251 7. Pathetic Proof: Passionate Appeals Speech is a powerful guide, which by means of the finest and most invisible body effects the divinest works: it can stop fear and banish grief and create joy and nurture pity. . . . Fearful shuddering and tearful pity and grievous longing come upon its hearers, and at the actions and physical sufferings of others in good fortunes and in evil fortunes, through the agency of words, the soul is wont to experience a suffering of its own. (Gorgias, "Encomium of Helen" 8). Rhetors can find arguments in the issue itself (logos), and a rhetor's character (ethos) can be persuasive as well. According to Aristotle, a third kind of intrinsic proof is also available: rhetors can appeal to human emotion (pathos). In early Greek thought, the term pathos referred to a passive state we might call “experience”; later, in Greek plays called “tragedies,” this state came to be associated with suffering. In the fifth century BCE Plato and Aristotle began to use the term pathos to discuss the emotions in general. “Pathos” is still used in English to refer to any quality in an experience that arouses emotions, and many English words are borrowed from the Greek term including “sympathy” and “empathy.” Speakers of modern English generally use an adjective form, "pathetic," to refer to anything that is meager, as in the phrase "that's a pathetic excuse." But "pathetic" also refers to the arousal or expression of emotions, and that's the sense in which we use it here. Aristotle and Cicero discussed the following sets of emotions: anger/calm, love/hate, fear/confidence, shame/shamelessness, compassion, pity/indignation, envy/emulation, joy, and hope (Rhetoric II 2-12; De Oratore II i 203). Emotions should be distinguished from appetites such as pleasure and pain. They must also be distinguished from values such as 251 252 justice and goodness. However, people do hold values with more or less intensity, and this intensity is where the rhetorical force of emotional appeals resides. People respond emotionally when they or those close to them are praised or threatened; rhetorically, they also respond emotionally when their values are reinforced or threatened. Like ethos, pathos creates rhetorical disposition. Recall from the last chapter that for Aristotle, the rhetor’s disposition—how she presents herself— “makes much difference in regard to persuasion.” As a result, the audience’s disposition toward the speaker or writer, or to the issue under deliberation—that is, whether one is well or badly disposed to someone or something—makes a difference as well. As Aristotle put it, “things do not seem the same to those who are friendly and those who are hostile, nor to the angry and the calm but either altogether different or different in importance” (II.2.1378a). For Aristotle, then, the rhetorical situation layers dispositions on dispositions: the rhetor’s and the audience’s dispositions each shape the other, and this shaping process can even change during the a speech or a piece of writing. Of all the ancient kinds of rhetorical proofs, the appeal to the emotions seems strangest to contemporary rhetors. Perhaps it seems a little shoddy, as well, to appeal to fear, or hatred, or anger. In our own time people revere reason (at least in theory), and in our culture a sharp distinction is often made between reason and emotion: if you're emotional, you're irrational. Reason is associated with mind, and connotes a calm, studied approach to issues, while emotions are associated with the body--that container for the mind whose functions we cannot always govern. Hence we assume that emotions can derail reason, or cause someone to “lose control.” Furthermore, people tend to think of emotions as belonging 252 253 to individuals, like opinions. These prejudices are inaccurate and unfair. New research in neuroscience suggests that we can’t think without emotions, and that our emotional responses are intricately tied up with our beliefs, as well (Damasio). Other research suggests that emotions can be shared among individuals, as is illustrated by the excitement shared by large crowds at concerts or sports events or the shared joy felt at a religious gathering (Brennan). And anyone who has suffered the loss of a loved one knows that grief becomes more intense when shared with others who are suffering. The ancients understood all of this, and hence they taught us that rhetorical appeals to the emotions were very effective. Contemporary advertisers and political spin artists also understand the important role played by emotion in our responses to their messages. The most obvious modern use of emotional appeals appears in advertisements that appeal to consumers' desire for success ("be all you can be;" “just do it!”) or their fear of losing status in their communities ("don’t let this happen to you!"). But emotional appeals appear in other sorts of discourse as well. Clearly, the nation’s emotional response to the events of September 11 played a large role in Americans’ support for the subsequent wars in Iraq and Afghanistan, support that was very strong immediately following the event but that has dwindled as time passed and the nation’s grief and shock grew more muted. The diminishing support for these wars, interpreted as retaliation for September 11, suggests to us that as emotional intensity wanes, so does the persuasiveness of arguments based on emotional appeals. For those of us who actually witnessed 9/11, though, accounts or images can still 253 254 evoke the emotions we felt then. In his introduction to an anthology of essays about September 11, Phil Scraton recounts his own emotional responses on that terrible day, thus artfully drawing his readers into the scene: Trying to make sense - emotional, physical, political- of September 11, I return to my initial reactions and responses. Like so many others across the world, via satellite I witnessed truly horrifying scenes of scarcely believable atrocity. Filmed from every conceivable angle the second passenger aircraft imploded the twin tower. Its nose-cone, having passed through the building, was instantly engulfed in flames. At that 'live by satellite' moment, the collapse of the entire World Trade Center inevitable, the realisation dawned that the dual crashes were no coincidence. Both aircraft had been piloted, purposefully and accurately, into their targets. As news broke, telling of two other planes crashing, one into the Pentagon, the second out of control in Pennsylvania, the immensity and significance of these disasters became apparent. They had to be the dreadful end-product of effective and efficient collaboration involving groups working together, carefully planning and acquiring skills. These were not random targets. The World Trade Center, bomb damaged just eight years earlier, and the Pentagon represented hugely symbolic as well as material targets. In a Verona hotel room we watched the dramatic live transmissions from downtown Manhattan. Firefighters and rescuers raced into the disaster zone passing dust-covered, ghost-like workers coming from the opposite 254 255 direction - running or staggering for their lives. Cameras homed in on others trapped in offices