S. MARC COHEN PLATO'S METHOD OF DIVISION Our main difficulty with Plato's method of division is that we don,t know what is being divided or what it is being divided into. And until we know thesethings, we don't know very much about the method of division. ProfessorMoravcsikrightly focusseson thesequestionsand doesus the serviceof laying out for our examinationseveralclearmodelsof what the method may be, as well as the texts onto which thesemodelshave to be imposed.By examiningboth the internal structureof thesemodels and their compatibility with Plato's texts we should begin to achievea better understanding of themethodof division. In my commentsI will ignorewhat Moravcsikcallsthe.crude'model, and concentrateon the 'clean' and 'intensional mereology' (hereafter 'LM.') models. At the risk of proliferatingmodelsbeyondnecessity, I will also introduce,for eachof thesemodels,a variant which I think deserves seriousconsideration.In contrast to the clean model I will presentone which I think is 'cleaner'still, and asa rival to the I.M. modelI will offer a version which I hope avoids what seemto me to be difficulties in ProfessorMoravcsik'sformulation. I. WHAT GntS ntvtoeo? There are immediatelytwo possibilities:what gets divided may be an extensionalentity, or it may be an intensionalentity. Moravcsik'sclean model has a class,presumablyan extensionalentity, as what I will call the dividend(i.e.,what getsdivided); theparts,then,(i.e.,what the dividendgetsdividedinto) will alsobe extensional entities- subclasses of the dividendclass.Alternatively,what gets divided may be an intensional entity (a Form itself, rather than its extension);and the parts will also be intensionalentities.Someof the partswill be Forms,but some,it seems, will not. This createsa problemwhich I will return to later. The clean model treats the dividend as an extensionalentitv and the J. M. E. Moravcsik (ed.), patterns in plato,s Thought,IgI-191. Alt RightsReserved Copyright @ 1973 by D. Reidel publishing Company, Dordrecht-Holland t82 S. MARC COHEN part-oI relation as the subclass-ofrelation. But it is not the only possible modelwhich hasthesefeatures.The dividendclasson the cleanmodelis a predicate.But we classof Forms, i.e., the extensionof a second-order i'e', as the particulars, of a class as class divided the might, instead,treat as a classof class divided the treat extensionof first-orderpredicate.If we of the subclasses particulars, division will still involve distinguishing dividendclass,and thepart-of relationwill still be thesubclass-olrelation. And as with the cleanmodel, proper division will be division into a subclasswhich is the extensionof a Form. We divide into parts (subclasses) betweenthe modelsis accordingto Forms(kat' eidE).Theonly difference over the questionofwhat the dividendclassis a classof. II. THE SUPERCLEAN MODEL model.According I'll call this alternativeto the cleanmodelthe superclean to it, to define'sophistry'or'the sophist'is to enumerateall thoseForms Fsuch that: (i) theextensionof 'sophist'is includedin theextensionof d and (ii) the extensionof F is includedin the extensionof the originaldividendForm, in thiscase,the Form technE. (tt may be that the supercleanmodel is merelya more precisearticulation of the crude model - I don't flnd the crude model in cornford clear enoughto tell.) III. OBJECTION TO THE SUPERCLEAN MODEL Against the supercleanmodel it might be urged that Plato divides,4rr into the variousarts.not into the variousartistsor art-works.Soa part of be a classofartistsor a classofartworks,but the dividend, technE,cannot must be a classof arts. And an individualart is presumablya Form in which artists (or artworks - how can we decidewhich?) participate.So the dividend classmust be a classof Forms, rather than a very general classofparticulars. IV. REPLY But how goodis this objection? It is only asgoodasthe claimthat we are dealing,in division as practicedin the Sophist,with second-rather than PLATO'S METHOD OF DIVISION 183 fust-order predicates.But how is this established?Consider Professor Moravcsik'sargument: Mr, X might be a sophist; but what we are accountingfor is not Mr. X and his cohorts, but the art of sophistry, of which they partake.... [Wel name properties of the art of sophistry, and not properties of individuals. E.g., sophistry is an acquisitive art - according to some of the divisions - but Mr. X is clearly not; he partakesof an art which in turn is acquisitive.Neither predication, nor Plato's participation relation are transitive, starting with particulars. I do not find this argumentconvincing.ProfessorMoravcsik thinks that Mr. X cannotparticipatein the Form Acquisitivelrtr because he is a man and not an art. But how then can Mr. X participatein the Form Sophistry? For surelyMr. X is not a sophistry.