided that a transplant from a living donor, our son Alessandro, should be postponed, due to the wors- rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/ztr2748-09a angnes Sⴝ46 9/11/09 4:43 Art: TP201180 Input-mn S139 © 2009 Lippincott Williams & Wilkins ening of Aldo’s state of health and to summon the ethical-scientific emergency committee. It was Good Friday; we went home and spent Easter in the dark. But, on the day after Easter Monday, there was light, and it was announced that a donor had been found whose life had ended only to give a new beginning to Aldo’s and also to all of our lives. 4. Our experience, which started at a different transplant clinic in 2005, is proof that not all clinics are the same and that it is worth aiming for quality, rather than quantity, to get centers of excellence with the best human resources and the necessary structure and financial support. 5. Our experience shows that guidelines have to be in place but they have to be flexible and continually updated in order, not just to cure, but to take care of the patient who is “unique”, who has the right to be looked after in safety (free from worry and at the least risk) but also with curiosity (by those who are constantly looking for knowledge and experimenting new things). Care is at the root of both safety and curiosity. 6. Aldo’s strength and perseverance along with the active help of the extended family network was another deciding factor before and after the transplant. After the awful experience at the first clinic (we were told on the November 29, 2007, “the transplant cannot be performed, there is nothing we can do”), we chose not to give up and to fight on to the end if we had to. We studied, we got informed, we got hold of expert friends and acquaintances in the medical field, we got in touch with the national body, which coordinates transplant clinics and with the help of Dr. Alessandro Nanni Costa, we got to Padova. Information and knowledge (which are always important) have been essential factors in our story, as well as the support and involvement of the family network. This suggests that information and knowledge should be more accessible and that people who are going it alone and would otherwise not get through, should be supported by social-medical structures and volunteers. It was, and continues to be, important for us to have a positive relationship with the local medical services, the day hospital in Valdagno which is in connection with the transplant center, and Dr. Sergio Urbani who takes care of us almost daily. This was also an extraordinary experience for us, because it made us question more strongly why we are in the world and how we live. It confirmed to us that ethics are visible in the way in which every person (on the basis of what they are offered by society, their resources and history) decides their answer to the question of meaning which life puts to them, developing their own religious and political ideals and, in this way, expressing the goals which they hope to achieve. We think about the meaning of life all too rarely, but the goals which we hope to achieve are not hidden: they are expressed in our daily actions and in how we live in our private and public spheres. The waiting lists for transplants are long and there are still only very few “donated” organs. A strong message for all of humankind goes out from this important and significant event regarding organ dona- tion because “A Gift for Life” is much more than a gift to give life: it is a sign of love toward others and toward ourselves. THE COORDINATOR Pier Paolo Donadio, Anna Guermani and Riccardo Bosco he Italian National Health Care Service is organized on a regional basis. Each region has its own organ procurement organization, where the key role is that of the transplant Coordinator, who is present at each hospital where there is an intensive care unit (ICU). In most hospitals of the Piedmont Region, the transplant Coordinator is an anesthesiologist with ICU experience, who is involved not only in organ procurement but also in the usual daily ICU activity. He or she is also involved in the treatment of patients with brain damage, who are typically those that eventually suffer brain death and become potential donors. As a result, he or she is the one who suggests the possibility of organ donation to families. In this article, therefore, by “Coordinator” we mean the person who suggests the possibility of an organ donation. He belongs to the team who has taken charge of the patient’s treatment. The death of a person always constitutes a moment of sorrow and bereavement for his or her relatives. However, this is especially true when death is caused by acute brain damage, because it occurs suddenly and unexpectedly, and as such, it does not possess any of the soothing and alleviating aspects of predictable and expected deaths. Moreover, the death of a patient represents a defeat for the physician who treated him or her. When brain death comes, the physician’s position, both towards the patient and his or her relatives, radically changes. The physician can no longer give hope to the relatives, nor can he or she do one’s best to heal the patient. Nonetheless, he or she still has the chance and an obligation to do more. Even though it is no longer possible to treat the patient, the relationship with the family does not cease. On the contrary, under the special circumstances of an abrupt loss, not only it is still possible to comfort, to listen and to bring relief to the relatives but, if a positive relationship was established with them during the patient’s hospitalization, the moment of death constitutes a time when it is possible to create moments of extraordinary empathy toward the relatives themselves. Those who have experienced the loss of a relative, remember precisely all that happened on the day when the relative died. Simple words and gestures of those who were around, as well as seemingly unimportant things, in those moments penetrate deep in the minds and souls of deeply saddened people, to remain there forever. The Coordinator must be aware of how delicate these moments can be. He or she must be capable of preserving and nurturing the relationship with the relatives by accepting their many diverse reactions when facing the death of a beloved one. The Coordinator must accompany the relatives along this difficult path whilst ensuring his or her continued assistance. As the relationship with the family does not cease, the therapeutic effort does not cease either. The physician who loses a patient to brain death must be aware that, from that T rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/ztr2748-09a angnes Sⴝ46 9/11/09 4:43 Art: TP201180 Input-mn S140 | www.transplantjournal.com time on, other people become his or her patients: they are those who are waiting for a transplant. This awareness is very important, because it justifies and motivates the continuation of the therapeutic effort. The physician who does not strive to recognize a potential donor and then to take care of the donor management shows that they are not capable of understanding that they now have new patients. The physician does not know them, but they must learn to “feel” them, even though they are not present, and to operate in their interest, because they alone have the means to secure the needed therapy for them. This is why the physician must always suggest organ donation. Some claim that suggesting donation is the most difficult proposition to advance to families, made at the worst possible time. With this, they justify their weak propensity towards procurement. The effective Coordinator must realize it is not so. He or she must be convinced that donation is a positive opportunity to offer to the relatives of the deceased, a way to turn a great evil into a great good. Donating does not remove the suffering, but it can somewhat ease it. Certainly, it does not worsen it. To be able to correctly propose donation, it is necessary to be intimately convinced that the proposal is an offer and not a request: the Coordinator is not asking for organs, but is offering the relatives the opportunity to do some good at a time of utmost suffering. They know that donation, besides being indispensable to the patients on the waiting list, is also good for the relatives of the donor. It is essential for the Coordinator to think of themself as one who offers rather than one who asks for something. By far, in the majority of cases, the doubts of the relatives, implicit or explicit, come down to three main questions: “Is he/she really dead? Was everything possible done by the physicians in order to save him/her? What will be done with the organs?”. These questions must be answered by the Coordinator clearly. The cadaver of the brain dead person does not look like a corpse: it is not pale and cold; the heart is beating, the chest is heaving. It is hard to believe that that person is dead. The Coordinator must be capable of explaining brain death simply and clearly, in a direct and easily understandable way. An image, such as that of a single photon emission computed tomography (SPECT) scan, can be helpful to explain what has happened. Words must be simple. The term “dead” must be openly used. It is also necessary to give the relatives some time to comprehend and internalize death. When the family members refuse the removal of the organs claiming that, for instance, their relative “has already suffered too much”, this shows that they have not truly comprehended death; they still do not consider the body of their beloved as that of a dead person. Conviction is rational, but being persuaded is emotional. To consent to a donation, it is necessary that the relatives are not only convinced but also intimately persuaded to be in front of a corpse: this often takes time. The Coordinator must be capable of helping the relatives to start the difficult process of bereavement acceptance and he must avoid the risk, among other things, of inadvertently proposing donation as a way to make a part of the deceased live on within the body of someone else. This is why such words as “dead”, “corpse” and other similar words, should not be avoided. On the contrary, it is necessary to say them clearly over and over Transplantation • Volume 88, Number 7S, October 15, 2009 again. It is also necessary to accompany the family members toward the realization that that body, which still looks like their living relative, has truly become a corpse and that he or she has irreversibly passed away. The second question asked by families, implicitly or explicitly, is about the quality of treatment: was everything possible done by the physicians to save their relative? The best circumstance is when this question is not raised, because the family have already found an unspoken satisfactory answer through the relationship they have developed with the physicians during the administration of therapy and is also thanks to a positive impression that the relatives formed about the overall health care system. Unfortunately, this is not always the case: many of the refusals to donations are due to the relatives perceiving a generally poor quality of care and treatment. Trust in the health care system typically impacts the perceived quality level, and poor quality is the likely cause of most refusals, more often in Southern Italy than in Northern Italy. The perception of quality, as well as the credibility and trustworthiness of the Coordinator, are both established before the death of the relative, i.e., during the therapeutic endeavor. If before the death, there was keen attention, empathy, dedication and consideration, when death comes the Coordinator will be viewed and felt as a trustworthy person, caring for both the patient and the relatives. On the contrary, if before there had been only cold technical jargon, it will be most difficult for the Coordinator to build the trust needed for them to be able to propose donation, especially as an act of consolation for the relatives and a gift for the potential recipients. In the context of sheer technicality, donation remains organ procurement and organ procurement is a request and not an offer. On the contrary, within a previously established empathic relationship, organ procurement becomes a donation, and donation turns into an offered opportunity of bereavement alleviation. Of course, this kind of attitude should not only be followed by Coordinators when a potential donor is involved. It should be the standard attitude of all the ICU team physicians towards all patients, so that their relationship with families can be one of empathy, solidarity and consideration. This way, not only will the number of donors increase but also the quality of the relationship with the relatives will improve. The third question concerns the allocation of the organs. “Who is going to get the organs of my relative? And you, who are asking me to allow you to take them, what will you do with them?”