high above the flames, some throwing themselves from windows to avoid choking or burning to death. As the towers collapsed, clouds of grey toxic smoke covered all and everything in their path. Then came the first reports of agonised telephone calls made from one of the planes and by those facing death trapped in their offices. These were final goodbyes to loved ones. They reminded me of rescue workers recounting disaster scenes where the only sounds they could hear, as they listened for potential survivors, were those of mobile phones ringing from the debris as desperate relatives tried to make contact. (1) Scraton’s description is detailed but simple. Such a powerfully evocative event can effectively do the work of pathos without the need for over-the-top descriptions. Ancient Teachers on the Emotions Greek orators could find examples of the persuasive use of emotion in the texts of the poet Homer, whose two great epic poems, the Iliad and the Odyssey, were well-known among the Greek people. In the last book of the Iliad, Homer depicted the Trojan king, Priam, appealing to Achilles, the Achean hero, to return the body of his son, Hector. [FIGURE that is in 4e: Priam pleading for the return of the body of Hector] Remember your own father, Achilles, in your godlike youth: his years like mine are many, and he stands upon the fearful doorstep of old age. He, too, 255 256 is hard pressed, it may be, by those around him, there being no one able to defend him from bane of war and ruin. Ah, but he may nonetheless hear news of you alive, and so with glad heart hope through all his days for sight of his dear son, come back from Troy, while I have deathly fortune. Noble sons I fathered here, but scarce one man is left me. Fifty I had when the Acheans came, nineteen out of a single belly, others born of attendant women. Most are gone. Raging Ares cut their knees from under them. And he who stood alone among them all, their champion, and Troy's, ten days ago you killed him, fighting for his land, my prince, Hector. It is for him that I have come among these ships, to beg him back from you, and I bring ransom without stint. Achilles, be reverent toward the great gods! And take pity on me, remember your own father. Think me more pitiful by far, since I have brought myself to do what no man else 256 257 has done before--to lift to my lips the hand of one who killed my son. (XXIV 485-506) Priam first arouses Achilles' sense of filial love by reminding him of his own father, and tries to arouse his pity for the plight of lonely old men whose sons are missing or dead. Then he tells how his many children have been slain, hoping to rouse Achilles' pity for his misfortunes, and he mentions ransom, hoping to stimulate Achilles' greed. He reminds Achilles of the gods; this is a subtle attempt to make Achilles fearful, since he committed a serious religious transgression by refusing to bury Hector's body. Finally, he asks Achilles to pity him for the shameful position in which he, a king, has been placed by being forced to beg a soldier to return his son's body. As this passage makes clear, emotional appeals are based on the assumption that human beings share similar kinds of emotional responses to events: fathers everywhere weep for lost sons; an old man who has lost his family is pitied by everyone, even his enemies. While this may not be true across wide cultural differences, it certainly is the case that people who live in the same community have similar emotional responses. If this were not true, governments would not be able to incite great numbers of people to volunteer for military service during wartime (which is an irrational thing to do, after all). In his history of the Peloponnesian War, Thucydides reported a speech made by Pericles, who had incited the Athenians to war against the Spartans. When this war did not go well, the people became angry. Pericles "called an assembly, wanting to encourage them and to convert their angry feelings into a gentler and more hopeful mood" (II 59). Pericles was only partially successful in quelling the anger of the people because the war had brought them great suffering. As this 257 258 passage indicates, Pericles was quite aware that rhetoric could arouse or dispel emotional responses, and that communities could share emotional responses to public events. Ancient rhetoricians also treated the emotions as ways of knowing, thus associating them with intellectual processes. Gorgias argued in the "Helen" that the persuasive effect of verbal seduction is no different from physical force; Helen was blameless no matter whether she was abducted or whether her seducer simply persuaded her to flee her husband and country. Indeed, early rhetorical theorists like Gorgias and Plato characterized rhetoric as a psychagogia, a leader or enchanter of souls. Gorgias argued that, given the right circumstances (kairos), a rhetor could alter an audience's emotional state of mind and thus change their assessment of reality, in essence helping them to see the world in new ways. In other words, the ancients taught that emotions hold heuristic potential. The emotions even seem to be a means of reasoning: if someone becomes afraid, realizing that she is in a dangerous situation, she quickly assesses her options and takes herself out of danger as quickly as she can. Emotions can also move people to action: if someone feels compassion for someone else, he helps the suffering person. Early sophistic treatises on rhetoric included topics for appealing to the emotions. For example, the Rhetoric to Alexander discussed appeals to friendliness, kindliness, and the like as a means urging an audience to act on behalf of the needy (1439b 15ff.). Since sophistic manuals were organized according to the parts or divisions of a discourse, they gave no systematic advice about arousing the emotions but rather included it in their discussions of introductions and conclusions. Aristotle seems to have been the first rhetorician to provide a systematic discussion of 258 259 emotional proofs. In Book II of the Rhetoric, he defined emotions as "those things through which, by undergoing change, people come to differ in their judgments" (i 1378a). This sounds very much like Gorgias’s argument that emotional responses help people to change their minds. When a person experiences an emotion such as anger, pity, or fear, she enters a new state of mind in which she sees things differently. If she has become angry at someone, for example, she sees that person in a different light than she previously did. Perhaps she is angry with her supervisor because he mistakenly blamed her for something that was not her fault. Her angry reaction to this event will change her attitude toward her supervisor. She may even be moved by this new way of thinking to change her behavior toward him: she may, for example, vow to speak up for herself the next time she is unfairly accused; she may even decide to quit her job. Aristotle realized that emotions are communal in the sense that they are usually excited by our relations with other people. We do not become angry in some general or vague way; ordinarily we are angry at someone else. We do not feel love toward nothing; we