Animalism and the Unborn Human Being Christopher Tollefsen University of South Carolina Recent work in the metaphysics of identity seems indebted to a revival of the Aristotelian distinction between substance and accident, a revival possibly to be attributed to David Wiggins’ Sameness and Substance. As Wiggins points out, everything that exists is a “this such,” and it is the concept under which a thing falls as a this such, rather than concepts that indicate what it is doing, or what color it is, and so on, that tells us what the thing is.1 For at least some things that we ordinarily characterize as particulars, the concept under which they fall as particulars will be their substance concept.2 It is this concept that tells us what the thing in question most truly is, and, as Eric Olson writes, it is this concept that “determines persistence conditions that necessarily apply to all (and perhaps only) things of that kind.”3 The language of substance may not be equally amenable to all, but everyone involved in the abortion debate at a philosophical level has an interest in understanding what you and I and things of our sort are most fundamentally, because this understanding will determine when we come to be, as well as when we cease to be. And, as Patrick Lee has pointed out, what most defenders of abortion have held, implicitly or explicitly, until recently, is that you and I are essentially persons.4 “Person” was then understood in a quasi-Lockean way to involve such properties as psychological continuity or 1 David Wiggins, Sameness and Substance (Oxford: Blackwell, 1980) p. 15. Although the sortal concepts under which particular artifacts fall are analogous to substance concepts, I do not think artifacts are substances in a proper sense, as I will argue below. 3 Eric Olson, The Human Animal (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997) p. 28. v “Kind” here should be understood with some specificity: not just “animal,” but “dog” or “cat.” So if a dog were to gradually be changed into a cat, that dog would cease to exist. 4 Patrick Lee, “A Christian Philosopher’s View of Recent Directions in the Abortion Debate,” Christian Bioethics, forthcoming. 2 connectedness, and from this it was inferred that no person existed prior to the presence of such psychological properties. It was an easy step from this to the conclusion that embryos and fetuses, lacking the relevant psychological properties, were not persons, and thus were not entitled to the respect ordinarily due persons. Problems with the view that you and I are essentially persons have been apparent for quite some time; for one thing, this would mean that you and I were the same kind of substance as intelligent Martians, angels, and perhaps members of the Trinity; but why think we have their persistence conditions? But Eric Olson has raised perhaps the most damning objection. Olson points out that on the received view, you and I were never, for example, fetuses, for you and I are essentially persons, and substances of the person sort do not come to exist until the onset of psychological traits. But fetuses themselves seem to belong to a substance class – they are particulars of the substance sort “human animal.” And this raises problems for the view that you and I are essentially persons. What, for example, has happened to that other substance, the human animal? Does it continue to exist in the same space as the human person? Did it cease to exist with the coming to be of the human person? If the former, how can it not share exactly all of the person’s properties, and if so, why is it not also a person? If the latter, is there now no longer a human animal in the space that I occupy? None of the options seems metaphysically palatable.5 The solution is that you and I are essentially human animals; thus you and I were once fetuses, and, at least plausibly, embryos as well. But if you and I are not essentially See Olson, The Human Animal, especially chapter 4. Lynne Baker’s “Constitutionalism” attempts to provide a middle account between the previous dualism and Olson’s animalism. I critique her arguments against animalism, and her defense of constitutionalism in my “Persons in Time,” American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly, forthcoming. 5 persons, but animals, what sort of concept is the concept “person”, and when and how do we become persons? Olson’s answer might seem to be the only possible option here: “person” is a phased sortal, like “teacher” or “ambulator.” Human animals move into a stage of personhood, and possibly out of it, while remaining the same substance, just as a baby’s substance does not change when she learns to walk. This move from the metaphysics of identity has been appropriated in the ethics of abortion. It is no longer metaphysically plausible to hold that you and I are essentially persons which come to be late in the career of an animal; so personhood should, like “ambulator” be viewed as an achievement, rather than a status; and human animals, like other animals, may be killed when they are not persons. One upshot of this discussion is this: Insofar as defenders of abortion accept that you and I are essentially animals, then they must argue that you and I are not as such worthy of respect. Many philosophers have pointed out how deeply arbitrary such a position is bound to be in determining who