. The lay people do not know that organ allocation takes place according to strict pre-established rules and the Coordinator has absolutely no role the process. The Coordinator must be capable of clearly explaining the rules governing organ allocation. He or she must also be capable of vouching for the ethicality of such rules, thanks to the credibility he has earned from the relatives. To do so, besides being trustworthy, he or she must know the system and its rules perfectly and the system must not have shown any signs of questionable behavior. When scandalous mismanagement of allocation takes place, the number of refusals sharply increases. Therefore, the system must be trustworthy. When a Coordinator finds himself in the context of a system that is ethically weak, or worse, plagued by scandals, his action is objectively quite impaired. Confidence in the ethical merits of rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/ztr2748-09a angnes Sⴝ46 9/11/09 4:43 Art: TP201180 Input-mn S141 © 2009 Lippincott Williams & Wilkins the system enhances the motivation and credibility of the Coordinator. If the three prerequisites; certainty of death; perception of quality care, both relational and medical; and assurance of ethical allocation of organs, are all met with satisfaction then the donation proposal will finally be accepted. In essence, it is necessary to create conditions in which the Coordinator can address the relatives with words similar to those which Jesus spoke when he sent the Disciples to spread the Gospel: “Freely you have received, freely give” (Matthew 10, 8). THE ANESTHESIOLOGIST Franceso Giordano and Blanca Martinez Lopez de Arroyabe T1 Definitions The main role of the anesthesiologist-intensive care physician is to treat all the organ failures, especially the lifethreatening ones, which compromise vital functions. The patients affected by alterations of vital functions because of acute reversible pathologies or exacerbation of chronic diseases need intensive medical treatment, monitoring and nursing. The admission in the intensive care unit is considered adequate when a reasonable probability of beneficial outcomes from the intensive treatment exists. Regarding neurological failure, the severity of the clinical picture can cause an absent or insufficient response to the adequate therapy performed and a secondary evolution to mild (Glasgow Coma State [GCS], 13–15), moderate (GCS 9 –12), severe (GCS 6 – 8) or high severe (GCS 3–5) comatose state (1). Coma is the condition in which both components of consciousness, wakefulness (sleep-wake cycles) and awareness, are lost. Often the vegetative functions (including breathing and cardiovascular activity) are severely altered. Coma is a deep, sustained pathologic unconsciousness that results from dysfunction of the ascending reticular activating system in either the brain stem or both cerebral hemispheres. The eyes remain closed and the patient cannot be aroused for at least 1 hr (2). The causes of coma can be classified in two main categories: primary encephalic lesions and diseases (trauma, vascular lesions, infections, tumors, seizures and degenerative diseases) or systemic and extracranial lesions (metabolic disturbances and hypoxic-ischemic due to cardiac arrest) (3). The acute phase is followed by a postacute phase and subsequently the final phase of the outcome, which includes a gradation of probable conditions defined by the Glasgow Outcome Score (GOS). The GOS varies from a state of good recovery, mild or severe disability, persistent or permanent vegetative state, leading up to brain death (Table 1). The vegetative state is a clinical condition of complete unawareness of the self and the environment, accompanied by sleep-wake cycles with either complete or partial preservation of hypothalamic and brain-stem autonomic functions. The vegetative condition may be transient, because it is merely a stage in the recovery from severe or permanent brain damage as a consequence of the failure to recover from such injuries. The vegetative state can also occur as a result of the relentless progression of degenerative or metabolic neuro- TABLE 1. Glasgow Outcome Score (4, 21–23) Glasgow Outcome Score GOS 5: good recovery Capacity to resume occupational and social activities, although there may be minor physical or mental deficits or symptoms. GOS 4: moderate disability Disabled but independent. Independent and can resume almost all activities of daily living. Disabled to the extent that they cannot participate in variety of social and work activities. GOS 3: severe disability Conscious but disabled. No longer capable of engaging in most previous personal, social, or work activities. Limited communication skills and have abnormal behavioral or emotional responses. Typically are partially or totally dependent on assistance from others in daily living. GOS 2: persistant vegetative Not aware of surroundings or state purposely responsive to stimuli. Patient exhibits no obvious cortical function. GOS 1: brain death — GOS, Glasgow Outcome Score. logic diseases or from developmental malformations of the nervous system. The diagnostic criteria of vegetative state are as follows: (a) No evidence of awareness of self or environment and an inability to interact with others; (b) No evidence of sustained, reproducible, purposeful or voluntary behavioral responses to visual, auditory, tactile or noxious stimuli; (c) No evidence of language comprehension or expression; (d) Intermittent wakefulness manifested by the presence of sleep-wake cycles; (e) Sufficiently preserved hypothalamic and brain-stem autonomic functions to permit survival with medical and nursing care; (f) Bowel and bladder incontinence; and (g) Variably preserved cranial-nerve reflexes (pupillary, oculocephalic, corneal, vestibulo-ocular and gag) and spinal reflexes (2). The vegetative state was originally defined by Jennett and Plum in 1972. According to the authors, the term “persistent”, when applied to the vegetative state, meant sustained over time; “permanent” meant irreversible (4). The adjective persistent refers only to a condition of past and continuing disability with an uncertain future, whereas permanent implies irreversibility. Persistent vegetative state is a diagnosis; permanent vegetative state is a prognosis (5, 2). The term vegetative state explains the important contrast existing between the severe mental compromise and the preservation of autonomic functions (6). Finally, brain death is defined as the permanent absence of all brain functions, including those of the brain stem. Brain-dead patients are irreversibly comatose and apneic and have lost all brain-stem reflexes and cranial-nerve functions, they have unresponsiveness and a lack of receptivity and the cause has been identified (7). The brain death is characterized by irreversibility. The patients affected by this clinical picture rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/ztr2748-09a angnes Sⴝ46 9/11/09 4:43 Art: TP201180 Input-mn S142 | www.transplantjournal.com (GCS 3, bilateral midriasis and absence of brain-stem reflexes) present the legal conditions and requirements to perform the declaration of brain death. These subjects are considered to be potential organ and tissue donors. To these patients, the intensive treatment is clinically and ethically justified, up to the moment of organ withdrawal, to perform organ transplant on patients suffering from terminal organ dysfunction. The main limitation of transplant activity is the low availability of organs and the disparity between the number of potential organ donors and the number of used donors (8). The strategy to increase the number of suitable organs consists in the improvement of the clinical management of the potential donor, with prevention and early treatment of complications from brain death which cause hypoxemic- ischemic phenomena of the organs (9, 10). Therefore, the anesthesiologist is the specialist in the middle of the donation withdrawal transplant process. When, despite maximum therapeutic efforts brain death occurs, the focus of the anesthesiologist is not on cerebral protection, but is directed to adequate organ conservation. At this point, the role of the intensive care physician includes clinical aspects (identification and support of potential organ donors as well as organ suitability), organizational aspects, legal (declaration of brain death process) and relationship aspects, such as communication with the donor’s family and with the local, regional, interregional and national transplant coordinating centers (11). F1 Clinical Aspects Regarding clinical aspects, the aim of the treatment of the potential organ donor is to guarantee a satisfactory level of perfusion and oxygenation of the organs and tissues destined to transplant. These organs are compromised by hemodynamic instability and the inefficacy of homeostasis mechanisms. These phenomena are the consequence of the final loss of feed-back neurovegetative mechanisms, due to the complete and irreversible cessation of the encephalic functions (10). The state of brain death is unavoidably followed by somatic death due to cardiac arrest after several hours. During this period, if an early and intensive treatment is not performed, the evolution from brain death to cardiac arrest can cause a loss of 10 –20% of potential donors (12). The treatment of the donor must correct the functional disturbances resulting from brain death and restore and preserve the quality of the organs. The main pathophysiologic alterations due to irreversible cessation of encephalic functions are the following: hemodynamic disturbances, respiratory exchange alterations, electrolyte derangements, coagulation, metabolic and hormonal disturbances and alteration of temperature regulation mechanisms. The hemodynamic alterations are the ones that most influence the organ quality (13). Several therapeutic schemes have been proposed for adequate hemodynamic management of the potential organ donor (Fig. 1). Moreover, another important clinical aspect regards organ suitability evaluation. The final result of a transplant depends on multiple factors associated with the receiver’s clinical conditions (i.e., urgent transplant) and to the donor’s characteristics. The insufficient donor availability, the transplant risks or benefits relationship and the restricted ischemia time of the grafts are responsible for the method and timing of the evaluation of an organs’ suitability. In transplant activity, the zero risk for infections and tumor diseases transmission Transplantation • Volume 88, Number 7S, October 15, 2009 does not exist despite correct application of international guidelines. Despite these limits, all the organs targeted for transplantation must be of acceptable quality and must not expose the receivers to unacceptable risks (15). The levels of risk are classified as unacceptable, increased but acceptable, calculated, unevaluated and standard risk. For increased risk cases, the receiver’s, informed consent is necessary. The process of organ suitability evaluation is multidisciplinary and involves the intensivist, the coordinating centers, the National Transplant Center experts (second-opinion) and the transplant surgical teams in the operating theater. The standard evaluation is based on medical history, clinical examination, instrumental and laboratory tests and eventual histological or postmortem examinations (15). Legal Aspects The anesthesiologist takes part in the process of brain death declaration. In Italy, the diagnosis of brain death is governed by the laws dated December 29, 1993 and August 22, 1994 (16, 17). These laws were updated in April 2008. Clinical and instrumental requirements are necessary for brain death diagnosis. The clinical examination remains the standard for the determination of brain death but Italian law requires that a compulsory instrumental tool, which is the electroencephalography (EEG) must be performed. The EEG and clinical examination must be performed twice during the period of brain death diagnosis by three physicians (a legal medicine specialist, an anesthesiologist and a neurophysiologist, neurologist or neurosurgeon with expertise in EEG) (18). The clinical examination includes the assessment of coma state, the absence of brain-stem reflexes and the absence of respiratory drive at a PaCO2 that is 60 mm Hg. In addition, some prerequisites must be established; the cause of coma, the ascertainment of irreversibility and the absence of possible confounding factors, such as particularly severe electrolyte, acid-base, or endocrine disturbances; the absence of severe hypothermia, hypotension or drug intoxication, poisoning or neuromuscular blocking agents (19). Confirmatory tests of brain death may be necessary in some special cases. These confirmatory tests are instrumental research of the lack of cerebral blood flow. Nowadays, the most accepted tests are cerebral angiography, transcranial doppler ultrasonography and single photon emission computed tomography. The lack of cerebral blood flow must be performed if the patient is a child under the age of one or cofounding factors are present (see above), the cause of coma is unknown or conditions that prevent brain-stem reflexes exploration or EEG performance are present (19, 20). Communication Aspects The carefulness of communicative and relational aspects with the potential donor’s family must be similar to that which is applied to the families of patients admitted to the intensive care unit. This is a process that involves all the intensive care unit staff and it is based on a relationship of trust dependent on the level of transparence, consistency and clarity of communication. The relationship between the anesthesiologist and the family begins at the moment of the patient’s admission to the ICU and continues until the communication of the patient’s death to the family. rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/ztr2748-09a angnes Sⴝ46 9/11/09 4:43 Art: TP201180 Input-mn S143 © 2009 Lippincott Williams & Wilkins FIGURE 1. Management of the hemodynamic instability of potential organ donors. Modified from several authors (10,12,14). The proposal of donating must be put forward by the local transplant coordinator at a different time to when the patient’s death is communicated to the family. Sometime later, the family is informed of the result of the organ transplantation by the local coordinator (21). 3. 4. 5. 6. 7. Conclusion Society is the protagonist in the donation and transplantation process and everyone must work together so that nobody dies waiting for an organ. The anesthesiologist has a fundamental role in the donation transplant process because he works on the front line and is charged with clinical, organizational, legal and relational duties. The anesthesiologist above all is an impartial figure with respect to the transplant and the allocation of organs, and for these reasons, he is indispensable for the transparency of the entire process. 12. References 13. 1. 2. Teasdale G, Jennett B. Assesment of coma and impaired consciousness. A practical scale. Lancet 1974; 2: 81. The Multi-Society task force on Persistent Vegetative State. Medical aspects of the persistent vegetative state—First of two parts. N Engl J Med 1995; 330: 1499. 8. 9. 10. 11. 14. Verlicchi A, Zanotti B. Il coma and co. New Magazine 1999, pp 18. Jennett B, Bond M. Assesment of outcome after severe brain damage. Lancet 1975; 1: 480. Jennett B, Plum F. Persistent vegetative state after brain damage: A syndrome in search of a name. Lancet 1972; 1: 734. Verlicchi A, Zanotti B. Il coma and co. New Magazine 1999, pp 175. A definition of irreversible coma. Report of the Ad Hoc Committee of the Harvard medical School to examinate the definition of brain death. JAMA 1968; 205: 337. Sheehy E, Conrad SL, Brigham LE, et al. Estimating the number of potential donors in United States. N Engl J Med 2003; 349: 667. Giordano F, Margarit O, Di Silvestre A, et al. Gestione del donatore d’organi. In:Atti del corso postuniversitario F.E.E.A. Linee guida in medicina intensiva e dell’emergenza. Lignano 2000. Martini C, Lusenti F, De Angelis C, Procaccio F, et al. Trattamento del potenziale donatore. In: Procaccio F, Ghirardini A, Nanni Costa A, eds. Manuale del corso nazionale per coordinatori alla donazione e prelievo di organi e tessuti (4 Ed). Bologna, Editrice Compositori 2002, pp 95. Tufano R, De Robertis E. Organ donor and health policy: The anaesthesia and reanimation. Minerva Anestesiol 2004; 70: 131. Wood KE, Becker BN, McCartney JG, et al. Care of potential donor. N Engl J Med 2004; 351: 2730. Giordano F, Martinez B. “Standard of care” per la terapia di supporto del donatore d’organo. Minerva Anestesiol 2005; 71(suppl 1): 323. Zaroff JG, Rosengard BR, Armstrong WF, et al. Consensus conference report. Maximizing use of organs recovered from the cadaver donor: Cardiac recommendations, March 28 –29, 2001, Crystal City, Va. Circulation 2002; 106: 836. rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/ztr2748-09a angnes Sⴝ46 9/11/09 4:43 Art: TP201180 Input-mn S144 | 15. 