STIGLITZ2003rev Global Public Economics A B Atkinson, Nuffield College, OXFORD 1 Global Public Economics My title combines the research interests of Joe Stiglitz circa 1970 with those of Joe Stiglitz today. In the late 1960s/early 1970s, there was a flowering of the field of “public economics”. This brought together the theorems of general equilibrium and the tools of dynamic optimisation with the traditional concerns of public finance and welfare economics. Consideration of equity and efficiency drew on the latest developments in moral philosophy. It was a heady cocktail. Arrow-Debreu and Ramsey-Samuelson and Bentham-Rawls all mixed into Richard Musgrave’s Theory of Public Finance (1959). It was a cocktail that brought not just refreshment but also considerable insight into the analysis of policy. There were advances in understanding both positive and normative issues. The lessons of public economics have wider application than to public finance issues, but these lessons have diffused slowly. Robert Lucas once remarked that, as a macro-economist, he had “greatly enjoyed [his] excursion into public finance ... How refreshing it is to spend some time in the company of a group of applied economists who simply take for granted the desirability of using (and extending) the powerful methods of dynamic general equilibrium theory to gain a deeper understanding of policy issues” (1990, page 314). This remark is generous but reveals the extent to which public economics has not been assimilated into the mainstream of economics. Its main lessons have not been fully disseminated in the profession. Nowhere is this failure of communication greater than discussions about globalisation. Many of the global issues being currently discussed are concerned with public policy: tax competition, survival of welfare states, global public goods, trade policy, role of multinational corporations, worldwide inequality, and the financing of the Millennium Development Goals. In order to create a global public economics, at least three elements are required. The first, on which considerable progress has already been made, is the analysis of national policy in a global context. Models of tax competition, for example, have been extensively investigated. Here I concentrate on two further elements: the need for developing models appropriate for the analysis of policy incidence in an interdependent world, and the application of principles of cosmopolitan justice to the normative issues of global policy making. There are of course many other promising avenues, but space does not allow me to explore them here. 2 Modelling Policy in an Interdependent World One important ingredient in making progress in economic analysis has been the development of new models. A classic example is the introduction into public finance by Arnold Harberger (1962) of the two-sector general equilibrium model widely used in international trade theory. The model allowed the formalisation of existing insights into tax incidence and the derivation of new results. The trade model provides the example that I take here. The standard Heckscher-Ohlin model of 2 countries, each with 2 sectors, using 2 factors (“the 2 x 2 x 2 model”) has been used to examine the implications of different redistributive policies in a model of increasing global trade. Contrasts have been drawn between a country with clearing competitive 2 labour markets (the “US”) and a country with a wage floor governed by minimum wage legislation or unemployment benefit (“Continental Europe”). Opening up of trade with newly industrialising countries (NICs) shifts demand away from products that use unskilled labour intensively. In the “US” case, the relative wage of unskilled workers falls, causing increased wage dispersion. In the “European” case, relative wages are fixed, and the result is unemployment for unskilled workers. In this way, we have a unified explanation as to how a single cause – increased trade with NICs - has a differential impact on the US and on Continental Europe. However, as Donald Davis (1998) has pointed out, we cannot look at two parallel universes with 2 trading regions (in one case US and NIC, and in the other Europe and NIC). We need a minimum of 3 trading regions (US, NIC and Europe). If in a unified analysis the US and Europe both produce the good that faces NIC competition, then the wage floor in Europe determines the relative goods prices (in a standard two good two-factor Heckscher-Ohlin model, where it is assumed that one good uses unskilled labour relatively intensively). If the minimum wage is unchanged, this prevents the relative price from falling. The US is therefore unaffected by increased trade. Europe bears the brunt in terms of unemployment. On this basis, the outcry about globalisation should be in Europe not in the US. On the other hand, Europe may be protected to a degree because it has already become specialised in goods that use skilled labour intensively. If, in the standard trade theory model, we allow the EU to have become specialised, then the consequences of opening trade are different. Suppose that the NICs are specialised in the good that uses unskilled labour intensively. Their entry into world trade drives down the price of this good, and hence causes the relative wage of unskilled workers to fall in the US, which produces both goods. We then have the US side of the textbook conclusion, but not the 3 European side, since the demand for the good using skilled labour intensively is higher, causing a fall in unemployment. Either way, one or other part