feel love for some persons or creatures. We can also communicate emotions to others-people who are afraid can make others fearful as well. Most post-classical rhetorical treatises employed the sophistic habit of treating the emotions as suitable proofs only in the introduction and conclusion of a piece of discourse. Cicero's De Oratore and Quintilian's Institutes are exceptions to this general rule. While both rhetoricians adopted Aristotle's tripartite division of rhetorical proofs, neither added much of theoretical value to his discussion of pathos. However, their treatises do supply numerous examples of successful emotional appeals and give helpful suggestions on how to 259 260 compose these. For these reasons, we rely on Aristotle for the theoretical part of our discussion of the emotions, and turn to Cicero and Quintilian for advice on how to compose emotional appeals. Emotions as Rhetorical Proofs According to Aristotle, three criteria must be met if rhetors wish to understand how emotions are aroused or quelled. First, they must understand the state of mind of people who are angry, joyful, or indignant; second, they must know who can excite these emotions in people; third, they must understand the reasons for which people become emotional (II 1 1378a). People do not enter the state of mind called "anger" without a reason, and they become angry at someone, even if they don't know who the person is. If man leaves his workplace feeling perfectly calm, this state of mind changes when he discovers in the parking lot that someone has put a dent in his car. The reason he becomes angry is that this situation leaves him with choices that are unpleasant: don't repair the dent, in which case it may rust and become worse, thus lowering the car's value; do repair the dent and pay for it out of his own pocket, since the repair will probably cost less than the deductible on his insurance. Note that his anger is not irrational in this case; it is a perfectly reasonable response to events. Aristotle's first criterion is that rhetors must know the emotional states of mind of their hearers or readers. An audience may bring a certain emotional state of mind to a rhetorical situation, and if so, the rhetor needs to decide whether this state of mind is conducive to their acceptance of her proposition. If it is not, she needs to change their states of mind. Aristotle thought that emotional change came about through changes in the level of 260 261 intensity with which emotions are felt (II ii 1377b-1378a). Emotional intensity alters in accordance with the spatial and temporal proximity of the people or situations that arouse them. When the person with whom someone becomes angry is close, either physically or relationally, anger will be felt more intensely. If the person who dented the car is still in the lot when its owner arrives there, the owner focuses his anger more intensely on the culprit than if he can only be diffusely angry in general with people who dent parked cars and run. (In this case he may even refocus his anger on another car or on the traffic as he drives home). If the culprit happens to be someone known to the owner of the dented car, the owner’s emotional response will be intensified, as well, and the quality of their relationship may evoke other emotions in addition to anger. If the two are co-workers who don't like each other very much, the owner of the dented car may be more intensely angry than if the culprit is a friend. Their relationship may deteriorate even more. If the culprit is a supervisor, however, the owner of the dented vehicle may try to temper his anger with mildness. If the two are spouses or partners, however, things become enormously complex emotionally. As this example demonstrates, the relation of spatial proximity to emotional intensity depends upon social hierarchy, as well. As Aristotle noted, "people think they are entitled to be treated with respect by those inferior in birth, in power, in virtue, and generally in whatever they themselves have much of" (1378b). According to Aristotle's reasoning, people are less prone to be angry with those above or equal to them on a scale of social authority, while they are more prone to be angry with those below them on that scale. According to this analysis, then, if the supervisor who dented the car is a shop foreman, the car’s owner 261 262 may be more angry than he would be if the culprit were the president of the company. Some emotions are also more intensely felt if people nearby are experiencing them as well. This feature of emotional intensity is what makes horror fiction and films work because the audience fears for the characters. The feeling of fear is intensified in a theater because others are sharing it. Joy and anxiety appear to be shareable emotions, and mob violence can be stimulated by shared hatred and/or rage. Entire communities can feel hope, as when it seems likely that a war is about to end. They can also feel despair, as Americans did during the Great Depression, or, they can share a sense of horror, as they did during and after the events of 9/11. The intensity with which emotions are felt depends on the nearness of their objects in time, as well. Love tends to grow with time, but so can hatred. The intensity with which people feel joy depends very much on the temporal proximity of a joyful event, while sadness seems to linger through time. The intensity of grief fades, but it nearly entirely disappears. Anger tends to fade with time, unless the object of that anger is nearby in either time or space. The car owner’s anger toward the person who dented his car will lessen over time, unless for some reason he fails to get the dent fixed. In that case, every time he sees it he may get angry all over again. Proximity also influences the intensity with which fear is felt. Because people fear far-off dangers less than those which are closer in time and space, climate change may not intensely frighten people now because its visible effects on human culture will not occur for many years. And because proximity is related to emotional intensity, during wartime or when relations between nations are tense, governments try to stimulate fear of the enemy by 262 263 bringing their images close to the people, altering them into objects of fear and thus disguising the fact of their spatial and temporal distance. In 2008 and 2009 when relations between North Korea and the United States were very tense over North Korea’s nuclear program, American media portrayed the Iranian leader, the Ayatollah Khomeini, as a crazed lover of violence. We can probably safely assume that U.S. presidents George W. Bush and later Barack Obama were not presented in the most positive light in North Korea. In other words, both parties to the conflict tried to personalize it for their citizens, because it is easier to make people afraid and angry toward a person than it is to make them afraid and angry toward an abstraction. This strategy of depicting leaders in a frightening way is not limited to other countries, of course. During and after the 2008 presidential election, some people opposed to electing Obama began carrying signs depicting Obama as Hitler. Most of these