16. 17. 18. 19. 20. www.transplantjournal.com General criteria for organs’ suitability evaluation. Consulta Nazionale Trapianti e Centro nazionale trapianti guidelines September 2003. In: Procaccio F, Manyalich M, Venettoni S, et al. Manuale del corso nazionale per coordinatori alla donazione e prelievo di organi e tessuti [ed 5]. Bologna, Editrice Compositori 2004, pp 66. Legge 29 Dicembre 1993 n. 578 “Norme sull’accertamento e certificazione della morte.” Decreto 22 Agosto 1994 n. 582 1994 “Regolamento recante le modalità per l’accertamento e la certificazione della morte.” Gianelli Castiglione A. Accertamento di morte. In: Procaccio F, Manyalich M, Venettoni S, et al. Manuale del corso nazionale per coordinatori alla donazione e prelievo di organi e tessuti [ed 5]. Bologna, Editrice Compositori 2004, pp 168. Wijdicks EF. The diagnosis of brain death. N Engl J Med 2001; 334: 1215. Commision of Italian National Transplant Consultants. Guidelines for cerebral blood instrumental diagnostic tools application in order to Transplantation • Volume 88, Number 7S, October 15, 2009 21. 22. 23. establish brain death in patients with encephalic lesions. 2003 (Gruppo di lavoro della Consulta Nazionale per I Trapianti. Linee guida relative all’applicazione delle indagini strumentali di flusso ematico cerebrale in situazioni particolari, ai fini della diagnosi di morte in soggetti affetti da lesioni encefaliche). www.trapianti.ministerosalute.it/imgs/C_17_ normativa_506_allegato.pdf. Feltrin A, Sommacampagna M. La relazione d’aiuto alle famiglie dei donator: una modalità operative. In: Procaccio F, Manyalich M, Venettoni S, Nanni Costa A. Manuale del corso nazionale per coordinatori alla donazione e prelievo di organi e tessuti [ed 5]. Bologna, Editrice Compositori 2004, pp 222. King JT Jr, Carlier PM, Marion DW. Early Glasgow Outcome scale scores predict long-term functional outcome in patients with severe traumatic brain injury. J Neurotrauma 2005; 22: 947. deGuise E, leBlanc J, Feyz M, et al. Long term outcome after severe traumatic brain injury: the McGill interdisciplinary prospective study. J Head Trauma Rehabil 2008; 23: 294. Promotion of the Organ Donation Culture SPECIFIC PASTORAL INITIATIVES sanitary projects”. These two objectives highlight the commitment to focus on life and human solidarity. Marco Brunetti The Role of the Church Donating organs means giving a part of ourselves. This gift can be traced in the bible where John, in his first letter, states: “We know love by this, that He laid down His life for us” 1John 3:16. These words summarize the love movement that characterizes the relationship between God and men. It is from this kind of donation, above all, of the Son Jesus, that every Christian should look up to becoming a gift for his own brothers and sisters who are made vulnerable by suffering. One of the key expressions of solidarity is properly constituted in organ donation, which is a true, proper, authentic and efficient gift of oneself for the service of life. It is about instilling a mindset of self-donation, among other various possible forms. Organ donation is an authentic, inclusive act of solidarity: above all it is a civil act—and I believe in this we could have a common agreement between believers and nonbelievers— but also Christian, which gives an added value to give to this self donation in the context of Christian faith. Now, to facilitate the development of the theme, I would like to introduce a pastoral project draft focusing on some initiatives linked to the donation of organs. Pastoral Goals on Various Initiatives Such objectives can be extracted from the notes of the Italian Episcopal Conference (CEI) Pastoral Report related to Pastoral Health Care, entitled “La Pastorale della Salute nella chiesa Italiana” (Health Pastoral Care in the Italian Church), released in 1989, which—at number 20 —sets among its pastoral objectives those of “performing health and moral education with the prospect of inestimable value of life from birth to death” and again, “creating awareness among institutions and pastoral organisations present in the territory of the health problem and providing assistance to the sick, indicating operative guidelines toward a responsible involvement in socialThe author declares no conflict of interest. Those Involved in Animating and Proposing Pastoral Initiatives Entities involved in this education commitment may be identified in some ecclesiastical personalities or representatives such as: The Bishop who, as the shepherd in his diocese, preeminently carries out the role of a teacher, hence educator, of the community entrusted to him. A Bishop’s unequivocal statement regarding the subject of organ donation could help many consciences to decide on this issue. Offices set up for Pastoral Care of Health, which are a point of reference—and to some extent the operative hand, promote and amplify all the pastoral initiatives of a diocese aimed at promoting the culture of giving in favor of life. Spiritual care assistants in hospitals have a more difficult task with regards to other pastoral care personalities; the difficult task of consoling people, mostly hard hit, whose relatives often pass their time in an intensive care unit waiting room. At times, such spiritual assistants are called upon to lend a shoulder to a distressed relative who has just learnt of the death of their loved one, and it’s precisely at these crisis times that one needs the capacity to exercise the ministry of consolation but also to be able to propose, with due sensitivity, the possible removal of organs, thus transforming a moment of grief into a reason for life and hope for the organ receiver, who will have the possibility to continue living, thanks to such gift. Parishes, Associations and Formation Schools are important pastoral vectors, as during catechesis and spiritual preparation and formation, they can transmit fundamental messages to reach the motivated in order to make a decision about donating. These are doubtlessly the main pastoral entities assigned to deliver pastoral initiatives aimed at spreading the organ donation culture. rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/ztr2748-09a angnes Sⴝ46 9/11/09 4:43 Art: TP201180 Input-mn © 2009 Lippincott Williams & Wilkins Suitable Places for Spreading Specific Pastoral Initiatives The most suitable places for introducing and spreading pastoral initiatives, regarding the mentality in favor of organdonation, are as follows: The Parish, which through its numerous occasions, is definitely a privileged place; easily accessible to everyone with simplicity but deeply rooted. Health care institutions, especially hospitals, are authentic “human meeting points” in which it is possible to elaborate on, with diverse initiatives, even in strictly scientific issues, the matters related to donating one’s organs. Formation courses, of university value and nonuniversity level, for example the masters degree in Bioethics, where issues regarding donation of organs, both at scientific and ethical levels, are deemed of vital importance aimed at preparation of some actual formators about open conscience of self-giving, including one’s organs. Identifying the Object of Such Awareness It is also important to define a wide spectrum of possibilities susceptible to an awareness campaign, including all possibilities—starting from blood donation, organ donation and up to donating one’s body for scientific research purposes—as hoped for by St. Francis de Sales. Obviously, each of these donations requires different musings and diverse in-depth analysis, but preparation provided for gradual awareness may help in making ethical and responsible decisions for the good of the entire humanity. The Experience of the Diocese of Turin and Piedmont Region I now prepare myself to describe some concrete initiatives already implemented in the Diocese of Turin, to which I belong and work, by trying to show how the roadmap described earlier was accomplished. The initiatives that I am presenting to you vary in form and intensity and were performed in conjunction with the Pastoral Offices for health as well as civil and health authorities, thus creating the network required for implementing the initiatives: A. February 8, 2003, Diocesan Congress “Giving out oneself. The donation of organs”. The congress, promoted by the Archdiocese of Turin in conjunction with “Piccola Casa della Divina Provvidenza” (Little House of Divine Providence – Cottolengo) and “S. Camillo” (Camillian) Formation Centre, was purposely held in a public venue—“A. Dogliotti” Conference Centre at the “Molinette” hospital in Turin, and was sponsored by the Region of Piedmont, Turin City Municipality and “Azienda Sanitaria Ospedaliera San Giovanni Battista” (St. John the Baptist Hospital Enterprise) in Turin. The event was a great success with approximately 500 guests, including health and pastoral workers, of the Diocese. Experts intervened on various aspects of the subject; professionals expressed opinions as did scientists, doctors, ethics and Christian moral experts, as well as volunteers representing associations of this field. The Cardinal Archbishop closed the event. S145 This initiative, meticulously prepared over a long period of time, had a positive impact on the territorial and pastoral setup of the diocese, highlighting the Church’s existing attention on these issues. B. Explanatory pamphlet. This other initiative, repeated several times, was performed in a joint effort between the regional coordination of organs and tissues removal of Piedmont Region and the Regional Consult for pastoral care for health of Piedmont Episcopal Conference, and consisted of sending an organ donation explanatory pamphlet to all Piedmont and Valle d’Aosta Parishes with the aim of enlightening and promoting a conscious choice. Together with the pamphlet— mainly scientific—were some declarations of the Church’s teachings regarding the matter accompanied by a request, directed to the Parish Priests, to distribute it on a given Sunday after having talked about it to the faithful present at the Eucharistic celebrations. Parish Priests welcomed the initiative and distributed thousands of pamphlets. C. Masters degree in Bioethics. A third pastoral initiative is centered within the masters degree in Bioethics promoted in conjunction with the Archdiocese of Turin, Association of Catholic Doctors and with the sponsorship of the Faculty of Medicine, Turin University, Turin’s Faculty of Theology for Northern Italy and Turin parallel section, which had its first edition in the 2006/2007 academic year and is currently in operation. During the first year of the programmed biennium, an entire section is dedicated to the organ transplant, with analysis of the scientific and ethical aspects entailed, regarding both removal and organ transplant. Bearing in mind that the number of students enrolled for each masters degree is about 200, it is possible to guess the potential impact that such targeted information would carry. D. The conference: “I trapianti fra scienza ed etica” (Science and ethics with regard to transplants). Another formational event entitled “I trapianti fra scienza ed etica” (Science and ethics with regard to transplants) was promoted by the S. Giovanni Battista Hospital in Turin in May 2007, with the sponsorship of various institutional, scientific and ecclesiastic entities, whose event attained an Educazione Continua in Medicina (continuous medical education) accreditation from all health professions, hence a great success too for this event. The conference lasted 3 days, and both scientific and ethical issues were analyzed in an exhaustive and unbiased manner, with an educational impact on all the fields represented by the participants. Conclusions My aim was to outline a base project roadmap, in such a manner, as to take into account all the main elements required to build pastoral initiatives concerning donation of organs. The Turin experience shows that in a pastoral sphere, and by other various ways and means, some action can be promoted, proposed and set in motion. I would like to conclude with the words expressed by the Cardinal Archbishop of Turin at the end of the aforementioned 2003 conference; “We should consider organ donation as one of the utmost expressions of love. You have referred to it as solidarity, but we Christians know that Jesus Christ called rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/ztr2748-09a angnes Sⴝ46 9/11/09 4:43 Art: TP201180 Input-mn S146 | www.transplantjournal.com upon us to consider that the entire Law and Prophets is summarized in God’s commandment of love for our brethren. Thus, organ donation is therefore an act of love; a great act of love” (Card. Severino Poletto). TRAINING OF HEALTH CARE PROFESSIONALS Martí Manyalich, Gloria Páez, and Ricardo Valero uring the past 20 years, health care policies and individual programs have tried to analyze the different possible factors that could influence organ donation numbers positively. Besides comparing the different legislation systems, no real evidence was identified, as such, for better outcomes in the cases of presumed consent versus explicit informed consent. Other possible causes could be identified according to center or country-based analysis: donor detection, professional training or absence of clear guidelines (1, 2). Advanced education has been seen as a possible solution to tackle the unfavourable donation rates and as a possible factor that could influence donation rates at different levels within the healthcare area (3–5). The organ donor process still needs a multidisciplinary, advanced approach to maintain quality and safety. To explain and motivate the professionals involved in the organ and tissue donation process, different training courses have been held (6, 7). Therefore, most of the undertaken actions have often been isolated within one system or country, which could lead to only local or regional factors being identified and analyzed. Based on the analysis of the donors per million population rates, a large variability was seen