(If it is objectedthat the Form Mr. X partakesof is Sophist,not Sophistry,the reply is that ^Soprrst is not if participate an art either one thinks it is, then Mr. X cannot in it.) Of course,we do want to allow that Mr. X participatesin the form Sophistry, and in virtue of this participationhe is a practitionerof that art, i.e., a sophist.If Sophistryis an acquisitiveart, then Mr. X participatesin the Form (if therebeone)Acquisitive Art,and in virtue of this participationis practitioner a of that kind of art, i.e., an acquisitiveartist.('Acquisitive artist', like 'good cobbler',doesnot, in general,admit of simpliflcation.) In short, I seeno reasonwhy we cannot treat all the predicatesalike, presumablyas first-order predicates.If Mr. X can partake of Sophistry and be therebynothingmore than a sophist,then he can partakeof Art withoutbeingtherebyanythingmoreexaltedthanan artist. V. FURTHER COMMENTS ON THE SUPERCLEAN MODEL In favor of the supercleanmodel is the fact that in it, unlike the clean model, there is no confusionbetweenclassmembershipand classinclusion.Recallthat on the cleanmodel,eachdivisionyieldsa subclass of the dividendclass,until we reachthe final division,which yieldsa member of the dividendclass.(AcquisitiveArt is a classof arts; Sophistryis not a classof arts, but an art.). So 'part', on the cleanmodel, has to cover both the notion of class-inclusion and the notion of class-membership. But on the supercleanmodel, parts are alwayssubclasses. The extension of Art (: the classof artists)is divided into subclasses, one of which would be, e.g.,the extensionof AcquisitiveArt (:the classof acquisitive 184 S. MARC COHEN artists),and finally into the extensionof Sophisty (:1hg classof sophists). Further division is possible,of course,for there are kinds of sophistry, too, but noneis wanted,sinceit wasSophistrythat wasto be defined. Of course,the other threeof Moravcsik'sobjectionsto the cleanmodel also militate againstthe supercleanmodel. But there may be plausible rejoindersto theseobjections.For example,we may saythat when Plato talks of dividing or cutting a Form he iust meansdividing its extension into subclassesaccording to Forms of which those subclassesare the Ifdividing a form This bringsup an interestingconsideration. extensions. it would seemto follow ,,4is just dividing its extensioninto subclasses, that if two Forms are extensionallyequivalent,to divide the one is to dividethe other. It seemsto me terribly difficult to decidejust which way this consideration cuts.Onewould havethought that whenPlato wasdividing the Form Dffirence into parts,he wasnot alsodividingthe restof the megistagen? into parts. And if he was not, the supercleanmodel must be abandoned. On the otherhand,thereis an argumentat Soph.257D-Ewhich seemsto of division.Thereit is argued,in requirejust this thesisof extensionality effect,that sinceNot-Bequtifulis a part of Dffirence, it is thereforea part of Being. Now Dffirence and Being are extensionallyequivalent but intensionallydistinct.So the only way the conclusionwill follow is if we assumethat a part of Dffirence is just a subclassof the extensionof Dffirence. For given this, a part of Diference will also be a subclassof the extensionof Being,and hencea part ofBeing. I hope I havegiven sufficientreasonfor treating the supercleanmodel as a seriouscandidate.To pushit throughall the way one would haveto hold, I think, that Plato useseidosin a systematicallyambiguousway, sometimesmeaningForm, sometimesmeaningextensionof a Form. (Better: eidos sometimeshas an intensional sense,and sometimesan extensionalsense.)This may be supportedon the groundsthat Plato is ambiguousin just this way in usingthe namesof individualForms; the ambiguityin the nameof eacheidosmayperhapshavecarriedover to the technicalterm e#ositself. VI. CRITICISM OF THE I.M. MODEL Ratherthan pursuethe supercleanmodel any further, I want now to turn PLATO'S METHOD OF DIVISION 185 my attention to the I.M. model. In this model, extensionsare abandoned altogether.A Form is an intensionalentity which may havetwo sorts of parts: what Moravcsik callsparts' and,ports". A part' is