is worthy of respect. But it seems to me to be subject to even further difficulties. The earlier view was dualistic, separating the substance that I am, from the animal substance I am associated with. This involves an alienation from that bodily nature, an alienation that Germain Grisez, John Finnis, and Joseph Boyle have argued is theoretically untenable.6 Still, untenable though it may be philosophically, it seems psychologically possible – I take myself not to be that animal, and am alienated from it as from other things that I am not. The new account seems even more problematic from the first person practical standpoint, however, for it seems to involve, as did the earlier account, a rejection of my 6 See John Finnis, Joseph M. Boyle, Jr., and Germain Grisez, Nuclear Deterrence, Morality, and Realism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987) pp. 308-309. bodily nature, but now with that nature understood as mine. That is, under the earlier conception, on which you and I were essentially persons, the animal, the embodied being, was other than I, other than you. You and I were essentially alienated from that bodily nature, but there was perhaps some solace in the essentiality of the alienation. On the new conception, I am that bodily being, but if I am valuable only insofar as I have achieved the status of personhood, then I am not only, on my own self conception, alienated from the embodied animal, but from myself, for I am, by my own self understanding, that embodied animal. I can not, on this view, attribute to myself as such the value and worth that demands respect, from others or from myself. This would seem to be a form of practical alienation from oneself that gives reason to reject the claim that the animal that I essentially am only gradually becomes worthy of respect. 7 So animalism leads quite naturally to the view that respect is due to a human being from the time that it starts to exist as a human being.8 7 This difficulty is replicated in our relations to others. Consider in this light also the related, and very disturbing, set of attitudes manifested by David Boonin towards his son, Eli. Boonin, in his recent book on abortion, writes that on his desk are several pictures of his son at various ages. But “through all the remarkable changes that these pictures preserve, he remains unmistakably the same little boy.” Boonin then goes on to say: “In the top drawer of my desk I keep another picture of Eli. This picture was taken on September 7, 1993, 24 weeks before he was born…There is no doubt in my mind that this picture, too, shows the same little boy at a very early stage in his physical development. And there is no question that the position I defend in this book entails that it would have been morally permissible to end his life at this point.” But what can the willingness to have ended what he acknowledges was his own son’s existence be but an alienation from his son, a failure to fully accept his son’s existence as in a relationship to his own. 8 What, then, should we say about the relationship between the concepts of “human being” and “person”? Two possible strategies seems promising. The first would be to abandon the notion of “person” altogether. A direct argument to the effect that human animals were the sorts of beings that deserved moral respect would then be required, and would presumably, be available on grounds familiar from earlier stages of the debate. I view this as rather a pragmatic move, which concedes that the concept of person has been so abused in the abortion debate that it is no longer helpful in making the essential points that you and I are deserving of moral respect in virtue of what we are, rather than what we achieve. Jenny Teichman seems to adopt such a strategy. A second strategy is that pursued by, e.g., David Braine, in The Human Animal. Braine denies that the only two options are that “person” is a substance concept or a phased sortal concept, arguing instead that it is a “range concept.” Such concepts “always indicate the subjects, not of just one predicate, but of a family of interrelated predicates, a family united by a role in a mass of discourse, in the case of ‘person’ a role in statements with a certain place in schemes of historical explanation.”8 Animalism has at least tacitly been a crucial element in another discussion concerning unborn human life in recent years. Discussion of abortion has recently been somewhat surpassed by discussion of embryo creation and research. But the strategy of those favoring creation of, and research on early human embryos is not simply to deny personhood to these embryos but to make the stronger claim that these embryos, because of their potentiality for twinning, are not even human beings at all. Why should twinning be thought to militate against the humanity of the early embryo? One crucial consideration in the argument concerns the individuality of that early embryo. Recall the Aristotelian suggestion hearkened to by David Wiggins, that everything that exists exists as a this such. So any particular substance will be a member of some substance kind, but it will also be an individual in its own right. Indeed, this consideration is of somewhat unrecognized importance in considering whether certain sorts of entities that appear to be substances really are. For if something genuinely is a this such a