between different countries. Even countries with similar types of healthcare systems showed dramatic differences. Over the last 10 years, Spain has showed to be number one worldwide in generating organ donors per million population, averaging around 35 donors pmp. Despite different, often very expensive analysis and approaches, no other country has achieved these rates. This has led to what people in the professional environment would call the “Spanish Model”. Analyzing this model has shown that, besides the strong motivation and publicity for the need of organs for the society, education has always been an essential element in the entire process (3, 4, 8, 9). In 1991, a group of professionals founded the Transplant Procurement Management (TPM) Project. The TPM was a pioneering program, initially started in Spain, in response to the need of well-trained transplant coordinators. Since 1991, the course contents have been constantly reevaluated and adapted to meet the educational needs. The “Vital Circle” theory, initially introduced during the development of the TPM projects, highlights the fact that organ donation and transplantation is a part of society and organs are societal goods. D Purpose The TPM educational project provides the participants with the knowledge and skills required to understand the process and to guide all possible professionals involved in the donation process. The final goal is to generate more organs and tissues, ensuring that they are effectively obtained, preserved and distributed, as well as Transplantation • Volume 88, Number 7S, October 15, 2009 guaranteeing quality and transparency throughout the entire process. Following is a report on the evaluation of TPM courses, with relevant information on the total number of courses, educational methodology and participant’ profiles, according to the objectives established for each of the theoretical or practical sessions, teaching program assessment results, practical simulations and technical organization. The purpose is not only to analyze what type of courses have been held throughout the last 17 years, but also to evaluate at which levels these types of courses meet the needs for formation and permanent awareness required to increase organ donor rates. Methods A retrospective and descriptive analysis was carried out to map and evaluate the educational programs implemented by the TPM project. Since 1991, seven crucial points have been identified which provide the best possible education and training. Initially, based on the learning through experience model, the courses were organized around the transplant coordination activity with a general program. Today, a clearly defined program is carried out at different levels within the organ donation process and within communities significantly impacting potental donor rates. With the intention to increase donor rates, TPM has designed different kinds of courses adapted to local, national and international educational needs, medical practices and current laws. Course Methodology Basic knowledge includes topics of donor detection, identification and selection, brain death diagnosis, maintenance of brain death donors, family approach, organ retrieval and sharing, recipient selection, tissue recovery, processing and distribution, the quality control of the donation process, the organization of a transplant coordination office and a global view of the ethical and legal aspects of the process. Advanced courses are organized with a broad subject base, structured in different modules. Theoretical sessions are followed by practical sessions. TPM facilitates the development of proactive experimentation with training provided by means of the relevant simulations. Instruction and practice are a further step to complementing the previous skills. The results have been analyzed according to the type of course, professional profiles and course assessment. The faculty is formed by professionals with conceptual and practical knowhow in the field of donation and transplantation. In general, the teacher or participant ratio is close to 1:1, which enables a more personalized training and teaching. Assessments of the educational program followed by participants (advanced, intermediate and introductory courses) have shown compliance with teaching objectives. Theoretical contents are rated 4.1 as an average (rating 1–5) with regards to content, presentation and ability to answer questions during theoretical classes. The know-how acquired by the participants was assessed by means of a self evaluation test. The percentage of correct answers exceeded 75%. Practical skills assessed through direct observation showed an average of 8.1 (rating 1–10). rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/ztr2748-09a angnes Sⴝ46 9/11/09 4:43 Art: TP201180 Input-mn © 2009 Lippincott Williams & Wilkins Results TPM National Training Courses In 1991, a national face-to-face course was launched under the name of TPM at the University of Barcelona. Within the course, three different levels were identified to meet the needs of different levels of professionalization in the process of organ and tissue donation and transplantation: “Introductory Courses” were designed to empower active detection of donors in the hospital setting; “New Life Cycle Courses” were designed to promote a positive attitude with regards to donation; “Advanced Courses” were designed to train specialized professionals in the field. TPM Fellowship Programs In 1994, TPM, based on needs analysis and also on the increased success of its program at a national level, started training people worldwide. Every year since, professionals from all around the world have been invited to an international advanced course, which is held in Barcelona, Spain. Since 1994, TPM has coordinated numerous international courses, providing truly international training. Moreover, participants can apply for a prolonged 2-month training stage in the frame of the Intercatt Project, involving several transplant centers in Spain. This was already in place for national purposes, but has been enlarged to an international level. TPM Training Courses Within a Country Since 1997, Italy and since 2006, France, have organized, under the management of TPM, their own national training courses on transplant coordination adapted to their systems. The methodology of the international training course was projected inside a national system, but with the same elements as the advanced international TPM course. In addition, managers of the national courses within those countries also joined the international advanced courses in Barcelona, mainly to fine-tune and optimize the national courses for their country, together with the educational staff of TPM. A well-defined balance of national and international teaching staff was performed. Since 1997, 24 Italian courses with 1032 participants, and since 2006, six French courses with 267 participants, were developed. On top of this, a few short introductory courses were designed and implemented in different countries. TPM e-Learning Programs The e-learning program was launched in 2002, with the intention of overcoming the time and geographical barriers and of facing the technological developments in the educational area. The use of the internet as the basic transmission channel of knowledge facilitates individualized and interactive contact between all members of the virtual community. The learning method used in the TPM online courses is highly interactive. Moreover, each course develops a core structure with factual information based on written materials (structured in modules) and audiovisual support, which promotes learning by emphasizing the key concepts. This also invites both participants and teachers to actively contribute and discuss different aspects of the course contents through open forum debates. The participants are supported throughout S147 their learning process by a team of trained tutors. Eight different modules have been created so far, covering the whole process of organ and tissue donation: (1) Donor detection system; (2) Brain death diagnosis; (3) Donor management and organ viability; (4) Family approach for organ donation; (5) Organ retrieval organization; (6) Preservation and allocation criteria; (7) International online tissue banking course; and (8) Training for trainers (the last one, in the frame of the European Training Program on Organ Donation Project), with a total number of 671 participants trained from 59 countries. PIERDUB Project In 2006, a new project was created at the Medical School of the University of Barcelona to educate and motivate medical, healthcare science and other university students in the field of donation and transplantation. From the philosophy that the organ donation principle can only be successful if a wide trust within the entire health care related community is secured, three different training phases, within organ donation and transplantation, were designed: (1) Train the trainers by giving theoretical and practical training to medical students; (2) Training of health science related faculties and others within Spain; and (3) Research projects to evaluate methodology and impact of this training towards attitudes. Since 2006, 240 trainers and students were trained within five schools across the country. At the end of 2008, 600 questionnaires had been revised. TPM International Masters on Transplantation of Organs, Tissues and Cells The international master program was designed in 2005 and is based on 15 years experience of training professionals, around the world, within the field of organ and tissue donation and transplantation. It was created to provide specific education that benefits those professionals working as transplant coordinators, by developing an updated educational program and issuing a masters university degree. Its aim is to complete the health professionals’ training on transplant coordination, tissue banking and cell therapy research by having them complete a 1-year training and education program and writing an applicable research project. Moreover, participants attend clinical sessions and an online module to create a network to facilitate communication among the participants from different countries. To date, there has been one edition in English, with a total of three participants, three editions in Spanish, with 37 participants and four editions in Italian, with 55 participants. European Training Program on Organ Donation Project The project’s aims were to validate a professional training program on organ donation at different professional levels, to contribute to increased organ donation knowledge, to maximize the growth of organ donation rates and to disseminate reliable information to the community. The execution of the project is being carried out through 17 countries and 20 partner organization representatives in 25 target areas. rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/ztr2748-09a angnes Sⴝ46 9/11/09 4:43 Art: TP201180 Input-mn S148 | www.transplantjournal.com The methodology of the project responds to the cycle of: Analysis of the country’s current situation; Designing a training program adapted to the needs, validation and implementation of the program; Follow-up; Evaluation and finally; Analysis of its transferability, observing again the country’s current situation. Within this framework, the learning methodology to implement the European Training Program on Organ Donation is based on two modalities: blended learning and faceto-face training. To date, 51 Senior Transplant Coordinators have been trained through Training for Trainers; 45 essentials in organ donation seminars have been carried out; 49 Junior Transplant Coordinators have been trained in the Professional Training on Organ Donation Program; and 23 Transplant Area Managers have attended Organ Donation Quality Managers Training. Overall, results show that since 1991, 66 advanced courses have been held, with 2915 participants. Fifty-six introductory courses, with 2523 participants and 15 intermediate, with 501 attendees, were developed. Participants of the advanced courses came from Europe (2462; 660 from Spain), America (317, mostly from Latin America), Asia, Africa and Australia (136). In advanced courses, the professional profile of the majority of participants was medical doctor (from 49% to 90% depending on the courses), followed by nursing (13% to 49%) and other professions, such as psychology and biology, among others. More nursing professionals participated in introductory courses. In advanced courses, the most common medical speciality was anaesthesiology (from 4% to 54%, depending on the course), followed by intensive care medicine (7% to 46%) and transplant coordinator (8%–30%). The rest of the pupils correspond to a great variety of medical specialities, such as cardiology, general surgery, emergencies and neurology. Forty-one percent of the participants in Spanish courses and 17% in English courses had no previous experience in transplant coordination. The faculty was formed by professionals with conceptual and practical know-how in the field of transplants. In general, the teacher/pupil ratio was close to 1:1, which enabled more personalised treatment in each course. Assessment of the educational program followed by participants (advanced and introductory courses) showed compliance with teaching objectives. Theoretical contents were valued more than 4.1 as an average (rating 1–5) with regards to content, presentation and ability to answer questions made in theoretical classes. The know-how acquired by the participants was assessed by means of a self evaluation test. The percentage of correct answers exceeded 75%. Practical skills assessed through direct observation showed an average of 8.1 (rating 1–10). Conclusions The professionalization of transplant coordination can be achieved with suitable training. The TPM educational program offers its participants a wide range of necessary knowhow and skills to build their competences in the donation of organs and tissues for transplant. Health professionals and international organisations concerned about the scarcity of Transplantation • Volume 88, Number 7S, October 15, 2009 organs may find TPM a useful tool for their training and consequent work as transplant coordinators. Based on this, the two essential elements for healthcare-related professionals to understand and be motivated to perform them in their jobs are highly developed within the different TPM training modules. Organ donation and transplantation within society needs a multilevelled approach to be able to tackle organ donation issues at different levels. Motivation and ability to perform well can only be reached if both professionals