signs were carried by members of the newly established “Tea Party,” a very conservative political group. The signs redesigned a familiar image from Obama’s campaign using starker colors and giving him a small Hitlerean moustache. This practice is not new, of course; George W. Bush was also depicted as Hitler by certain groups. Such depictions attempt to arouse fear of the President among Americans by identifying him with a man who is widely regarded as the epitome of evil. At Jon Stewart’s 2010 Rally to Restore Sanity, however, several participants carried signs that respond directly to such depictions. Here is one of those signs: 263 264 On The Daily Show, Stewart himself added to the commentary on Tea Party signs, subtly pointing out that disagreement is not the same thing as mass murder. [permission note: the first image is a photograph taken by Pamela J. Morris. She has already preliminarily granted permission to use the photograph, and I am including her contact image 264 265 below. Please use the email address to contact her. The second image is I’m sure property of the Daily Show. I would really love to use this one and hope they don’t charge too much. PLEASE let us know if they want too much money; I’m pretty sure I can find another image of this sign. Pamela J. Morris, Ph.D. Baruch Institute for Marine and Coastal Sciences University of South Carolina Baruch Marine Field Lab PO Box 1630 Georgetown, SC 29442 Cell no.: 843.991.8355 pjmorris@belle.baruch.sc.edu] These textual/visual conversations show how pathos and logos are frequently wrapped together. The depiction of Obama with a tiny moustache is an enthymeme whose premises forward rather muddled equations between socialism and Nazism, but whose conclusion (Obama is like Hitler) is a straightforward appeal to fear. The “Sanity” signs appeal to reason as well—the first is an enthymeme arguing that Obama (or really anyone) can’t be Hitler because there was only one Hitler. The second one makes a more general case against the practice of portraying anyone who holds a different view as a fascist, murderous, dictator. To do so, this sign combines ethos, logos, and pathos: the first assertion, “I disagree with you,” shows the sign-bearer as as someone who can think for himself. The net effect of the sign portrays a reasonable ethos by distinguishing between the act of disagreement and the murderous acts of Hitler. The approach of these signs, along with their context (Stewart’s Rally) is layered with wry humor. The understated stance—e.g., “I am pretty sure you’re not Hitler”—exposes the absurdity of depicting an opponent as Hitler. With such humor, these responses contain strong pathos appeals as well. The “Sanity” signs meet one pathos (appeal to fear) with another (appeal to humor). . 265 266 The Characters of Audiences and Rhetors In the Phaedrus, Plato instructed rhetors who wished to be persuasive to study the people in their audiences: Since the function of oratory is in fact to influence men’s souls, the intending orator must know what types of soul there are. Now these are of a determinate number, and their variety results in a variety of individuals. To the types of soul thus discriminated there corresponds a determinate number of types of discourse. Hence a certain type of hearer will be easy to persuade by a certain type of speech to take such and such action for such and such reason, while another type will be hard to persuade (271d). He might have meant that rhetors should study the emotions of their potential hearers or readers. In any case some authorities think that Aristotle followed Plato's advice in Book II, chapters 12-17 of the Rhetoric, where he developed some general guidelines for evaluating the emotional states of audiences. He listed many Greek commonplaces about the differing attitudes held by young, middle-aged, and old people. For example, young persons are more passionate than older people, Aristotle wrote, but their emotions pass quickly. Older people, on the other hand, tend to be suspicious because their hopes have often been dashed. He also provided commonplaces about the differing attitudes of rich and poor, powerful and powerless, and those who have good or bad luck. In Cicero’s De Oratore, one of the dialogue participants argues that it is desirable for an audience to "carry within them . . . some mental emotion that is in harmony with what the advocate's interest will suggest. For, as the saying goes, it is easier to spur the willing horse 266 267 than to start the lazy one" (XLIV 185-86). He continued: This indeed is the reason why, when setting about a hazardous and important case, in order to explore the feelings of the tribunal, I engage wholeheartedly in a consideration so careful, that I scent out with all possible keenness their thoughts, judgments, anticipations and wishes, and the direction in which they seem likely to be led away most easily by eloquence. . . . If . . . an arbitrator is neutral and free from predisposition, my task is harder, since everything has to be called forth by my speech, with no help from the listener's character. (187) In this passage Cicero anticipated the findings of contemporary research about audiences. Roughly speaking, members of an audience may hold one of three attitudes toward an issue or a rhetor's ethos: they may be hostile, indifferent, or accepting. Communication researchers have found that it is easier to move people who care about an issue than it is to influence those who are indifferent. That is, it is easier to bring about a change of mind in those who are accepting or hostile than in those who are indifferent. Take the issue of gun control, for example. This issue directly concerns gun owners and those who trade in guns--such as owners of gun shops--as well as organized groups such as the National Rifle Association. It also concerns anyone who worries about their personal safety or that of others, but people in this second group are less likely to pay attention to gun control legislation than those who are more directly involved with the circulation of guns. Such people will move away from indifference, of course, if a family member or friend or some well-known person has been threatened with a gun or injured by a gunshot. People who use guns or rely on them for a livelihood are likely to be emotionally committed during 267 268 discussions of gun control legislation, no matter whether they oppose or favor it. People in the second group, whose lives or work are not tied to gun use, are likely to be indifferent to discussions of this issue. They will be more difficult to persuade in any direction, because they first have to be shown compelling reasons why they should care about the issue at all. Researchers have also discovered that a person's willingness to change her mind depends on two things: the emotional intensity with which she clings to an opinion and the degree to which her identity--her sense of herself--is wrapped up with that opinion. People who are intensely invested in a position are less likely to change their minds than those who are not. Someone who favors gun control, for example, might do so for intellectual reasons: perhaps he worries that if guns are freely