substance then it should be the case that it has determinate identity conditions, even if it is not always possible to identify them, or to identify whether they are satisfied or not. That is, there should always be a definite yes or no answer to the question: is this the same substance as that (was). It is clear that this condition is not met by some things that for more or less pragmatic and social reasons are given names and treated as if they were genuine individuals. For example, a pile of trash is not really a substance. Its beginnings and its endings are vague and a matter of convention, as are, in fact, its physical boundaries. When large bits of the pile are replaced, there need be no definite yes or no answer to the question “Is this the same pile of trash as the one that was here yesterday?” There are other arguments for not treating the pile of trash as a genuine substance. The pile of trash, for instance, does not have its own causal powers. Although it appears to stink, and to thus to cause the wrinkling of noses in its vicinity, and to attract flies, the causal powers of the trash seem entirely reducible to the causal powers of its parts, and ultimately to its smallest parts. This does not appear to be true of organisms: that this is a dog, or a cat, or a human being, enters necessarily into our explanation of why this is chasing a rabbit, or a mouse, or a high paying job.9 Philosophers such as Trenton Merricks and Peter van Inwagen have extended these arguments so as to argue that in fact none of the ordinary artifacts that we find around us daily are, after all, genuine individual substances. Merricks and van Inwagen thus conclude that such artifacts are not really entities after all: there are no baseballs, no statues, no flags, merely simples arranged baseball-wise, statue-wise and flag-wise. In essence, it seems to me, there arguments work by showing that everything that is not an individual substance is ultimately a kind of heap, any one of which might be more or less important to us in our social life, but all of which are ontologically on par with one another. There are of course, counterexamples, but even these serve to bring out the differences between the causality of a substance and that of, especially artifacts. It is true, as Lynne Baker argues, that statues, not statue shaped rocks, raise our insurance premiums, and that flags bring a tear to our eye.10 But they do not do this in the way that I raise my hand, or the dog brings the ball. The statue and the flag interact with members of the social world in such a way that members of the social world themselves change or 9 Thanks to Pat Lee for this. Lynne Rudder Baker, “Review: Trenton Merrics Objects and Persons,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 81 (2003) 597-598. 10 bring about change. But while the flag qua flag has this sort of derivative social causality, it has no agency of the sort that humans, dogs, and cats have. Such entities themselves act, albeit in different ways. The agency of substances, and their individuality in a substance kind, are not unrelated. Individual substances have the sort of agency that they have in virtue of the sorts of things they re – dogs have a doggy agency just as humans have a human agency. And this is in turn related to the claims about the persistence conditions for substances following from what they are: they persist as long as they able minimally to maintain the processes necessary for their particular, i.e., species specific, forms of agency, and to continue, even if in a greatly attenuated manner, some form of their appropriate agency. Substances are self-movers, and their form of motion is species specific; hence any individual substance will play a crucial and unique explanatory role as a substance in a number of causal stories.11 This hardly exhausts what can be said about substances, but many of the traditional attributes of substance would seem to follow from these: an individual substance would need to have fairly definite boundaries, for example. But two further characteristics deserve mention here. First, substances must have definite beginnings and endings; I will briefly defend this claim later in the paper. Second, substances cannot be composed of other substances. As discussed above, substances are agents, and their autonomy is not entirely derivative from the action of their parts. But this in turn must mean that the activity of the parts is not entirely intelligible apart from their role in their 11 It follows that artifacts of any kind, and non-organic but natural beings are not substances. Does this mean that they are not objects or entities as Merricks and van Inwagen would have it? I see no reason to be so parsimonious: “object” and entity”, like “exist”, don’t seem to me to be univocal terms. A baseball is an entity in a lesser sense than a dog because it is not a substance. whole – their substance. Thus Aristotle’s famous claim about the detached finger being a finger in name only – separate a part of a substance from the whole of which it is a part, and it is no longer the sort of thing it was as a part. But if the substance-parts cannot, as such, have this kind of independent agency and intelligibility, then they cannot themselves be substances.12 So why, then, does the early embryo’s capacity for twinning render it unfit to be an individual