and the general public understand the different elements of the process (10). It has been shown that advanced education positively contributes to the motivation and ability of professionals working in the field of organ donation and transplantation (11). TPM educational project has also highlighted, in all its trainings, the need for a multidisciplinary approach, in which different medical and nonmedical professionals have been trained. Professionals ranging from medical doctors and nurses to health care administrators were trained over the past 17 years at regional, national and international levels. This unique mixture of different disciplines, with different experience levels, provided teachers and students with the skills to analyze elements related to organ and tissue donation as well as transplantation. The teaching methodology of close to 1:1 teacher-student ratio created a unique way of problem-solving teaching, and the fact that students had no threshold to pose questions and give remarks on subjects related to the course. From a unique experience built up over the last 17 years, the TPM project has become the largest international education program in organ and tissue donation and transplantation. TPM has also opened doors to third world countries and countries seeking help to get their systems optimized and developed, to be able to perform well on a national basis. Within the TPM project, the students are quoted to be of extreme value and are widely invited to share their experiences, no matter if they have had an extensive or a limited experience. TPM educational projects are supported by a professional international staff of teachers and collaborative centers who build the bridge between educational needs in the specialized field of organ and tissue donation with the need for improving results. But still, the enormous gap between different countries in donor numbers remains the main drive behind these courses; to perform better from sharing experiences at an international level. Furthermore, the TPM project’s ambition for the future is to create a new masters degree, so that scientific value can be given to all those professionals working in this field and doing research. Acknowledgments The authors would like to thank F. Van Gelder for the scientific consultancy and Mediconed Consultancy, for advice and support writing the article and analyzing the methodology. References 1. 2. 3. Manyalich M, Cabrer C, García-Fages LC, et al. Training the transplant procurement management (TPM) coordinator. In: Touraine JL, Traeger J, Betuel H, et al, editors. Organ shortage: The solutions. Dordrecht, Kluwer Academic Publishers 1995, pp 191. Manyalich M. Organization of organ donation and role of coordinators: Transplant procurement management. Saudi J Kidney Dis Transplant 1999; 10: 175. Paredes D, Valero R, Navarro A, et al. Transplant Procurement Man- rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/ztr2748-09a angnes Sⴝ46 9/11/09 4:43 Art: TP201180 Input-mn © 2009 Lippincott Williams & Wilkins 4. 5. 6. 7. 8. 9. 10. 11. agement: A training tool to increase donation. Transplant Proc 1999; 31: 2610. Manyalich M, Cabrer C, Valero R, et al. Advanced international training course on transplant coordination. Transplant Proc 1993; 31: 2610. Essman CC, Lebovitz DJ. Donation education for medical students: Enhancing the link between physicians and procurment professionals. Prog transplant 2005; 15: 124. Kiberd C. Curriculum effect on nursingh students’ attitudes and knowledge towards organ donation and transplantation. ANNA J 1998; 25: 210; discussion 217. Jacoby L, Crosier V, Pohl H. Providing support to families considering the option of organ donation: An innovative training method. Prog Transplant 2006; 16: 247. Van Gelder F, Van Hees D, de Roey J, et al. Implementation of an intervention plan designed to optimize donor referral in a donor hospital network. Prog Transplant 2006; 16: 46. Dubois JM, Anderson EE. Attitudes towards death crietria and organ donation among healthcare personnel and the general public. Prog Transplant 2006; 16: 65. Williams MA, Lipsett PA, Rushton CH, et al. The physician’s role in discussing organ donation with families. Crit Care Med 2003; 31: 1568. Elding C, Scholes J. Organ and tissue donation: A trustwide perspective or critical care concern? Nurs Crit Care 2005; 1053: 129. GLOBAL APPROACHES TO ORGAN SHORTAGE Rafael Matesanz, Elisabeth Coll, Beatriz Dominguez-Gil, Beatriz Mahillo, Eduardo Martin Escobar, and Gregorio Garrido rgan transplantation has progressively become the best, and sometimes the unique, therapeutic alternative for patients with end-stage organ failure as well as many other life-limiting conditions. Thanks to the continuous improvement of immunosuppressive therapies and surgical techniques, transplantation today no longer represents an experimental procedure, but a well-established clinical therapy, which saves the lives or enhances the quality of life of thousands of patients every year. According to estimations from The Global Observatory of Donation and Transplantation (1), there are almost 100,000 solid organ transplants performed annually all around the world. The impressive evolution of organ transplantation activity in a 50-year period is greatly related to the extraordinary results obtained with this therapy, which have progressively improved for the different types of solid organ transplants (2– 4). These results are well represented by the longest survivals described by Cecka and Terasaki (5) for transplanted patients: up to 45, 38 and 29 years for a kidney, a liver and a heart transplant recipient, respectively. However, these excellent results have led to transplantation becoming a victim of its own success. Organ shortage is a universal problem that precludes transplantation from developing to its maximum potential and is related to a wide set of individual and global consequences. O The Figures of Organ Shortage Difficulty in obtaining accurate and transparent figures of transplantation activity is highly increased when we reach the point of analyzing the needs. There is no accurate global The authors declare no conflict of interest. S149 estimate for the number of patients on the waiting list for a transplant, but a simple calculation can be performed by extrapolating the number of patients on the list in Spain (6) to the world population, assuming the same criteria applied. The result would be no less than 1 million people potentially benefiting from organ transplantation each year: 10-fold the estimated number of transplanted patients (1). However, it is clear that any approach to the number of patients on the waiting list is always an underestimation of the needs. Focusing on the kidney, end-stage renal disease (ESRD) has become a universal health problem, with more than one and a half million patients on dialysis therapy (Luc Noel, personal communication) and 66,000 kidney transplants performed each year (1) (Fig. 1). However, there are marked differences in the number of patients per million population accepted for renal replacement therapy in the different parts of the world (7). These differences might be partially explained by epidemiological aspects (as is the case of Japan) but mainly by economical reasons. Hence, demand is well above the supply of organs for transplantation, according to current figures that possibly underestimate the real needs. Finally, demand is expected to increase in the near future, particularly for kidney transplantation. It has been estimated that the number of patients with diabetes mellitus will double from the year 2000 to 2030, especially in developing countries (8). This 21st century pandemic of diabetes, added to the ageing of the population, arterial hypertension and obesity, is expected to significantly impact the prevalence of ESRD across the world and hence the need for kidneys for transplantation. F1 Consequences of Organ Shortage The most important and obvious consequence of organ shortage is the fact that many patients will never be placed on the waiting list, and many will die or deteriorate whilst waiting for an organ. No less than 1 million people die every year in the context of ESRD without adequate therapy all over the world (Luc Noel, personal communication). Another important problem derived from the shortage is the cost to the systems of alternative renal replacement C O L O R FIGURE 1. Kidney transplants. Annual global estimates (per million population [pmp]). Percentage living/total kidney transplants. rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/ztr2748-09a angnes Sⴝ46 9/11/09 4:43 Art: TP201180 Input-mn S150 | www.transplantjournal.com therapies, i.e., dialysis, to kidney transplantation. Lysaght (9) predicted the total cost of dialysis in the world would be U.S. $1200 billion for the decade 2000 to 2010, probably underestimated. In Spain, Italy and Western Europe in general, renal replacement therapy represents 2% to 2.5% of all health expenses. The total therapy cost per patient in dialysis, per year, in the European Union is approximately €50,000 (U.S. $70,830). Kidney transplantation has proven to have a more favorable cost effectiveness ratio than dialysis. It is related to better results in terms of survival (10) and quality of life (11). In addition, depending on the country, the cost of kidney transplantation can be offset in 2 to 4 years when compared to dialysis. This has been clearly proven in Europe, the United States, and also in countries like Pakistan, where renal transplantation remains being the best and least expensive renal replacement therapy (12, 13). Organ Shortage and Transplant Commercialization Desperation of patients waiting to be transplanted, at a time of organ shortage, derives in another dramatic consequence; the development of criminal practices, such as organ trafficking and the progressively better known phenomenon of transplant tourism. Transplant tourism is defined as the movement of organs, donors, recipients or transplant professionals across jurisdictional borders for transplantation purposes (involving organ trafficking and transplant commercialism), if the resources devoted to providing transplants to patients from outside a country undermine the country’s ability to provide transplant services for its own population (14). This phenomenon has emerged due to a lack of organs, as an immediate solution for patients in need and in the extreme context of an extremely unequal distribution of wealth, with 20% of the world’s population controlling 80% of global resources. Not by chance, the most usual practice is represented by the movement of patients from rich to poor countries, profiling a “North to South” flow in which wealthy patients, in their desperation for finding an organ, travel to developing countries where the donor, usually a vulnerable and poor person, agrees to sell a kidney to solve his, also desperate, economical situation (15). These practices also have one of their main roots in results related to living kidney transplantation, in particular, to better outcome results in terms of patient and graft survival than deceased kidney transplantation. Today, these better results are regardless of an existing relationship between donor and recipient (16). Hence, living unrelated kidney transplantation has become a reality with excellent results after advances in immunosuppression have reduced the relative importance of human leukocyte antigen matching for postransplant outcome. Examples of these practices, that have arisen as a modern horror added to the endless series of tragic disasters that affect the whole world, are unfortunately too abundant. Asia, with 60% of the world population, provides no more than 2% to 3% of all deceased organ donors, leading to the proliferation of living transplants performed under the umbrella of different forms of commercialisation. India, Pakistan, Philippines, Egypt and several Latin American countries are recognized as involved in organ trafficking and transplant tourism (15). In China, most of the transplanted organs were alleged Transplantation • Volume 88, Number 7S, October 15, 2009 to have been procured from executed prisoners (17), a practice which has been criticized by the international community, with a quite recent and fortunate compromise of the Chinese Government to stop this practice. Another particular form of commercialization is the Iranian model (18). In this country, nearly 2000 patients receive a kidney transplant from a living donor every year, most of them unrelated. Donors receive some bonus, partially supported by the state and partly by the recipient, in a system which is organized and controlled by nongovernmental organizations and forbidden to foreign citizens. Although criticized by the international community, this system has allowed the country to do away with the kidney transplant waiting list and avoid transplant tourism. Defendants claim that the system cannot be judged from the opulence of Occidental countries. Organ trafficking and transplant tourism violate the most basic of human rights. These practices are also related to safety problems, especially in the case of the living donors, with no guarantee of application of the international safety standards, but also in many recipients transplanted by these means (15). These practices also cause a profound damage to the universal image of donation and transplantation, which generates a climate of distrust toward the system that might contribute even more to the exacerbation of the underlying problem of organ shortages for transplantation. Global Approach to Organ Shortage: The Role of Transplantation Society, WHO and ONT Organ shortage and its consequences, including organ trafficking and transplant tourism, has become a universal problem. The World Health Organization (WHO) estimates that at least 10% of all kidney transplants in the world are performed under some kind of commercialism. Universal problems need global solutions. Some years ago, the WHO, together with The Transplantation Society, initiated a global project to overcome organ shortage and efficiently combat unethical practices. Actions such as the recent generation and wide dissemination of the “The Declaration of Istanbul against transplant tourism and commercialism” (14), are good examples of this global approach. The Spanish Transplant Organization (ONT), an official Collaborating Centre of the WHO, has been actively participating in this process from the very beginning. The mission of the WHO in the area of transplantation is to meet the requirements of the 57th World Health Assembly Resolution (WHA 57.18), regarding Human Organ and Tissue Transplantation (19). Since 2005, the WHO, with the