alwaysa Form, but a part" neednot be. Now the successof this model requires,at least, the adequacyof the deflnitions of the two sorts of part, for they form the backboneof the model. Unfortunately, I find neither of the definitions adequate.I will first considerthe notion ofparts". When he confronts his favored model with the difficult eidoslmeros distinction in Pol. 263A-8, Moravcsik saysthat the questionof whether eachmeros(of somegenos)is an eidoscan be representedin the model in this way: is eachpart" of a Form A alsoan eidos?But curiously,he does this without everhavingdef,ned' x is a part" of A' in settingup the model. So how are we to understandthe question? What hasbeendeflnedis the conjunction'Xis a part" of A and x is an eidosof A', and this hasbeen deflnedto mean'x is a kind of z4'.But to dealwith 263A-8, we mustalso makesenseof 'x is a part" of ,4 and x is not an eidosof ,4'. But what sense are we to makeof this? X, in sucha case,must be in everyway like a kind of I exceptfor not beinga kind. At onepoint (p. 175)Moravcsikseemsto give 'collectionof parts' of I' as a glosson 'part" of ,4'. But what is a - a collectionof parts'is, collectionof parts'?This smacksof extensionality perhaps,a set or classof parts'. But then a meroswhich is not an eidos will turn out to be a classof Forms which haveno specificunity. If so, a meroswhichis an eidosturns out to be a classof Forms which do havea specificunity - presumably,a classof Forms suchthat thereis someForm that they, and only they, partakeof. And if sucha merosreally r'san eidos (as opposedto merelyhavingan eidos),then an eidos,as well as a meros, turnsout to be a classof Forms. But now the I.M. modelhascomedangerously closeto collapsinginto the cleanmodel.For on the cleanmodel,a meroswastreatedas a class, and the I.M. modelwas supposedto be ableto avoid this. Further,the LM. modelnot only treatsmerosas ambiguous,it also seemsto haveto treat eidos as ambiguous: sometimeseidos means Form, sometimesit meansclassof Forms.At this point I feelsomeinclination to go back to the supercleanmodel, which need take only eidos ambiguously,and ambiguouslyin a different,and what seemsto me to be a more plausible,way (sometimesmeaningForm, sometimesextensionof a Form). t86 S. MARC COHEN Not only doesthe I.M. model containno definition of part" ; it contains what seemsto be an inadequatedefinition of part'. The definition' you will recall,is this: x is a part' of A: x has,4 asa propertyand x is itselfa Form and ,4 doesnot havex as a property. Note that the third conjunct is requiredif thepart' o/ relation is to be asymmetricaland irreflexive;for otherwise,self-predicativeForms would be parts' of themselves,and the megistagenE,e.g.,would be parts' of one another.But the trouble is that the definition doesnot rule out quite enough.As it stands,the definition will allow genericForms to have quite unexpectedand unwantedparts'. The intent of the definition, Moravcsik makesclear, is for a part' of a genericForm to be a specificsub-Form of that Form. Thus, "an art is a part' of the Form Art; and... the parts' of Scienceare the various (p. 175).Soin the caseof themegistagenE,onewould expectthe scienceso' parts of, e.g,,Dffirence to be the variousForms of difference(i.e', the Forms specifyingthe variouswaysof beingdifferent).z But Moravcsik's definition will allow any Form which sharesnonreciprocallyin Diference to be a part' of Dffirence. Thus, the Even,fot example,is a Form which hasthe property of difference(sinceeverything does)and Dffirence does not have the property of being even.So Even would have to be allowed as a part' of Difference.Indeed, every Form that Dffirence doesnot sharein would count,accordingto the proposed definition, as a part' of Difference.Similarly, the Large would haveto be thought of as a part' of Res/.But nowheredoesPlato give any indication that he thought of such Forms as standingin thepart o/ relation, in any senseof 'part'. The trouble,of course,is that whilethe partsof / may be Forms which have ,4 (non-reciprocally)as a property, this is only incidentalto their beingpartsof,4. as Thesedefectsin the I.M. modelseemto me to makeit unacceptable it stands.But if the letter is wrong, the spirit may still be right; in what followsI will try to developanothermodel,similarto the I.M. model,but freeof the defectsof the latter. VII. A NEW I.M. MODEL The following assumptionsand stipulationswill be operativein the model howeverthis is to (l) We assumethat therearc intensions, to be sketched. predicates.)