substance? Which specific criterion does it fail to meet? And what is its status supposed to be in the time period in which “it” is not yet a human animal? Two proposals in particular are of importance here. The first is that precisely because of the early embryo’s capacity for twinning, it cannot be an individual. But if not an individual, then not a substance, and hence not a human animal. This argument seeks to show that because of what the embryo can do, it cannot be an individual; similarly, if some supposed entity was capable of shaking hands and going two separate ways, it too would not be an individual substance.13 The second argument relies on a Lockean claim, plausible in itself, about what is responsible for the persistence of some particular organic substance. Peter van Inwagen summarizes the claim: If an organism exists at a certain moment, then it exists whenever and wherever and only when and only where the event that is its life at that moment is occurring; more exactly, if the activity of the xs at t1 constitutes 12 This is not to say, of course, that we cannot say a considerable amount about the parts by abstracting from their role in the whole: the cells of the finger have much in common with the cells of the spleen, at the biological level. It is also worth pointing out that it is traditional to say of a cell that it is an organism, just as the larger substance of which it is a part is an organism. This is fine, so long as it is not understood to imply that an individual cell that is a part of a dog, say, is a substance. 13 An example which owes something to Parfit’s divided and reimplanted brain halves who eventually play tennis together. a life, and the activity of the ys at t2 constitutes a life, then the organism that the xs compose at t1 is the organism that the ys compose at t2 if and only if the life constituted by the activity of the xs at t1 is the life constituted by the activity of the ys at t2.(145) Now a one-celled zygote has a life; it is a single organism. And an embryo at, say, three weeks has a life; it, too is a single organism. But van Inwagen claims that the two-celled “organism”, and similar collections of cells, do not have a shared life: They adhere to each other, but we have seen that that is no reason to suppose that two objects compose anything. The zygote was a single, unified organism, the vast assemblage of metabolic processes that were its life having been directed by the activity of nucleic acid in its nucleus. No such statement can be made about the two-cell embryo. No event, I should say, is its life. The space it occupies is merely an arena in which two lives, hardly interacting, take place….It seems to me most implausible to suppose that the developing embryo is yet an organism if it is still at the stage at which monozygotic twinning can occur…if an embryo is still capable of twinning, then it is a mere virtual object. (153-4) Here two arguments run together. The first is an empirical argument about the biological life of the early embryo: in van Inwagen’s view, that “life” is insufficiently unified to constitute a single life, just as the lives of two adhering paramecia would be insufficiently unified to compose one organism. The second argument is the earlier conceptual argument about twinning: anything that can twin cannot itself be a single organism, for this capacity is incompatible with being an individual. The empirical, biological issue has a certain obvious priority over the conceptual issue here. Surely, it is theoretically imperative first to look at whether the purported entity in question the early human embryo seems to have one life, or to be a collection of several lives. For if it is best characterized biologically as a single organism, then this should determine the answer to the conceptual question: can a biologically unified substance have the potential to divide into two independent substances? By way of analogy: one might have thought that it was conceptually impossible for a human organism to come to by any other means than by the fertilization of an egg by a sperm. But if human cloning is, as seems most likely, a physical possibility, then the purported conceptual impossibility is not, after all, a conceptual impossibility at all. I believe that the biological evidence gives good grounds for thinking that the embryo is the subject of an individual life, specifically an individual human life.14 There is much that could be said about all that is going on in the early embryo, but I wish to make only one general remark about the relationship between the biology and what has been said so far. There are many good summaries of the early development of the embryo. Barry Smith and Berit Brogaard provide an excellent such summary in their article “Sixteen Days.”15 As they show, the process begins with fertilization, after which there are a number of cell divisions that take place within the physical boundaries of the zona pullicida. Some subsequent steps in the progress towards gastrulation, in which cell See the reviews of the relevant evidence in A.A. Howsepian, “Who, or What Are We?” The Review of Metaphysics; 45 (1992) 483-502; Mark Johnson, “Delayed Hominization: Reflections on Some Recent Catholic Claims for Delayed Hominization,” Theological Studies 56 (1995) 743-763; and Patrick Lee, op. cit. 15 Barry Smith and Berit Brogaard, “Sixteen Days,” The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 28 (2003) 4578. 