available, irresponsible people will be able to purchase them. On the other hand, if he has been held up at gunpoint, he may oppose gun control because he wishes to carry arms himself in order to protect himself and his family. His commitment to the free circulation of guns centers on a basic desire to survive any future encounters of the kind. Theoretically, this person would be more difficult to move away from his position than is someone whose commitment to gun control is only intellectual. And if his identity and/or his fortunes depend on the free circulation of guns, he will not be at all receptive to arguments supporting gun control. As we pointed out in the chapter on ideology, he may share an entire set of beliefs—an ideology--about guns with members of his community, and in this case he will be very difficult to move away from any position he holds about them. In sum, rhetors need to assess the emotional states of their audiences as well as the 268 269 intensity with which they adhere to those states. Rhetors need to decide as well whether those emotional states render their audiences receptive to themselves and/or their proposition. Next, they should decide whether or not an audience can be persuaded to change their minds, and, if so, whether they will be moved by appeals to their current emotional states or to a different one induced by a rhetor. If the answer to that last question appears to be “yes,” then the rhetor needs to decide on the appropriate level of intensity her emotional appeal might take. And if the rhetor is going to deliver a speech, and the emotional intensity needs to be high, then she probably ought to seem a little emotional herself. Recall Aristotle’s picture of the rhetorical situation as ethos meeting (and creating) pathos, layers of dispositions. If a rhetor wants to evoke an emotion, it is best to display that emotion as well. As Quintilian wrote, The heart of the matter as regards arousing emotions, so far as I can see, lies in being moved by them oneself. The mere imitation of grief or anger or indignation may in fact sometimes be ridiculous, if we fail to adapt our feelings to the emotion as well as our words and our face . . . Consequently, where we wish to give an impression of reality, let us assimilate ourselves to the emotions of those who really suffer; let our speech spring from the very attitude that we want to produce in the judge. Will the hearer feel sorrow when I, whose object in speaking is to make him feel it, feel none? Will he be angry, if the person who is trying to excite his anger suffers nothing resembling the emotions he is calling for? Will he weep when the speaker’s 269 270 eyes are dry? Impossible! (VI ii 30) Quintilian’s impassioned observations about passion still hold true to some degree today. In the weeks following the 2010 explosion of British Petroleum’s Deepwater Horizon oil rig in the Gulf of Mexico, which ultimately resulted in more than two-hundred million gallons of oil spilling into the ocean, U.S. citizens looked to President Barack Obama for a stern and passionate response. Newswriters and other pundits believed that President Obama should have exhibited more anger toward BP, and that he should have taken swifter, stronger actions, making an example out of the corporation. One writer, New York Times columnist Maureen Dowd, characterized one press-conference exchange this way: Reporters grilled Robert Gibbs at his White House briefing on Tuesday about the president’s strange inability to convey passion over a historical environmental disaster. This was underscored by Obama’s perfunctory drop-by to a sanitized beach in Grand Isle, La. Despite his recent ode about growing up near an ocean, he didn’t bother to meet with the regular folks who have lost their seafaring livelihoods. After Gibbs asserted that his boss was “enraged” at BP, CBS News’s Chip Reid skeptically pressed: “Have we really seen rage from the president on this? I think most people would say no.” “I’ve seen rage from him, Chip,” Gibbs insisted. “I have.” Reid asked for an exact definition of what constitutes emotion for Obama: “Can you describe it? Does he yell and scream? What does he do?” Gibbs mentioned the words “clenched jaw” and the president’s admonition to “plug the damn hole.” 270 271 Such speculations about Obama’s emotional response pressed upon the rhetorical situation of a televised speech he later delivered on the matter. Here are three excerpts from the text of the speech. You may find the full text as well as a video at americanrhetoric.com. OVAL OFFICE ADDRESS TO THE NATION ON BP OIL SPILL DISASTER Excerpt 1. Already, this oil spill is the worst environmental disaster America has ever faced. And unlike an earthquake or a hurricane, it’s not a single event that does its damage in a matter of minutes or days. The millions of gallons of oil that have spilled into the Gulf of Mexico are more like an epidemic, one that we will be fighting for months and even years. But make no mistake: We will fight this spill with everything we’ve got for as long as it takes. We will make BP pay for the damage their company has caused. And we will do whatever’s necessary to help the Gulf Coast and its people recover from this tragedy. Excerpt 2. You know, for generations, men and women who call this region home have made their living from the water. That living is now in jeopardy. I’ve talked to shrimpers and fishermen who don’t know how they’re going to support their families this year. I’ve seen empty docks and restaurants with fewer customers -- even in areas where the beaches are not yet affected. I’ve talked to owners of shops and hotels who wonder when the tourists might start coming back. The sadness and the anger they feel is not just about the money they’ve lost. It’s about a wrenching anxiety that their way of life may be lost. 271 272 Excerpt 3. We cannot consign our children to this future. The tragedy unfolding on our coast is the most painful and powerful reminder yet that the time to embrace a clean energy future is now. Now is the moment for this generation to embark on a national mission to unleash America’s innovation and seize control of our own destiny. These three excerpts mark moments in the speech during which pathos is at the fore; excerpt 1 conveys anger; excerpt 2 sadness; excerpt 3 evokes hope and inspiration. The first excerpt follows a careful and matter-of-fact explanation of the situation in the Gulf, an explanation replete with logic and historical facts. After comparing the spill to an epidemic for its longterm and dire consequences, Obama pointedly begins a pathos appeal with brief transition: “But make no mistake.” At this point in the speech, the rhetorical style becomes a bit more elevated; each of the three sentences in that paragraph begins with the word “We will,” and they are delivered more slowly than the previous description, with conviction and emphatic gestures, conveying his anger over the situation. If you watch the video of the speech, you will notice that with the words “we will make BP pay,” Obama points his finger at an angle between the camera and his desk. The pointing is emphatic but is not directed at the camera—the viewers—who