(2) of the senses (Perhaps be insentions will be understood. PLATO'S METHOD OF DIVISION 187 Someintensionsare Forms, and someare not. (Thus, while there will be an intension for every predicate,there will not be a Form for every predicate.)(3) A part (meros)of an intension is itself an intension. (4) GenEand eidEare both Forms (cf. Soph.222D,227D,2288). (5) Each eidosof a genosis a part (meros)of that genost but not everymerosof a genosis an eidosof that genos(cf. Pol. 2638).(6) Thepart o/ relation will be definedin termsof entailment. VIII. (l) (2) (3) (4) (5) (6) (7) MACHINERY OF THE NEW I.M. MODEL Let'A','B', etc.,bepredicate variables. I is theintensionof A, etc. E (A) is theextensionof A. (E(A):iAy) The arrowwill represent entailmentbetweenintensions; A--+B iff n (x) (Ax>Bx) l i s a p a r t o f B : a r A - - + B& - ( B - - + A ) Note that while ,4-+ ^BentailsE (A) c E (B), the conversedoes not hold. lisan eidosofBiff (a) ,4 is a part of .8,and (b) lisaForm. (How we decidewhen 7(b) is true posesa problemwhich I shalldiscuss in SectionXI below.) IX. DIVISION AND COLLECTION ON THE NEW I.M. MODEL The method aims at giving the /ogosof some eidos,i.e., some abstract singular description of the eidosin terms of the parts of some suitably broad genos.The method requiresthe following procedures: (l) (2) (3) (4) Selection:An original dividend genosis selectedwhich has the eidos to be explicated as a part. Division: Two or more parts of a genosare ascertained. Collection: Two or more parts of a genos are examined to see whether they are parts of some eidos of that genos. Location:, The eidos to be explicated is found to be a part of 188 S.MARC COHEN one (or more) of the parts reachedby previousstepsof division or collection. Closure:The eidosto be explicatedis found to be an imme' 'immediate part of a part reachedby a previousstep,where diatepart of is definedasfollows: A is animmediatepart of .B: asA is a part of B and thereis no C suchthat: A is a part of C and C is a part of ,8. (5) The methodof divisiondoesnot, of course,constitutea decisionprocedure for givinglogoi sinceit providesno rulesfor carryingout the stepsof selecting,dividing, locating,etc. Selection,division, etc., must be untuitive. Schematically,the methodproceedsasfollows: (l) (2) (3) (4) Suppose S is to be defined, and ,4 is the selectedgenos. ,4 is divided into parts 8r... Bn. S is located in one (or more) of 81,... Bo. Select one of the B's in which S is located and determine whether it is a Form. (a) Ifit is, divide it. (b) If it is not, collect it along with other parts of ,4 to see whether aC canbe found such that: (i) C is a part of A (ii) Cis a Form (iii) All the collected parts of ,4 are parts of C; If such a C can be found, divide it. Otherwise,the (non-Form) ,Bin which (s) (6) S has been located can be divided. Step (4) yields a set of parts. Repeated applications of location, division, and (where necessary)collection will yield a part R of which Sis an immediate part. At this point a closure of the division has been achieved. Tracing back through the steps of the division from S to ,'4 will yield an entailment chain (i.e., a set of intensi ons {A, B, . .. R, S) such that S--+R, R --+Q,..., B'-+ A.). An enumeration of all the intensions (save S) in the chain yields a logos of S. X. CONSIDERATIONS IN FAVOR OF THE NEW I.M. MODEL ( l ) It makes senseof the notion that Forms are divided into parts. PLATO'S METHOD OF DIVISION 189 Man is a part of Animal becausebeing a man entailsbeing an animal. (2) It provides an eidoslmerosdistinction while allowing that some merEcanbe eidE.Man is a part of Animal andis an eidosof Animal since Man is a Form: Barbarianis a part of Man (being a barbarian entails beinga man)but not an eidosof Man, sinceBarbarianis not a Form. (3) It allows division into non-eidorparts (e.g.,usingshort arguments) eventhough division into eidAis preferable(cf. pol.262E). (4) It treats the part o/ relation as irreflexive and asymmetricwhile avoiding the difficultiesin the part' of relation pointed out above.Thus, Large is not a part of Re.rtsincebeing large doesnot entail being at rest (eventhough,ofcourse,Largehasthe propertyofbeing at rest).On the other hand, Not-Beautiful (whether or not it is a Form) is a part of Difference,sincenot being beautiful entails being different. (Cf. Plato's analysisof'not beautiful' as 'differentfrom the nature of the