14 folds form the predecessor structures for a variety of bodily parts and organs, and neurulation, in which the initial structures of the nervous system are generated, include implantation, which is prior to gastrulation, and the formation of the morula. We may note in these names the passive voice of science: the stages are viewed as happenings, somewhat as we say that mistakes were made, when we wish to avoid taking responsibility. But the description as a whole gives the unmistakable impression, apart from other salient features, of a single entity acting with purpose: develop body parts, and implant in the uterus in order that the entity in question can begin to take in nutrition and establish firmer and more rigorous boundaries, in order that the entity in question can continue to grow and develop. Consider the following passage from Smith and Brogaard: The blastocyst, on completing its journey along the fallopian tube into the uterine cavity, moves into a position where it is in contact with the uterine wall, to which it adheres via its sticky exterior. Cells on its outer surface then begin to grow rapidly in such a way as to disrupt the surface of the wall. These cells actively burrow into the deeper tissue until they have become completely embedded (Smith and Brogard, pp. 55-56). What is the subject of this sort of activity? Is it the activity of a unified substance, or is it the activity of a collection of substances? It should be admitted that if we look only at the relations between the various cells of the early embryo, it can appear that they lack sufficient connection and relation to one another, as van Inwagen suggests, to be parts of a single entity. But leaving aside this question, on which there is also evidence to the contrary,16 when we look at the whole we seem to see a single self-directed entity, the nature of whose self-direction is species specific: the course of events outlined by Smith 16 See the literature cited in note 13. and others is the characteristic course of activity of the early human embryo in much the same way that it is characteristic of the adult dog to chase rabbits. What is the alternative? Only that the hundreds, and eventually thousands, of cells that are present prior to and during gastrulation and neurulation, each have their own species specific nature that causes them to bring about, each individually, a massively complex state of affairs that has not been coordinated by a single agent. Such a possibility seems to violate Ockham’s razor: why think that the many do what appears to be done by one? But suppose that that is the case. A new puzzle arises: what is the nature of the transition from these thousands of independent substances to a state of affairs in which there is but one unitary substance? It is this puzzle that I address in the remainder of the paper. In what follows, I identify three possible accounts of this position, all of which seem implausible. The first possibility seems to be the least likely: the various cells compose something – they are not an aggregate -- that is human, but not a human being, but that is coming to be a human being.17 But substances, of which human animals are perhaps the paradigm, are substances by virtue of their nature, or essence; this essence specifies the what-it-is-to-be of the individual substance, including that substance’s species-specific activities. Nothing is a substance without an essence. But the essence seems not only necessary for the existence of a substance, but, when enmattered, sufficient: except in the mind, the what-it-is of something simply does not seem to be the sort of thing that can exist save as a this-such. But if the cells composed something human, that was not a human being, this would seem to require the presence of the essence, in matter, without the substance. This seems absurd. 17 This seemed to be Elizabeth Anscombe’s position. What, then, about hearts or cell tissues, kept alive in a lab? These seem to be human, but not human beings. But these cases do not fall outside the range of those considered: artificially sustained hearts, or cell-lines are parts, or, better, potential parts, of human substances. They are not, themselves, self-maintaining and self-directing. They are not themselves, it seems, genuine entities, any more than the severed finger, but because their potentiality to be reintegrated into a substance en masse can be artificially maintained, it makes pragmatic sense to treat them as discrete realities. They are not good analogues for some real thing that is human but not a human being. Moreover, the way in which they eventually achieve a substantial existence, if they do, is crucial: it is only by integration that they will ever exist “as” substances.18 This is an instance of what Smith and Brogaard, in their taxonomy of “The Varieties of Substance Formation,” call absorption. It is not, in fact, a mode of substance formation, since there are no more, and no new substances, than before.19 But it is a way in which something appropriately related to a substance becomes “substantial.” But if the early embryo were like this, then it too would require the presence of a substance into which it would become integrated, nor would it be capable on its own of achieving that integration. But this is not the case. So the early embryo – the so-called pre-embryo – cannot be “human” in the way that a heart or a cell line is. The second possibility is that the early embryo is just an aggregate like the pile of trash. But an aggregate of what? Clearly of human cells, i.e., potential human parts. But then how does the aggregate cease to be an aggregate and become a substance? Potential 18 Not, of course, that they will be substances: they will be actual parts of a substance. Smith and Broaard think there is one less substance than before, but for reasons given in the paper, I don’t hold the heart or tissue to be substances. Smith and Brogaard’s actual example is of a cat-tail being reattached. 