are largely not culpable. Excerpt 2 appeals to emotion by detailing the hardships of the shrimpers and fishermen in the area, those who “have made their living from the water.” Obama describes this rather poetically, thereby heightening the appeal to pathos. The images of empty docks and tourist areas serve to evoke empathy for those whose livelihoods are in jeopardy, and they invoke fear for the local economies as well. Finally, excerpt 2 mentions sadness and 272 273 anger by name and conveys the overall sentiment in the Gulf as a kind of “wrenching anxiety.” The cadence can’t be captured by an excerpt, but it is worth noting that Obama’s cadence during these lines matches their gravity: he pauses noticeably between the words “sadness” and “anger.” Excerpt 3 returns to the resolute tone of excerpt 1, this time expressing conviction without anger. Words like “children” and “future” in the first sentence convey urgency; “tragedy,” “painful,” and “powerful” in the second heighten intensity, and “embark” and “unleash” in the third convey movement. The repetition of the word “now” at the end of sentence two and the beginning of sentence three work to galvanize the audience as Obama then goes on in subsequent paragraphs to lay out a plan for scaling back U.S. reliance on fossil fuels. Comparison of the written text to the video of the speech can raise interesting points about the available means of appealing to pathos in writing and speaking situations. In live or video recorded speaking situations, gestures and facial expressions can appeal to pathos, and in live, video recorded, or sound recorded arguments (e.g., a podcast), speed and cadence can also do so. Obama’s emotional expressions are more staid than Quintilian might have advised in his time, but it is important to remember that the close-up venue of television, which can capture the set of a jaw, places very different demands on a rhetor than the microphone-free delivery of Roman orators during Quintilian’s time. We will discuss the physical and visual components of emotion in the chapter on delivery; for now, suffice it to say that pathos and delivery work hand in hand. The next section discusses appeals to pathos in written 273 274 discourse. These are strategies that will likely work in composing a speech as well, especially when combined with advice in our chapter on delivery. Composing Passionate Proofs We noted earlier that ancient rhetoricians named many emotions to which rhetors can appeal: anger, love, hate, fear, shame, compassion, pity, indignation, envy, joy, and hope. We cannot predict which of these emotions will be operative in the rhetorical situations with which our readers are working, and so we cannot forecast ways in which you can arouse these emotions, or calm them if they are already present in members of your audience. We can give some general advice about when and how to use emotional proofs, however. Suppose that a rhetor who opposes the war in Afghanistan wishes to compose some suitable emotional appeals to use in her argument. She first needs to consider whether or not her audience will have an emotional response to this issue. Intense emotional responses are most likely if members of her audience are personally involved in the war—if they or family members are among the military personnel serving in Afghanistan, for instance. A strong emotional response is also likely if any members of the audience identify closely with the military because of a family history of honorable service, or with the values the war is said to represent—America’s safety from terrorism, for instance. If members of the audience feel strongly about the conflict in Afghanistan, whether they agree with the rhetor’s position or not, they will be interested in her argument. People who are intensely supportive of a war, as well as those who intensely oppose it, probably take those positions because for some reason their identities and belief systems are closely wrapped up with their hawkish or dovish positions. If this is the case, emotions 274 275 will run high when the issue is discussed. Such people are likely to read any departure from their preferred position as a challenge to their identities and beliefs, and this is why argument so often devolves away from rhetoric and into angry confrontation. Intense emotional attachment to claims can present serious barriers to rhetors who disagree with such claims. But ancient rhetoricians thought there were ways around and through such situations, and they provided us with a few bits of advice on how to navigate the emotional waters that surround the making of claims and arguments. Enargeia If an audience does not care about an issue in which a rhetor is interested, she will need to use emotional appeals to get their attention. In the case of an argument about the war in Afghanistan, she can do this by opening their eyes to the serious consequences of war— loss of innocent life, the physical and emotional injuries sustained by U.S. troops serving long and repeated tours, devastation of the countryside, ruin of the economy, the hatred and anger it creates and sustains, the seeming endlessness of a decade-long conflict. Ancient rhetoricians recommended that the most effective emotional appeals actually make an issue come alive for audiences, make them see vividly what is at stake in the issue. That is, emotional appeals can supply audiences with a reason for identifying with an issue, thus moving them away from indifference toward either acceptance or rejection of a position on it. In De Oratore Cicero's characters argued that emotional appeals are equal in importance to arguments from character (ethos) and from the issue itself (logos) (II xliv 185ff). One of the characters in the dialogue, Antonius, argued further that it is important for 275 276 a rhetor to feel the emotions he wants to arouse in his audience. He exemplified this point by recalling his defence of Manius Aquilius, who was accused of extortion: Here was a man whom I remembered as having been consul, commander-inchief, honored by the Senate, and mounting in procession to the Capitol; on seeing him cast down, crippled, sorrowing and brought to the risk of all he held dear, I was myself overcome by compassion before I tried to excite it in others. (xlvii 195) Cicero's rendering of this scene is so powerful that it still evokes compassion in people reading it two thousand years later. Cicero insisted that rhetors must somehow bring themselves to feel the emotions they wished to arouse in their audience. Quintilian echoed this advice in his discussion of emotional appeals, and he gave a useful hint about it. If a rhetor does not actually feel the requisite emotions while he is composing, he can draw on humans' shared emotions, their natural empathy with other human beings. Using these, he can imagine how events must have affected those who suffered them: I am complaining that a man has been murdered. Shall I not bring before my eyes all the circumstances which it is reasonable to imagine must have occurred in such a connection? Shall I not see the assassin burst suddenly from his hiding-place, the victim tremble, cry for help, beg for mercy or turn to run? Shall I