Beautiful' Soph.257D.) (5) It allowsfor the multiplicity of correctcharacteizationsby division. Characterizationby division consists of giving an entailment chain linking the Form to be characterized genos.It is clear with the selected that therecan be more than one correctentailment-chain, sincethe parts producedby divisionneednot be exclusive or exhaustive. XI. SOME RESERVATIONS AND LIMITATIONS (1) Thebasicnotionsof the New I.M. modelcanbe expressed in termsof set-theoryand modal logic. Or, at least,a modelisomorphicto the New I.M. modelcan be producedusingonly the notionsof classinclusionand necessity. Thus,the New I.M. modelmay be very closeto the superclean model,little more than notationally different.(But in my heart I favor the superclean modelanyway,soI'm not surethis is a disadvantage.) (2) The model givesus no help with the questionof which intensions are Forms, but assumeswe have someindependentway of determining this. But perhapsit would be requiringtoo muchof the modelto suppose it could providean answerto this question.(The questionis still an interestingone.Pol.262 suggests that the intensionof a predicateis a Form only if the membersof the extensionof that predicatehave somethingin common other than just the predicate.But this is not much help, since barbarianshavenot beingGreekin common.We might try to definethe 190 S.MARC COHEN intension'and saythattheintensionof a predicate notionof'non-negative is a Form only if the members of the extension of that predicate intensionin common.Thus, nol beingGreekis a have somenon-negdtive negativeintension,so the fact that barbarianshaveit in commonwill not makeBarbarianaForm. But now therecanbe no syntactictestfor whether an intensionis non-negative,sinceBarbarianis a negativeintensionbut is not explicitly negative.Nor will it help to say that Barbatianis negative sinceBarbarian:non-Greek,fotby the sametoken Greekwouldbe negative sinceGreek- non-Barbarian. Alternatively,we might saythat Socratesis an animal by virtueof being a man, whereasit is not the casethat Socratesis an animalby virtue of being a non-reptile. This suggeststhe following schemafor isolating intensionswhichareForms: ,4 is a Form itr(B)(x)(,a is a part of B & xe E(A)= Bx by virtue of the fact that Ax). 'Bx by virtue of the fact Unfortunately, giving the truth conditions for 'r4 is a Form'. And if the that Ax' seemsno easierthan giving thosefor Plato habitually uses, one intensionalnotion by virtue o/ usedhereis the 'by virtue then the procedureof applyingthis schemawill be circular. For 'by virtue of x's partiof the fact that Ax' will haveto be understoodas cipatingin A" andthis will be true only if ,4 is a Form. So it seemsthat in is an animalby virtueof beinga manwe have orderto know that Socrates alreadyto know that Mdn is a Form.) But the fact that the New I.M. model doesn'ttell us which intensions are Forms leavesit no worse off than any of its rivals, for analogous problems will crop up with them. Thus, on the supercleanmodel we know that a meroswhich is an eidosis the extensionof a Form, and a meroswhichis not an eidosisa subclassof the extensionof a Form but not itselfthe extensionof a Form. But what a Form is the modeldoesn't tell us. (3) MV final worry about the New I'M. model,indeedabout all intensionalmodels,is that they do not meshvery nicelywith an intuitive understandingof thepart o/ relation. one would have thought that while the classof menis a part of the classof animals,the intensionAnimalis part of the intensionMan, and not the otherway around.For'animal' is part 'man', while 'man' is not part of the definitionof of the definition of PLATO'S METHOD OF DIVISION 191 'animal'. If we want a model which makesgoodliteral senseof thepart of relation, we may have to go back to a model which givesus classesto divide and is henceat leastpartly extensional.Here the cleanand supercleanmodelsrecommendthemselves;of the two, I preferthe latter. University of Washington NOTES r I will adopt the practice of writing the names of Forms in italics, capitalizing the initial letters. 2 At Soph,257C-258C, the Stranger offers the Not-Beautiful and,the Not-Tall as €xamples of the parts of Dffirmce. If theseare Forms (which is controversial) they might be thought of as Forms which specifyways of being different (e.g.,being 'different from the nature of the Beautiful' (257D) is a way of being different). In this case, these 'negative' Forms would be parts'(in the intended sense)of Dffirence.