19 parts seem to become actual parts by integration into a substance, which we have seen is not the case. But can a collection ever become a substance with no external action, such as an act of God, being wrought upon it? Unlike the meeting of sperm and egg, on which more shortly, the purported substantial change involves no cessation of the various “parts” which enter into the change. At one moment there is a collection insufficiently organized and interrelated to constitute a single entity, and with no nature of its own, and at another, magically, there is a substance. This too seems absurd. Smith and Brogaard include “unification” in their taxonomy of varieties of substance formation. But as they point out, this type of substance formation is most typical of artifacts. But again, the essential point concerning the formation of entities through unification is this: to the extent that the unification is not entirely accidental, and hence does not result in a real substance, unification, like integration, seems to require the presence of a prior substance doing the unifying. Unification would appear to be the only candidate for the way in which the human being is formed on Smith and Broaard’s view, but it seems in itself the least likely, given the only other analogues of substance formation by unification.20 The third option avoids such difficulties, but at great cost. Ronald Green, in his attack on the humanity of the early embryo, writes that “Biology does not admit of definitive events.” In consequence, he argues, “the determination of significant points within these processes inevitably involves choice and decision on our part.” 21 Green supports his first claim not merely with his discussion of twinning, but even with claims about the nature of fertilization and conception itself. When does an embryo begin to Of course, as should be clear, I don’t even think that entities such as artifacts formed by unification are ever substances. How could unification ever result in a nature? 21 Ronald Green, The Human Embryo Research Debates (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001). 20 exist? Green suggests a number of possibilities, some of which are quite implausible: the mere fact that the sperm has entered the egg seems radically insufficient for us to say that there is a new individual entity. More plausible would be some point after syngamy in which 23 chromosomes from the egg and 23 chromosomes from the sperm line up at the new cell’s center. Somewhere around this stage, it would appear to be the case that there are no longer a variety of processes initiated by sperm and egg being carried out, but that a new entity exists, which is developing itself according to a single pattern. Conceptually, the changes that sperm and egg undergo to become a substance are not baffling in the way the changes just canvassed would be. Sperm and egg are each parts of a substance – not potential parts like a heart in a dish. So there is a substance – in fact, two substances – ontologically and causally prior to the new, third, substance, which comes about when the two parts perform their appropriate functions. Those functions can be understood as controlled biologically by the substances of which they are parts in a way that the thousands of adhering cells’ functions cannot be understood as controlled by the mother within which they exist. In fertilization, two substances, a human man and a human woman, act together to create a third substance. On the two models described earlier, non-substances spontaneously become substances. This does not appear to be ontologically coherent. It is true that it is difficult to establish a precise moment when the new individual substance exists, amid the welter of changes that take place during fertilization. But epistemic difficulties about the moment of death, for example, or the moment of individuation do not call into question the ontological claim that, pace Green, nature does admit of definitive events. If there is such a thing as a single substance, then there is of necessity a moment at which it exists, and a moment prior to that at which it didn’t a moment in which everything that was happening was a result of the play of independent biological forces. If Green’s claim is taken seriously, then there are no human beings, any more than there are, on Merrick’s or van Inwagen’s views, statues or flags. The most plausible story, metaphysically and biologically, thus remains the standard biological view of the origin of the human being: it takes place at the moment when fertilization is complete. And this is the only position, I suggest, compatible with the animalism.