not see the fatal blow delivered and the stricken body fall? Will not the blood, the deathly pallor, the groan of agony, the death-rattle, be indelibly impressed upon my mind? (VI ii 31) 276 277 Rhetors who can imagine the emotions evoked by a scene may stimulate similar emotions in their audiences by deploying the power of enargeia, a figure in which rhetors picture events so vividly that they seem actually to be taking place before the audience. Vivid depictions of events, Quintilian argued, stir the emotions of an audience exactly as if they had been present when it occurred. Newswriter Scott Maxwell uses enargeia when he describes a happy scene turned tragic: DRIVING ON DAYTONA BEACH: PARK THIS ‘TRADITION’ Four-year-old Ellie Louise Bland was doing what most any little girl would do during a glorious day at Daytona Beach this past Saturday — dashing here and there, playing with her family and soaking in the sunshine and salt air. It should have been a day for making memories — the kind that inspire crayon drawings and "Guess what I did!" exclamations when the vacation's over. Except there was nothing inspirational about Ellie's beach day. For it was her last. A car stuck the preschooler and killed her. One moment, she was holding her uncle's hand. The next, a Lincoln Town Car driven by a 66-year-old visitor from Georgia ended her life. Notice how the abrupt move from Maxwell’s sunny description of a day on the beach to a grim tragedy—“for it was her last”—recreates the suddenness of the accident itself. 277 278 Maxwell then deploys this powerful enargeia in order to convince his readers that beachdriving ought to be barred: Ellie's family must be struggling with the kind of "Why?" questions that shake even the most faithful. But a question we should all be asking ourselves is: Why does Daytona still allow cars on the beach? The short answer is tradition — and money. It is cheaper for the city to allow cars to drive and park where children play than provide proper parking. But whatever the rationale, the time for this tradition has passed. Cars and children do not mix. Neither do trucks and sunbathers, SUVs and sea turtles, or a clear summer day and exhaust fumes. "I have always advocated taking cars off the beach," said Volusia County Council member Pat Northey. "As long as we treat our beach like a roadway, we're going to have to face the fact the people are going to get hurt." But Northey has been outnumbered by those who believe beach-driving is as much a part of Daytona as racing. Council member Joshua Wagner, for instance, called Ellie's death "tragic" — but stressed that he is still committed to letting people drive by the sea. "People just need to understand it's a road," said the surfer and beach native. "It's just on the sand." It sounds simple enough when Wagner says it. Then again, he's not a preschooler. 278 279 It's amazing what kind of adult rules and logic can flee the mind of a young child who just discovered a hermit crab and is thrilled at the prospect of showing it off. All of the sudden, a few posts or warning signs don't seem like much of an impediment. The descriptive writing at the end of the piece effectively recaptures the perspective of a preschooler, reinforcing Maxwell’s argument that cars and trucks driving on the beach is a problem, regardless of any longstanding traditions or economic benefits. Maxwell’s argument is both kairotic and passionate. Such enargeia—almost painful to consider—is appropriate in this instance because opponents of the current law have met with little success in arguing for its repeal. His use of enargeia to argue on behalf of nonvoting toddlers, pre-schoolers, and children casts new light on the argument by invoking the innocence of children and the tragedy of their untimely deaths. In doing so, Maxwell attempts to galvanize the people and leaders of Daytona to finally reconsider their city’s laws. But there are instances where enargeia can be taken too far and can end up inhibiting one’s argument. Signs held by animal rights activists or abortion opponents that feature enlarged, bloody photographs can be stomach-turning for a lot of viewers and risk forestalling deliberation. Such strategies are the visual equivalent of shouting in someone’s face. Honorific and Pejorative Language Another way to evoke emotions is to use words that are honorific or pejorative. Honorific language treats people and things respectfully, while pejorative language 279 280 disparages and downplays them. That is, honorific and pejorative language conveys value judgments. In the passage that follows, written by Peggy Noonan, we have bolded the words that confer value: Conservatives talked a lot about Ronald Reagan this year, but they have to take him more to heart, because his example here is a guide. All this seemed lost last week on Sarah Palin, who called him, on Fox, "an actor." She was defending her form of political celebrity—reality show, "Dancing With the Stars," etc. This is how she did it: "Wasn't Ronald Reagan an actor? Wasn't he in 'Bedtime for Bonzo,' Bozo, something? Ronald Reagan was an actor." Excuse me, but this was ignorant even for Mrs. Palin. Reagan people quietly flipped their lids, but I'll voice their consternation to make a larger point. Ronald Reagan was an artist who willed himself into leadership as president of a major American labor union (Screen Actors Guild, seven terms, 1947-59.) He led that union successfully through major upheavals (the Hollywood communist wars, labormanagement struggles); discovered and honed his ability to speak persuasively by talking to workers on the line at General Electric for eight years; was elected to and completed two full terms as governor of California; challenged and almost unseated an incumbent president of his own party; and went on to popularize modern conservative political philosophy without the help of a conservative infrastructure. Then he was elected president. The point is not "He was a great man and you are a nincompoop," though that is true. The point is that Reagan's career is a guide, not only for the tea party but for all 280 281 in politics. He brought his fully mature, fully seasoned self into politics with him. He wasn't in search of a life when he ran for office, and he wasn't in search of fame; he'd already lived a life, he was already well known, he'd accomplished things in the world. Here is an old tradition badly in need of return: You have to earn your way into politics. You should go have a life, build a string of accomplishments, then enter public service. And you need actual talent: You have to be able to bring people in and along. You can't just bully them, you can't just assert and taunt, you have to be able to persuade. Americans don't want, as their representatives, people who seem empty or crazy. They'll vote no on that. It's not just the message, it's the messenger. Noonan’s portrait of Sarah Palin is as nasty as her account of Reagan is exalted. She makes these values clear with a series of subtle linguistic jabs—you need “actual” talent, and with the blunt transition “excuse me,” she makes no secret of the offense she takes to the disrespect she reads in Palin’s gaffe. We have rewritten the