support of Transplantation Society and ONT, began a set of consultations, two of a global scope and several regional consultations, with national health authorities in the different regions of the WHO. These regional consultations have been held in Manila with the countries of Western Pacific, in Karachi with Muslim countries and in Slovenia with the Republics of the old Soviet Union, among others. From the very beginning, the structure, background, stability and experience of ONT was offered to the WHO to support a partnership in developing an International Observatory of Transplantation, a need that was to be covered through the Global Knowledge base on Transplantation (GKT), with four components. GKT1 and GKT2 led to the rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/ztr2748-09a angnes Sⴝ46 9/11/09 4:43 Art: TP201180 Input-mn S151 © 2009 Lippincott Williams & Wilkins TABLE 1. Recommendations and other relevant documents generated by the Iberoamerican network/council on donation and transplantation C O L O R FIGURE 2. Deceased organ donors in Spain, evolution 1989 to 2007. F2 Global Observatory on Donation and Transplantation (http://www.transplant-observatory.org/default.aspx). This observatory, developed by ONT in collaboration with the WHO, has been available since 2007 and provides an interface for health authorities and the general public to access data on donation and transplantation practices and legal frameworks all over the world. The international role of Spain in this field is also the consequence of the successful donation program within the country. Spain has the highest deceased donation rates ever described in the world; double the mean value for the whole European Union. The success of the Spanish system is based on the implementation of a set of measures, mainly of an organizational nature, that is internationally known as the Spanish Model of Donation and Transplantation (20). These measures followed the creation of ONT in 1989 and led Spain to triple the number of organ donors, from 500 to more than 1500 donors in 2007 and more than double the deceased donation rates, from 14 to 34 to 35 donors pmp (Fig. 2), resulting in significant reductions in the number of patients on the waiting lists and their waiting times. The Iberoamerican Example It is in Latin America where the Spanish cooperation is clearly becoming important for obvious historical and linguistic reasons. Spain, in close cooperation with the Panamerican Health Organization, is in charge of the development of Resolution WHA 57.18 (19), through the “Iberoamerican Network/Council of Donation and Transplantation” (Red/Consejo Iberoamericano De Donacion y Trasplantes, RCIDT). The creation of the RCIDT was approved by the Heads of States and Governments at a summit held in Salamanca, Spain in 2005. ONT is in charge of the permanent secretariat of this newly created organization. The mission of the RCIDT, composed by 21 Spanish and Portuguese speaking countries, is the development of cooperation between its members, in terms of organizational, legislative, professional training, ethical and sociological aspects, related to donation and transplantation of organs, cells and tissues in Iberoamerican countries. The RCIDT considers organizational aspects as especially rel- Mar de Plata Declaration. RCIDT 2005 Recommendation Rec RCIDT 2005 (1) on autologous cord blood banks Recommendation Rec RCIDT 2005 (2) on the role and training of professionals responsible for organ donation (transplant donor coordinators) Recommendation Rec RCIDT 2005 (3) on the functions and responsibilities of a national transplant organization Recommendation Rec RCIDT 2005 (4) on quality assurance programmes in the donation process Recommendation Rec RCIDT 2005 (5) on the training plan for training professionals in donation and transplantation Recommendation Rec RCIDT 2006 (6) on solutions to organ shortage (phases of the deceased donation process-areas for improvement) Consensus Document: criteria to prevent the transmission of neoplasic diseases through transplantation Recommendation Rec RCIDT 2007 (7) on guides for the quality and safety of cells and tissues of human origin for transplantation Recommendation Rec RCIDT 2008 (8) on bioethical considerations on donation and transplantation of organs, tissues, and cells Recommendation Rec RCIDT 2008 (9) on harmonization of criteria for the diagnosis of brain death in Iberoamerica Declaration against transplant tourism evant in tackling organ shortage and cooperation indispensable in achieving the maximum effectiveness of the systems. Since its creation in October 2005, the RCIDT has held seven meetings; Mar de Plata (Argentina); Madrid (Spain); Montevideo (Uruguay); Punta Cana (Dominican Republic); Santiago de Chile (Chile); Havana (Cuba); and Mexico DF (Mexico). The group has generated 11 recommendations and consensus documents (Table 1) on relevant aspects on donation and transplantation. As training is considered essential, one specific action developed by the RCIDT has been the development of a whole training program in donation and transplantation activities. Through this ALIANZA Master, professionals appointed by the different health ministries of Iberoamerican countries are trained as transplant coordinators, in Spain. Training seeks to facilitate the translation of the Spanish Model to the Latin American reality. With a 2-month duration of each aspect, these selected professionals each completed a term in the biggest Spanish hospitals, participated in a general coordination training course as well as other specific courses relevant for their training, which were held in Spain during the time of the Master. They had to present a final written project before reaching the final degree of the Master. ALIANZA Master has been performed annually since 2005 and so far 182 professionals have been trained, all of them already working in their countries and many occupying positions of responsibility at a national level (Fig. 3). In parallel to the ALIANZA Master, training courses on specific aspects of the process of deceased donation and transplantation have been held in several American countries. In particular, a program on training of trainers on the commu- T1 F3 rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/ztr2748-09a angnes Sⴝ46 9/11/09 4:43 Art: TP201180 Input-mn S152 | www.transplantjournal.com Transplantation • Volume 88, Number 7S, October 15, 2009 of aspects, such as diagnostic criteria for brain death or clinical evaluation criteria of the possible donors. • RCIDT is progressively becoming a technical, ethical, training and cooperative reference for the development of transplant activities in all the countries within the region. • In addition, deceased donation activities are progressively increasing in countries within the region. The most notable change was detected from the year 2005 to the year 2006. In just one single year, deceased donation activities increased as much as 60% in Colombia, 30% in Cuba, 27% in Venezuela, 22% in Chile, 20% in Uruguay and 11% in Argentina. In 2006, Uruguay achieved deceased donation rates close to those described in the United States (25.1 donors pmp). C O L O R FIGURE 3. Number of participants in the ALIANZA Master according to the country of origin. nication of bad news was held in Argentina, Chile, Colombia, Central America and the Caribbean. In the context of these programs, teams of monitors are being trained who will be able to develop courses in their own countries as well as in others within the region. Finally, courses on quality and safety in the management of tissue banks are also being developed, with wide acceptance and increasing demand, mainly in those countries of the Southern cone. In addition, the running problems of organ trafficking and transplant tourism, which affect some of the countries within the region, were raised at the last meeting of the RCIDT in Havana, May 2008. Since its creation, the RCIDT has expressed its complete opposition to these practices, which facilitate transplant commerce, and has considered them as morally condemnable. In this context, the relevance of the document on bioethical considerations produced by the RCIDT must be highlighted. In countries with problems of organ trafficking and transplant tourism, the RCIDT is providing specific support to those organizations in charge of oversight of donation and transplantation, in order for them to overcome their problems. This support has been documented in the Declaration against Transplant Tourism. As a result of all these processes and of all the activities developed by the RCIDT: • Donation and transplantation organizations have been created, restructured, or revived in countries which were lacking this type of system or where activity was minimal or null. These organizations rely on or are supported by the health authorities, following the Spanish model, and are being organized as a coordination network. • Training activities for coordinators are being consolidated through the ALIANZA Master and courses performed in Iberoamerica, in cooperation with several countries. Training is focused to the different areas within the region and tailored to their specific needs. • Initiatives to harmonize criteria, in agreement with scientific societies and in accordance to international standards, are being developed, focusing on a wide number Conclusions In conclusion, organ shortage is a problem of a universal scope. It has important individual and global consequences. As a universal problem, it must be approached through global initiatives that provide the basic standards and pillars over which locally tailored actions are to be designed and implemented. Although changes in organ donation take time, what the Latin American experience shows is if steps are taken into the right direction everything is possible, even the construction of a successful deceased donation program. References 1. 2. 3. 4. 5. 6. 7. 8. 9. 10. 11. 12. 13. 14. 15. Global Observatory of Donation and Transplantation Website. Available at: http://www.transplant-observatory.org/default.aspx. Accessed October 2008. OPTN/SRTR 2007 Annual Report. OPTN website. Accessible at: www. optn.org. Accessed October 28, 2008. European Liver Transplant Registry website. Available at: http://www. eltr.org. Accessed: October 28, 2008. The International Society for Heart and Lung Transplantation website. Available at: http://www.ishlt.org. Accessed October 28, 2008. Cecka JM, Terasaki PI. Clinical transplantation 2007. Los Angeles, Terasaky Foundation Laboratory 2008. Spanish National Transplant Organization website. Available at: http:// www.ont.es. Accessed: October 28, 2008. Barsoum RS. Chronic kidney disease in the developing world. N Engl J Med 2006; 354: 997. Wild S, Roglic G, Green A, et al. Global prevalence of diabetes: Estimates for the year 2000 and projections for 2030. Diabetes Care 2004; 27: 1047. Lysaght MJ. Maintenance dialysis population dynamics: Current trends and long-term implications. J Am Soc Nephrol 2002; 13(suppl 1): S37. Wolfe RA, Ashby VB, Milford EL, et al. Comparison of mortality in all patients on dialysis, patients on dialysis awaiting transplantation, and recipients of a first cadaveric transplant. N Engl J Med 1999; 341: 1725. Keown P. Improving the quality of life—The New Target for Transplantation. Transplantation 2001; 72(12 suppl): 567. Shakuja V, Sud K. End-stage renal disease in India and Pakistan: Burden of disease and management issues. Kidney Int Suppl 2003: S115. Rizvi SA, Naqvi SA. Need for increasing transplant activity: A sustainable model for developing countries. Transplant Proc 1997; 29: 1560. Steering Committee of the Istanbul Summit. Organ trafficking and transplant tourism and commercialism: The Declaration of Istanbul. Lancet 2008; 372: 5. Shimazono Y. The state of the international organ trade: A provisional picture based on integration of available information. Bull World Health Organ 2007; 85: 955. rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/ztr2748-09a angnes Sⴝ46 9/11/09 4:43 Art: TP201180 Input-mn © 2009 Lippincott Williams & Wilkins 16. 17. 18. 19. 20. Gjertson DW. Look-up survival tables for living-donor renal transplants: OPTN/UNOS data 1995–2002. Clin Transpl 2003: 337. Budiani-Saberi DA, Delmonico FL. Organ trafficking and transplant tourism: A commentary on the global realities. Am J Transplant 2008; 8: 925. Ghods AJ, Mahdavi M. Organ transplantation in Iran. Saudi J Kidney Dis Transpl 2007; 18: 648. Resolution WHA57.18 about Human Organ and Tissue Transplantation. The Fifty-seventh World Health Assembly, May 22, 2004. World Health Organization. Available at: http://www.who.int/gb/ebwha/pdf_ files/WHA57/A57_R18-en.pdf. Accessed October 2008. Matesanz R, Domínguez-Gil B. Strategies to optimize deceased organ donation. Transplant Rev 2007; 21: 177. EDUCATIONAL PROPOSALS FOR PROMOTING A CULTURE OF DONATING ORGANS Felix Cantarovich Defining the Problem: What Needs to be Solved? During the previous decades, society’s behavior with regards to organ donation remains reluctant. A recent study showed that only 42% of potential deceased donors are used in the United States (1). This finding is in agreement with current data showing that the rate of willingness to donate an organ is 38% among young adults in the United States and 42% in Europe (2). Organ shortage is the main reason for the significant number of patients dying on the waiting lists (3, 4). It was mentioned that less than 40% of suitable people offered their organs after death (5). A survey showed that although people plainly accept to offer their organs for transplantation, (6) when a person dies, his or her relatives often refuse donation. To be able to change this ambivalence in the public it is fundamental to search for the reasons of this behavior (7). Review of the literature points towards two groups where actions should be performed to modify barriers for organ donation and transplantation: (a) The patient and the general public and (b) Healthcare professionals (8, 9). Barriers From the Patient and Public Perspective Most of the adverse reactions towards organ donation are due to a lack of information, mixed feelings and prejudice. Doubts About Medical Diagnosis and Treatment Understanding the concept of “brain death” remains a barrier for the family to accept the “use of organs” after the death. It is understandable that relatives without previous reliable information would feel reluctant to believe that the beloved patient is dead whilst seeing the patient breathing, with the heart beating. As well as this, the media publish and comment on “the case of a brain death patient going home” (10 –12). In addition, a very common doubt of