of the explanation cannot apply. It is not therefore a simple application of standard theory of the Heckscher-Ohlin variety. The model has to be expanded. We have to move to a 3 x 2 x 2 model. In many cases, moving from 2 to 3 in economics adds nothing but complexity. But here the third dimension is crucial. Indeed, I believe that we need 3 factors and 3 goods as well as 3 countries: a 3 x 3 x 3 model. The 2 factors identified above were skilled and unskilled labour. This serves to highlight one aspect of income distribution: the dispersion of wages. It does not however illuminate the role of capital income. Changes in the real rate of return can have powerful distributional consequences, particularly at the very top of the distribution. We need therefore to incorporate capital as a third factor. This allows us to address the classic, but now neglected, question of the distribution of national income between capital and labour. The behaviour of factor shares must be part of the story. Factor shares in turn have to be linked to the distribution of income among persons. Here, the model of Stiglitz (1969), drawing on the work of James Meade (1964), remains the key theoretical reference, even if it needs to be supplemented by introducing intermediaries such as pension funds. Much of the structural change in modern industrialised economies concerns, not agriculture and manufacturing, but manufacturing and services. The growth of service employment is a major element. We need therefore a three good model. Services may in the past have been treated as a non-traded good, but this may be changing as a result of new technology. Indeed, one way of representing the impact of increased globalisation would be to open to international trade the third service sector in a 3 x 3 x 3 model. 4 The model has moreover to be made dynamic. Factor supplies are evolving over time. Skill is a matter for investment as well as endowment, and the incentive to invest depends on the rate of return. Rising dispersion may in part be a reflection of a rising real rate of return on capital. Here too is work for the research agenda. The model of structural change advanced by Simon Kuznets (1955) has been used to throw light on the evolution of the distribution of income by Sudhir Anand and Ravi Kanbur (1993), among others, but the standard Kuznets model lacks both of the ingredients in which we are interested. The economy is assumed closed to foreign trade, so that globalisation has no direct role. There is no redistributive state. Nor is the accumulation of capital usually treated explicitly. The model has to be enriched to provide a basis for the analysis of public policy in a global context. I introduced the example by reference to the role of economic models, but the policy relevance is clear. The role of the welfare state in a globalising world is one of the central policy issues facing Europe, and the implications of European decisions will be felt in the US and in the developing world. The US policymakers calling for greater labour market flexibility in Europe may be aware that this can raise the rate of return to capital in the US. This possibility is not however widely recognised in the public debate. Nor is the impact on the US labour market. A weakening of the position of the less skilled in Europe will spill over to the US. Moreover, if the relative wage of the unskilled falls in Europe, this will reduce the relative price of the good using unskilled labour intensively, and this will turn the terms of trade against the newly industrialising countries. World output may rise, but some of the gains to European economic performance may be achieved at the expense of poorer countries. If welfare states in Europe become more ‘competitive’, then this can reduce the opportunities for the rest of the world. 5 3 Cosmopolitan Justice and Global Redistribution The evaluation of policy has been a key part of public economics. Its role has perhaps been misunderstood. A false dichotomy has been created between public choice theory and welfare economics. The purpose of the literature on optimum taxation, for example, is to illuminate the structure of arguments that take place within a political context. It seeks to test these arguments and see whether the policies proposed in the political debate follow from the professed objectives of the protagonists. In a national context, welfare economic arguments have often been founded, explicitly or implicitly, on a moral calculus. The whole Pigouvian tradition of public finance was deeply influenced by Benthamite utilitarianism. As it was put by Paul Samuelson, “to a man like Edgeworth ... individual utility – nay social utility – was as real as his morning jam” (1947, page 206). More recently, it has been recognised that individual welfares can be aggregated in different ways, ranging from distributional indifference through to Rawlsian concern with the least advantaged. And a variety of non-welfarist objectives have been taken into account, including explicit treatment of horizontal equity. As shown by Stiglitz (1982), horizontal equity may be a biding constraint on policymakers, since the pursuit of social welfare maximisation, or even Pareto efficiency, may be aided by random taxation. In a global context, however, we cannot appeal to such ready-made principles, and the calculus is more complex. The issue has been well stated by Amartya Sen (1999). He distinguishes two positions and argues that neither is satisfactory. The first is “national particularism”, where welfare judgments are made