passage without the honorific and pejorative language so that you can see what is lost without it: Conservatives talked a lot about Ronald Reagan this year, but they ought to think of him as more of a guide. Last week Sarah Palin called him, on Fox, "an actor." She was defending her form of political celebrity, her recent appearance on "Dancing With the Stars," for example. Here is what Palin said: "Wasn't Ronald Reagan an 281 282 actor? Wasn't he in 'Bedtime for Bonzo,' Bozo, something? Ronald Reagan was an actor." Palin’s account was unfortunate. I would like to use the incident to make a larger point. Ronald Reagan was an actor who became president of a major American labor union (Screen Actors Guild, seven terms, 1947-59.) He led that union through upheavals (the Hollywood communist wars, labor-management struggles); discovered and honed his ability to speak persuasively by talking to workers on the line at General Electric for eight years; was elected to and completed two full terms as governor of California; he challenged and almost unseated an incumbent president of his own party; and went on to popularize modern conservative political philosophy without the help of a conservative infrastructure. He was later elected president. The point is that Reagan's career is a guide, not only for the tea party but for all in politics. He brought his self into politics with him. He wasn't in search of a life when he ran for office, and he wasn't in search of fame; he'd already lived a life, he was already well known, he'd accomplished a number of things. People should have to earn their way into politics. They should go have a life, build up their accomplishments, then enter public service. To do so requires talent: one needs to be able to bring people in and along. One needs to be able to persuade. Americans don't want, as their representatives, inexperienced, unpredictable people. They'll vote no on that. It's not just the message, it's the messenger. Without the honorific and pejorative language, much of the emotional appeal of the original 282 283 passage dissipates. The author’s ethos changes as well, becoming more distant and formal. The revision is also far less interesting than the original, which suggests that pejorative terms are colorful, emphatic, and hence persuasive. We encourage our readers to use these strategies to insert pathetic appeals into their own speaking and writing. Try adding honorific or pejorative language into a description of an issue, or try composing an enargeia to gain your readers’ or listeners’ attention and to create a compelling scene for your argument. We think that if you compose these appeals carefully, with an eye toward the rhetorical situations you face, you will find that listeners and readers may respond to your propositions and arguments more warmly than they might have without your use of these appeals. Rhetorical Activities 1. Try creating an emotional appeal to use in an argument you are working on. If you are not working in a specific rhetorical situation at the moment, invent one. That is, describe an audience and an issue. Now decide what the emotional state of your designated audience is likely to be. Decide what emotions would rouse them to action, or at least move them to change their minds. Create an appeal to that emotion. Now create an enargeia, a vivid scene, that is calculated to rouse the requisite emotions. 2. Select a proposition from your own repertoire of beliefs--that is, from your ideology. For example, perhaps you believe that the United States ought to intervene the affairs of other countries for humanitarian reasons. Perhaps you support the legal status of abortion, or perhaps you oppose the death penalty. Now imagine an audience of one or more persons who are either hostile or indifferent to your proposition. Write a description of a 283 284 rhetorical situation in which you attempt to persuade this audience to accept your proposition. Try to figure out why your audience is hostile or indifferent to you or to your proposition. Compose a list of their possible emotional responses either to the issue or to your situated ethos. List some pathetic proofs you might use to persuade its members to accept your premise, or at least to examine it. 3. Think of a rhetorical situation in which an appeal to anger is appropriate. Compose the appeal. Now try composing appeals to other emotions discussed in this chapter. In what context would an appeal to shame be effective? Compassion? Hopelessness? 4. Advertisers often rely on fear--particularly the fear of losing status in the community--to get people to buy things. Find some examples of ads that do this. Do advertisers exploit other emotional appeals such as anger or dread or love or hope? 5. Are Aristotle and Cicero’s lists of emotions complete? That is, can you think of other emotions that are used in contemporary emotional appeals? For example, desire is often appealed to in contemporary rhetoric. Politicians say that “The American people want” this or that, and advertisers create extremely subtle appeals to desire, especially erotic desire. Perfume is a good example here—perfumes are often advertised with nothing but a photograph of a handsome actor’s face and a bottle of perfume. Are such ads effective? Why or why not? Can you think of other examples? Is desire an emotion? 5. Keep a list of the honorific and pejorative terms that you come across in your reading. Once it has become long enough (fifty examples each of honorific and pejorative terms should do), study the list to determine whether or not they tell you something about 284 285 community values. List of Works Cited Brennan, Teresa. The Transmission of Affect. Ithaca NY: Cornell UP, 2004. Damasio, Anthony. Descartes’ Error: Emotion, Reason, and the Human Brain. New York: Harper Collins 1994. Dowd, Maureen. “A Storyteller Loses the Story Line.” The New York Times. June 1, 2010. http://www.nytimes.com/2010/06/02/opinion/02dowd.html. Online. Feller, Ben. “White House Hits Back at Carter Remarks.” Yahoo News, 20 May 2007. http://news.yahoo.com/s/ap/20070520/ap_on_go_pr_wh/bush_carter. Accessed 05/23/07. Maxwell, Scott. “Driving on Daytona Beach: Park this ‘Tradition.’” Orlando Sentinel March 23, 2010, http://articles.orlandosentinel.com/2010-03-23/news/os-scott-maxwellbeach-drive-032310-20100322_1_ellie-cars-drive-and-park. Online Mitchell, W.J.T. Picture Theory. Chicago: U of Chicago Press, 1994. Noonan, Peggy. “Americans Vote for Maturity.” Wall Street Journal November 5, 2010. http://online.wsj.com/article/SB10001424052748703805704575594772776292394.ht ml. Online. Obama, Barack. “Oval Office Address to the Nation on BP Oil Spill.” Delivered June 15, 2010. http://www.americanrhetoric.com/speeches/barackobama/barackobamabpoilspilloval office.htm. Online. 285 286 Prendergast, Catherine. Buying into English. Pittsburgh: U of Pittsburgh Press, 2008. Rich, Frank. “The Clear Blue Sky.” Review of Falling Man by Don DeLillo. New York Times. May 27, 2007: section 7, p. 1; 8-9. Print. Scraton, Phil. “Introduction: Witnessing ‘Terror,” Anticipating ‘War’.” In Beyond September 11: An Anthology of Dissent. Ed. Phil Scraton. 1-10. London: Pluto Press, 2002. 286 287 287