the general public is the rigorousness of the patient’s treatment, if he or she is already known as a registered organ donor and the relatives have agreed to organ donation (13). Respect for the Body After Death The ancestral belief that the integrity of the body is necessary to reach eternity (Egyptian mummies) has been The author declares no conflict of interest. S153 transferred by ignorance to present-day faiths, and remains a barrier to donation (14). Lack of Awareness About the Need of Transplants for Thousands of Patients Transplantation is, for many people (including professionals), an uncommon medical practice. It is remarkable that only 53% of individuals prepared to donate organs have informed their family of their wish (15). In addition, the dilemma of increasing waiting lists and patients dying because of organ shortage is not well known by society (16). Healthcare Professionals’ Point of View Intensive care unit doctors face several challenges when confronted with a potential organ donor. Management of Brain Death and Request for Organ Donation Although brain death diagnosis is currently widely accepted, there are still challenges among the medical team (17, 18). In addition, several studies have shown that for many doctors requesting organ donation from the patient’s family is a difficult and, many times, resisted task (19 –21). Increased Work Load Leading to Loss of Interest to Participate in the Process of Organ Donation Several trials focusing on the workload and psychologic stress of intensive care unit doctors and nurses, when working on brain death diagnosis, showed the difficulties experienced by them. The medical team taking part in this task should also be involved in informing the family as well as in the request for organ donation (22–24). As the management of candidates for organ donation is complex, (critical care management, the declaration of brain death, the identification the and request for organ donation from the next of kin), it has been suggested that these patients are best managed in tertiary centers. These centers have professional staff with the expertise and interest in performing these tasks (25). Lack of Appropriate Training to Face the Different Medical, Ethical and Social Issues Related to Organ Donation and Transplantation The aptitude of medical teams, concerning issues of death and organ donation, can make the difference between a family accepting or refusing consent. Families expressed dissatisfaction with inappropriate communication and support when brain death was announced and thereafter when a request for donation was made (26, 27). Polls performed about the decrease in the number of organ donor shows a lack of knowledge among medical teams. Questions on brain death legislation and religious opinions to organ donation were incorrectly answered. When asked, “are brain death and cardiac death the same state (i.e., are both death of the patient)?” 45% of respondents answered “no” (28). The following factors were also reported as barriers for professional participation in organ request: (1) The value and contribution made by donotransplantation; (2) The unique idea of having another’s tissue in one’s own body; (3) The importance of organ donation; (4) The individual’s moral and nurses’ professional rejection of the responsibility for or- rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/ztr2748-09a angnes Sⴝ46 9/11/09 4:43 Art: TP201180 Input-mn S154 | www.transplantjournal.com gan or tissue donation; (5) The postmortem mutilation of the body; and (6) The potential distress donation may cause a bereaved family (29 –32). It was suggested that more knowledge among professionals would implicate larger society’s cooperation in the donation and procurement process (33). A significant correlation was observed between the awareness of transplantation, brain death and organ donation and the workplace (operating room and intensive care unit vs. other areas) (34). How Can Organ Donation and Procurement Be Improved? The persistent organ shortage, the constant increase of patients on waiting lists and the unfair mortality of people waiting for the “Gift of Life” have encouraged searching for alternatives in order to increase the availability of potential donors. The following are the main suggested options: 1. 2. 3. 4. Legal alternatives for consent Economic incentives Expanding donor pool Education The first three proposals aim for a rapid solution. However, their feasibility, ethical and moral acceptance, as well as the medical advantage of each of them, is a matter for discussion. Conversely, education, which could be a potential long-term solution, is largely accepted by society. Education may increase awareness about organ donation sustaining ethical principles (altruism, equality and fairness). How Should a Constructive Educational Project Be Organized? Several surveys investigating awareness of transplantation and organ donation showed a public lack of knowledge and insufficient university training of the medical team (doctors and nurses). This is a long-standing problem that needs to be solved. A structured and intensive educational program might consider the following priorities: a. An active state participation b. A full participation of all the sectors of society c. A change in the message should be considered An Active State Participation An intensive educational activity, structured between the State and the different interested partners (Transplantation community, interested ONGs (Organization NonGovernmental), schools and the university responsible) should be evaluated as a significant mission to be accomplished for the State’s authorities, who are responsible for health and education. The main actions to develop might be; (a) To settle the deficiency concerning donation and transplantation in all educational levels; (b) To develop pilot projects on education and information on organ sharing and donation; and (c) To collaborate with the media to create awareness and enhance public understanding and human solidarity. Transplantation • Volume 88, Number 7S, October 15, 2009 A Full Participation of All Sectors of the Society The public needs unambiguous and persistent information concerning organ donation and transplantation. Also, healthcare professionals present serious deficiencies in their training on transplantation issues. This situation needs to be modified by the educational authority responsible for teaching programs in medical schools. One sector of society that has not been a particular target of education regarding transplantation issues is the youth. The meaning of child education and the potential of teaching the subject of transplantation is remarked by several brilliant educationists, for example, “The purpose of education is to develop the knowledge, skill, or character of students”. “In ancient Greece, Socrates argued that education was about drawing out what was already within the student” (35). “The central task of education is to implant a will and facility for learning; it should produce not learned but learning people. The truly human society is a learning society, where grandparents, parents, and children are students together” (36). “No one has yet realized the wealth of sympathy, the kindness and generosity hidden in the soul of a child. The effort of every true education should be to unlock that treasure” (37). “The young rarely think about their own death or about giving their organs upon death, then they should be constrained and enabled to do so by the institutions, practices and laws we enact” (38). “Teaching young people about organ transplantation is not notably difficult”. “The organ transplant community has to offer strong inducements for teachers in various settings to take up the task”. “Strong persistent education efforts focused specifically on young people seem comparatively rare”. “Helping young people understand the facts about transplants early in life increases the chance of them being sympathetic to the idea of organ donation”. “They are also likely to respond to a teacher’s suggestion to find an occasion to discuss this topic with their families or with their peers, thus multiplying the educational effect” (39). “Education on organ donation is important to reduce organ shortage” (40). “Education and information will enhance the value of altruism protecting people from exploitation and emphasizing the meaning and worth of organ donation” (41). Some of the words of John Paul II in his address to the 18th International Congress of The Transplantation Society, supported the idea of youth education on organ transplantation as a pathway to improve society’s feelings. “There is a need to instill in people’s hearts, especially in the hearts of the young, a genuine and deep appreciation of the need for brotherly love; a love that can find expression in the decision to become an organ donor”. “I am confident that social, political and educational leaders will renew their commitment to fostering a genuine culture of generosity and solidarity” (42). Challenging Educational Programs Conversely, the usefulness of education to change peoples feelings toward organ donation has been criticized by economists that supported economic incentives, for example, Tabarrok considered that, “the public has been barraged with billions of dollars worth of educational campaigns and yet the organ rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/ztr2748-09a angnes Sⴝ46 9/11/09 4:43 Art: TP201180 Input-mn S155 © 2009 Lippincott Williams & Wilkins 3. During life, we have more chances of being an organ recipient than a donor. 4. Organ donation should be a citizen responsibility. 5. The use of organs and tissues for transplantation should be considered as part of a fair agreement between individuals and society. donation rate has remained essentially unchanged for the past decade” (43). Unfortunately, this statement is not entirely accurate, because there have always been reasons responsible for the current failure of education, for example, the media. Information from the media usually contains negative news regarding transplantation. Regrettably, preference is given to inform more anecdotal rather than real issues, for example, recovery from brain death, transfer of personality from donor to recipient, the organs’ black market and corruption in the medical community and the organ allocation system. On the contrary, the media does not give enough information on organ shortage consequences, for example, the increasing waiting lists and the number of people dying every day, or positive information as the attitude of monotheist religions toward deceased organ donation. Last but not least, the media should also use “A Gift of Life” as the message to encourage donation as a gift. Decades of unmodified organ shortage suggests that it should be evoked why, despite such message, many people still reject the idea to make a gift of the organs of their beloved one (44). It is most likely that a well-programmed media campaign, persistently diffused, could have influence in improving society’s attitude toward organ donation and transplantation. Could Education Lead Society to Acknowledge a Different Message? To evaluate this, possibility surveys and practical experiences have been performed. Surveys a. Between the public (n⫽2321) (Fig. 1), from five countries: Argentina, Austria, Brazil, France and Italy. b. Among 139 transplant specialists (abstracts reviewers of the XIX Congress of The Transplantation Society [45, 46]). Both groups considered the suggestion that organ donation means to share a chance of life acceptable. (Fig. 2) Concerning school education, the positive answer was highly significant (Fig. 3). Conversely, an unexpectedly public disinformation was observed with regards to the position of monotheist religions concerning organ transplantation (Fig. 4). A Change of the Message Should Be Considered The practically unchanged behavior of people towards organ donation suggests that the main goal of an educational program should be to improve the message to Society. It is my proposal to include the following ideas in a new message to the public: Practical Essay of Young People Education Young people have not been sufficiently informed about their potential role and their future needs of organ transplantation. It should be critical to define the goals of education of organ transplantation as part of schools’ curriculum; it will be essential to explain facts and updated information on the subject. To assess the impact of education on organ transplantation in elementary and high schools, 45 min class presenta- 1. Organ donation means sharing a chance of life with everybody, including our families. 2. Decease organs are a source of health. n=2321 46% 50 40 30 18% 20 16% 12% 8% 10 0 Argentina FIGURE 1. Survey by country. 100 80 Austria Brazil France 6% 9% 7% 7% 1% 2% No Do not know Other opinion Italy 82% 66% 60 40 2% 20 FIGURE 2. Do you believe that the initiative of sharing organs as a source of life for others may be assumed to be a fair agreement between individuals and society? 0 Yes Public = 2296 Transplantologists = 139 0% May be F1 F2 F3 F4 rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/ztr2748-09a angnes Sⴝ46 9/11/09 4:43 Art: TP201180 Input-mn S156 | www.transplantjournal.com Transplantation • Volume 88, Number 7S, October 15, 2009 120 100 98% 85% 80 Public = 2287 60 Transplantologists=139 40 9% 20 FIGURE 3. Agreement with educational programs targeting children at school. 1% 5% 1% 1% 0% Do not know Other opinion 0 Yes No n=2321 50 40% 36% 40 30 FIGURE 4. Do you know what is the attitude or belief of the Catholic and Protestant religions towards the use of organs or tissues for transplantation? 17% 20 7% 10 0 Accept Do not know No answ er 45 45 50 38 40 30 20 Refuse 25 27 24 12 11 9 Preadolescents Argentina (n=33) 4 10 Preadolescents Canada (n=55) 0 Share Waiting List FIGURE 5. Topic of interest preadolescents. 