for each nation treated separately, and then the relations between nations governed by an over-arching 6 judgment involving international equity. Whereas one can understand some of the principles that may apply to the over-arching judgment, this form of “two stage” evaluation does not allow, as Sen notes, for direct relations across national boundaries. Direct consideration of the position of individuals may call into question policy changes positively evaluated by this procedure but which involve transfers from poor people in richer countries to richer people in poor countries. The second position responds to such concerns by supposing what Sen calls a “grand universalism”, where we have a global social welfare function in which everyone enters symmetrically and where nationality has no role. On this view, the country in which one lives has no intrinsic claim on our attention. Such a position is, in my view, less easily dismissed. A global social welfare function is a valid point of reference. However, it would not be sensible to construct a normative theory of global public finance solely on this basis, totally ignoring nationality. National governments, by revealed preference, appear to give greater weight to their citizens, and it would be natural to consider the implications of national social welfare functions where citizens received a greater weight than non-citizens. Some people may suppose that these matters are largely abstract. In fact they are highly relevant to the issues of public policy with which Joe Stiglitz has been involved in recent years. The World Bank regularly publishes estimates of the number of people in developing countries whose income is less than $1 a day, and halving the proportion poor is one of the Millennium Development Goals (MDGs). To achieve the full set of MDGs is going to require a substantial increase in the flow of resources for development. In considering how this flow is to be ensured, one has to consider the impact on people in the transferring counties. Are higher taxes in donor countries going to be borne in part by lower income groups, aggravating poverty in those 7 countries? If so, then how can these be balanced? We then have to confront the tension between `absolute' definitions of poverty, such as the $1 a day standard, and the thoroughgoing relativity adopted in many OECD countries when measuring poverty, where the poverty line is set as a percentage of median income. On the first basis, there is little or no poverty in donor countries, but on the second basis risk of poverty remains a serious concern, as witnessed by the European Union programme for social inclusion. How can these be reconciled? One line of reasoning is to postulate a hierarchy or lexicographic order - in the field of poverty. Poverty is first defined on an absolute basis as referring to people whose income is insufficient to cover physical basic needs. When this is achieved, poverty is then defined on a relative basis as referring to people whose income does not allow them to function properly in their social environment. In this case, meeting the MDGs would have priority. A second line of reasoning consists of making relative and absolute poverty two dimensions to be evaluated jointly through some aggregate index. Such a view leads to defining poverty uniformly in all countries as some combination of the absolute and relative poverty concepts. As is developed in Atkinson and Bourguignon (2000), overall poverty is a weighted combination of poverty in developing and developed countries. Such a measure may become increasingly appropriate as an increasing number of countries acquire middle-income status. The welfare economic basis for global public economics is an important area for future research. In grappling with these questions, economics can fruitfully cooperate with other disciplines. In particular, the flowering of literature on cosmopolitan justice in the fields of political theory and philosophy may well influence global public economics in the same way that John Rawls and Robert Nozick influenced national public economics 30 years ago. 8 References Anand, S and Kanbur, S M R, 1993, “The Kuznets process and the inequalitydevelopment relationship”, Journal of Development Economics, vol 40: 25-52. Atkinson, A B and Bourguignon, F, 2000, “Poverty and Inclusion from a World Perspective” in H de la Largentaye, P-A Muet, J-F Rischard and J E Stiglitz, editors, Governance, Equity and Global Markets, La Documentation Française, Paris. Davis, D R, 1998, ‘Does European unemployment prop up American wages? National Labor Markets and Global Trade’. American Economic Review, vol 88/3: 478-494. Harberger, A C, 1962, “The incidence of the corporation income tax”, Journal of Political Economy, vol 70: 215-240. Kuznets, S, 1955, "Economic Growth and Income Inequality". American Economic Review, vol 45: 1-28. Lucas, R E, 1990, “Supply-Side Economics: An Analytical Review”, Oxford Economic Papers, vol 42: 293-316. Musgrave, R A,1959. Theory of Public Finance. New York: McGraw-Hill. Samuelson, P A, 1947, Foundations of Economic Analysis, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Mass. Sen, A K, 1999, “Global Justice: Beyond International Equity” in I Kaul, I Grunberg and M A Stern, editors, Global Public Goods, Oxford University Press, Oxford. Stiglitz, J E, 1969, “Distribution of income and wealth among individuals”, Econometrica, vol 37: 382-397. Stiglitz, J E, 1982, “Utilitarianism and horizontal equity: The case for random taxation”, Journal of Public Economics, vol 18: 1-33. 9