60 50 40 30 20 10 0 Tx Help No answ er 56 44 33 41 33 23 16 9 12 2 Share FIGURE 6. Topic of interest adolescents. F5– 6 Donation after dead tions about organ donation and transplantation were given to 362 school students in Argentina (Buenos Aires) and Canada (Montreal). The topics included the history of transplantation, brain death, the donor, waiting lists and religious thoughts on transplantation. Students were divided into preadolescents (⬍12 years) and adolescents (⬎13 years). The afforementioned new concepts were discussed. At the end of the presentation, the students completed a questionnaire. Overall, the students were interested in scientific topics and waiting lists. (Figs. 5 and 6) They remarked their intention to discuss the learned topics with parents, friends or both. This essay showed that young students are open to learning about organ donation and transplantation, to accepting new notions and to discussing them. This pilot study suggested that education on organ donation and transplantation, adapted to students’ age and regional socio-cultural characteristics, might be of value to developing changes in attitudes towards organ donation. Waiting List Donation after dead Tx Help Adolescents Canada (n=45) Adolescents Argentina (n=204) No answ er Education will help students to work through the fear and discomfort that might previously exist towards organ donation. Knowledgeable students could share information with friends and families. Parent Involvement in These Programs In early childhood programs, there should be a frequent exchange of information between parents and schools concerning the child, parenting, education and community services. Parental involvement is important during the early years of school life and it might be of extreme importance on issues related with transplantation. Participation of the Community Public and private schools need to be open about education on organ donation and transplantation programs. In collaboration with other organizations, they will provide the community with the best programs for children and their families. As it was mentioned “A communitarian approach to the problem of organ shortage entails rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/ztr2748-09a angnes Sⴝ46 9/11/09 4:43 Art: TP201180 Input-mn S157 © 2009 Lippincott Williams & Wilkins 3. An integrated and enthusiastic protagonist team. 4. The support of Transplantation Community. 5. An active participation and sustain of the States and Churches. changing the moral culture so that members of society will recognize that donating one’s organs, once they are no longer of use to the donor, is the moral (right) thing to do” (47). New Promising Experiences Developing in Argentina for Promoting a Culture of Donating Organs Argentina started experiences in school children education in 1979 (48). Looking forward to improve general knowledge and behavior about organ transplantation, an educational programs at different society levels have started in the last few years. References 1. 2. 3. 4. At National Level INCUCAI (National OPO) will develop a new school educational program “To donate organs means to share life” in one region of the country. 5. At Medical Team Level A 2-year postgraduate course on “Transplantology” (570 hr) is given at the Catholic University, Buenos Aires (from 2005). 7. At University Student Level A pilot investigational essay of education on transplantation has been started at the School of Medical Sciences at the Catholic University, Buenos Aires (2008). At Public Level A sustained educational action teaching basic concepts of transplantation is in course at one national worker union, the “62 Organizaciones” representing 2,500,000 members and their families (2008). 6. 8. 9. 10. 11. 12. 13. 14. Final Remarks Education could be the pathway for promoting a culture to improve “organ shortage”. Current people barriers and disinformation should be considerered when developing a different approach to society. The message should be addressed to all society levels, particularly to the medical professionals and the youth. Schools can incorporate concepts about organ donation and transplantation into their curricula to better prepare young children for their future role in a society which requires a full understanding of an urgent dilemma; “people unfairly dying because of organ shortage”. Children’s education on organ transplantation could be the alternative for a change in social opinion and a stimulus for modification of currents models for public information. Previous experiences in this matter showed that children are able to understand basic notions about transplantation. The following steps seem necessary for a promising development of this program: 1. Incorporation of the program in regular school curricula. 2. School teachers fully accepting the new instructed notions. 15. 16. 17. 18. 19. 20. 21. 22. 23. 24. 25. 26. 27. Sheehy E, Conrad SL, Brigham LE, et al. Estimating the number of potential organ donors in the United States. N Engl J Med 2003; 349: 667. Mocan N, Tekin E. The determinants of the willingness to donate an organ among young adults: Evidence from the United States and the European Union. Soc Sci Med 2007; 65: 2527. Cantarovich F. Improvement in organ shortage through education. Transplantation 2002; 73: 1844. Gibbons RD, Meltzer D, Duan N, et al. Waiting for organ transplantation. Science 2000; 287: 237. Spital A, Taylor JS. Routine recovery: An ethical plan for greatly increasing the supply of transplantable organs. Ethical, legal and financial considerations. Curr Opin Organ Transplant 2008; 13: 202. Gros T, Martinoli S, Spagnoloi G, et al. Attitudes and behavior of young european adults towards the donation of organs—A call for better information. Am J Transplant 2001; 1: 74. Barber K, Falvey S, Hamilton C, et al. Potential for organ donation in the United Kingdom: Audit of intensive care records. BMJ 2006; 332: 1124. Reubsaet A, Borne van den B, Brug J, et al. Determinants of the intention of Dutch adolescents to register as organ donors. Soc Sci Med 2001; 53: 383. Siminoff LA, Arnold RM, Caplan AL. Health care professional attitudes toward donation: Effect on practice and procurement. J Trauma Inj Inf Crit Care 1995; 39: 553. Pérez San Gregorio MA, Dominguez Roldan JM, Murillo Cabezas F, et al. Factores Sociales y Psicológicos que influyen en la donación de órganos. Psicothema 1993; 5: 241. Moraes EL, Massarollo MC. Family refusal to donate organs and tissue for transplantation. Rev Lat Am Enfermagem 2008; 16: 458. Van Norman GA. A matter of life and death: What every anesthesiologist should know about the medical, legal, and ethical aspects of declaring brain death. Anesthesiology 1999; 91: 275. Haustein SV, Sellers MT. Factors associated with (un)willingness to be an organ donor: Importance of public exposure and knowledge. Clin Transplant 2004; 18: 193. Haddow G. The phenomenology of death, embodiment and organ transplantation. Sociol Health Illn 2005; 27: 92. Pugliese MR, Degli Esposti D, Venturoli N, et al. Hospital attitude survey on organ donation in the Emilia-Romagna region, Italy. Transpl Int 2001; 14: 411. Weiss AH. Asking about asking: Informed consent in organ donation. IRB 1996; 18: 6. Doig CJ, Burgess E. Brain death: Resolving inconsistencies in the ethical declaration of death. Can J Anaesth 2003; 50: 725. Morioka M. Reconsidering brain death: A lesson from Japan’s fifteen years of experience. Hastings Cent Rep 2001; 31: 41. Kirklin D. The altruistic act of asking. J Med Ethics 2003; 29: 193. Bidigare SA, Ellis AR. Family physicians’ role in recruitment of organ donors. Arch Fam Med 2000; 9: 601. Truog RD. Consent for organ donation—Balancing conflicting ethical obligations. N Engl J Med 2008; 358: 1209. Frid I, Bergbom-Engberg I, Haljamäe H. Brain death in ICUs and associated nursing care challenges concerning patients and families. Intensive Crit Care Nurs 1998; 14: 21. Muller L. Organ transplantation: Approaching the donor’s family. BMJ 1995; 310: 1149. Wamser P, Goetzinger P, Barlan M, et al. Reasons for 50% reduction in the number of organ donors within 2 years—Opinion poll amongst all ICUS of a transplant centre. Transpl Int 2008; 7(suppl 1): 668. Mackersie RC. Analytic reviews: Organ procurement and brain death in trauma patients. J Intensive Care Med 1989; 4: 137. Bøgh L, Madsen M. Attitudes, knowledge, and proficiency in relation to organ donation: A questionnaire-based analysis in donor hospitals in Northern Denmark. Transplant Proc 2003; 37: 3256. Blok GA, van Dalen J, Jager KJ, et al. The European Donor Hospital Education Programme (EDHEP): Addressing the training needs of rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/ztr2748-09a angnes Sⴝ46 9/11/09 4:43 Art: TP201180 Input-mn S158 | 28. 29. 30. 31. 32. 33. 34. 35. 36. 37. www.transplantjournal.com doctors and nurses who break bad news, care for the bereaved, and request donation. Transpl Int 1999; 12: 161. Omnell Persson M, Dmitriev P, Shevelev V, et al. Attitudes towards organ donation and transplantation—A study involving Baltic physicians. Transpl Int 1998; 11: 419. Sque M, Payne S, Vlachonikolis I. Cadaver donotransplantation: Nurses’attitudes, knowledge and behaviour. Soc Sci Med 2000; 50: 541. Paerson IY, Zurynski Y. A survey of personal and professional attitudes of intensivists to organ donation and transplantation. Anaesth Intensive Care 1995; 23: 68. Schaeffner ES, Windisch W, Freidel K, et al. Knowledge and attitude regarding organ donation among medical students and physicians. Transplantation 2004; 77: 1714. Strenge H. [Organ donation from the viewpoint of the medical students]. Psychother Psychosom Med Psychol 1998; 48: 457. Molzahn AE. Knowledge and attitudes of physicians regarding organ donation. Ann R Coll Physicians Surg Can 1997; 30: 29. Singh P, Kumar A, Pandey CM, et al. Level of awareness about transplantation, brain death and cadaver organ donation in hospital staff in India. Prog Transplant 2002; 12: 289. Daniel Webster. Teacher’s mind resources. Available at: http://www. teachersmind.com/education.htm. Yero JL. The Meaning of Education Teacher’s Mind Resources. Available at: http://www.TeachersMind.com. Goldman E. Brainy Quote. Available at: http://www.brainyquote.com/ quotes/quotes/e/emmagoldma101425.html. Transplantation • Volume 88, Number 7S, October 15, 2009 38. 39. 40. 41. 42. 43. 44. 45. 46. 47. 48. Ramsey P. The Patient as Person: Explorations in Medical Ethics. New Haven, CT, Yale University Press 1970. Planting the Seed: Organ Transplantation Education for Children, Youth and Young Adults. Robert E. Schoenberg Surgeon General’s Workshop on Increasing Organ Donation. Washington, DC, Public Health Service, Office of the Surgeon General, July 8 –10, 1991. Childress JF. Editorial. Ann Intern Med 2006; 145: 224. Sotiropoulos GC, Brokalaki EI. Living organ donation: Is there still place for altruism? Hepatogastroenterology 2004; 51: 6. John Paul II. Address to the 18th International Congress of The Transplantation Society, 29 August 2000: Libreria Editrice Vaticana. Available at: http://www.vatican.va/holy_father/john_paul_ii/speeches/2000/ julsep/documents/hf_jp-ii_spe_20000829_transplants_en.html. Tabarrok A. Group Responds to Congressional Hearing on Organ Shortage. 2003. Available at: www.organgiving.org. Hanto DW, Peters TG, Howard RJ, et al. Family disagreement over organ donation. Virtual Mentor 2005; 7. Cantarovich F, Heguilen R, Abbud Filho M, et al. An International Opinion Poll of well educated people regarding awareness and feelings about organ donation for transplantation. Transpl Int 2007; 20: 512. Cantarovich F. Reducing the organ shortage by education and fostering a sense of social responsibility. Transplant Proc 2003; 35: 1153. Etzioni A. Organ donation: A communitarian approach. Kennedy Inst Ethics J 2003; 13: 1. Cantarovich F, Fagundes E, Biolcati D, Bacque MC. School education, a basis for positive attitudes toward organ donation. Transplant Proc 2000; 32: 55. rich3/ztr-tp/ztr-tp/ztr11109/autcont-09a panickes Sⴝ14 9/11/09 11:52 Art: Input-mn Author Information Mario Abbud-Filho Faculdade de Medicina e Instituto de Urologia de São José do Rio Preto. Rua voluntários de São Paulo 3826, São José do Rio Preto, SP, Brazil. CEP: 15015-200. Jean Laffitte Via della Conciliazione, 1 00193 Roma, Italy E-mail: jlaffitte@acdlife.va Riccardo Bosco Piemonte Regional Organ Procurement Organization E-mail: rbosco@molinette.piemonte.it Martı́ Manyalich Transplant Procurement Management. IL3 – Institute for LifeLong Learning – Universitat de Barcelona, Ciutat de Granada, 131, 08018 Barcelona, Spain E-mail: tpmproject@il3.ub.edu Marco Brunetti Director, Office of Pastoral Care for Health, Archdiocese of Turin Italy E-mail: salute@diocesi.torino.it Félix Cantarovich 14, Fantin Latour 75.016 Paris France E-mail: felix.cantarovich@orange.fr Nunziata Comoretto Center for Bioethics, Catholic University of Sacred Heart, 1, Largo F. Vito, I-00168, Rome, Italy E-mail: nunziata.comoretto@rm.unicatt.it Alessandro Nanni Costa Director of the Italian National Transplant Centre viale Regina Elena 299 00161 Rome, Italy E-mail: cnt@iss.it Francis L. Delmonico Professor of Surgery Harvard Medical School Massachusetts General Hospital Transplant Center Boston, MA 02114-2696 E-mail: francis_delmonico@neob.org Håkan Gäbel Olof Wijksgatan 4 412 55 Göteborg Sweden E-mail: hakan@Gäbel.se Valter D. Garcia Santa Casa de Porto Alegre. Rua Correa Lima 1493, Porto Alegre, RS, Brazil. CEP: 90850-250. Alexandra K. Glazier Vice President & General Counsel New England Organ Bank One Gateway Center Newton, MA 02458 E-mail: alexandra_glazier@neob.org Mariangela Gritta Grainer postal address: via pedescala 22 36078 Valdagno (Vicenza) E-mail: mgrainer@interplanet.it Anna Guermani Piedmont Regional Organ Procurement Organization E-mail: aguermani@molinette.piemonte.it Transplantation • Volume 88, Number 7S, October 15, 2009 Blanca Martinez Department of Anesthesiology and Intensive Care Medicine. Santa Maria della Misericordia University Hospital Piazzale Santa Maria della Misericordia 15, 33100 Udine, Italy E-mail: blancamartinez@libero.it Rafael Matesanz Organización Nacional De Trasplantes (ONT) Sinesio Delgado 6 28029, Madrid, Spain E-mail: rmatesanz@msc.es, rafmatesanz@yahoo.es Jose O. Medina-Pestana Hospital do Rim e Hipertensão, Universidade Federal de São Paulo, São Paulo, SP, Brazil. Rua Borges Lagoa 960, 11° andar, Vila Clementino, São Paulo - SP, Brazil. CEP: 04038-002. E-mail: medina@hrim.com.br Ferdinand Muehlbacher Medical University of Vienna Dept. of Surgery, Unit of transplantation General Hospital Vienna Währinger Guertel 18-20 1090 Vienna E-mail: ferdinand.muehlbacher@meduniwien.ac.at Donadio Pier Paolo Piedmont Regional Organ Procurement Organization Responsible, Azienda Ospedaliero Universitaria Molinette San Giovanni Battista Di Torino Corso Bramante 88/90-10126 Torino E-mail: pdonadio@molinette.piemonte.it Walter Schaupp Professor of Moral Theology Faculty of Catholic Theology Karl-Franzens University Graz A-8010 Graz, Heinrichstrasse 78B E-mail: walter.Schaupp@uni-graz.at J.M. Simón i Castellvı́ President of the FIAMC (World Federation of the Catholic Medical Associations) Palazzo San Calisto 00120-Città del Vaticano E-mail: metges@federaciocristians.org www.fiamc.org Antonio G. Spagnolo Dpt. Educational Sciences, University of Macerata and Center for Bioethics, Catholic University of Sacred Heart, Rome E-mail: agSpagnolo@unimc.it www.transplantjournal.com | S159