1 An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy Thomas Christiano Despite its increasing importance in contemporary political philosophy and its central role in the international law of human rights there has been significant resistance among political theorists and philosophers to the idea that there is a human right to democracy. In John Rawls’s late political philosophy of international justice and in the views of many who are sympathetic to these positions, the idea that there is a human right to democracy is vigorously rejected.i Other major recent treatments of human rights have either rejected the human right to democracyii or shied away from making arguments one way or the other.iii The key concerns behind many of these arguments revolve around the idea of collective self-determination of peoples either as a kind intrinsic right of peoples or as a kind of instrumental right. It is often argued that the existence of a human right to democracy in the international system would somehow impinge on or violate the collective right of a people to self-determination. It is claimed that some peoples reject democracy or the equality on which it is founded so that the recognition of a human right to democracy would impose upon them a set of norms that are alien to their political cultures. There has also been a popular spate of writings suggesting that new democracies often violate basic rights of citizens. This majority tyranny worry suggests a strong conflict between democracy and other basic rights. I argue that there are good grounds for thinking that there is a human right to democracy once we have a grasp of at least some sufficient conditions for human rights and once we understand the idea of democracy as something more than mere majority An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy T. Christiano 2 rule but not necessarily as much as full liberal democracy. And I argue that we can see how the above worries can be dispelled once we have a proper appreciation of these grounds. The argument I give here is a fully instrumental argument relying heavily on empirical studies of the relationship between democracy as I understand it and the protection of certain very urgent and widely accepted human rights. The right to democracy, if we are thinking in terms of this argument alone, derives from its central role in the protection of other fundamental rights.iv I think that there is also an argument for the human right to democracy that makes democratic rights fundamental but it must proceed from more controversial premises.v I believe it is worthwhile making out a separate strong instrumental right to democracy to the extent that democracy is essential to the protection of very urgent and widely accepted human rights. In what follows I will define a set of sufficient conditions for the kind of human right I will be talking about, I do not commit myself to necessary conditions since there may be a number of different kinds of human rights. I will also explain the conception of democracy I am working with and the idea of a human right to democracy. I will give a three step argument for the thesis that there is a human right to democracy: the domestic peace argument, the international significance argument and a structural argument. Along the way I will be exploring the relation between this assertion of a human right to democracy and the idea of collective self-determination. I will close with a fuller discussion of the self-determination objection to the idea that there is a human right to democracy. What Is the Human Right to Democracy? An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy T. Christiano 3 In this paper, I will not attempt a general account of the nature or grounds of human rights. In particular I will not attempt to lay out a set of necessary and sufficient conditions for the definition of a human right. Instead I will rely on a set of sufficient conditions, which I believe are particularly salient for my argument. I argue that a sufficient formal condition for a right being a human right is that there is strong moral justification for any state to respect, protect and promote the right and there is moral justification for the creation and/or maintenance of international institutions that respect and protect the right in all persons and that will assist in the securing of the object of the right for all persons. These sufficient formal conditions include the ideas of international institutions, rights and moral justification. It is sufficient for there being a human right to x that there is a strong moral justification for states securing the right to x and there is moral justification for having an international institution or convention or perhaps even a less formal but effective mode of organization that is international that secures the right at issue. In this sense, some human rights are artificial rights because they consist in aspects or parts of morally justified institutions. That is, they depend on the possibility of an efficacious institution. But they are universal both in terms of the possessors of these rights and in some respects in terms of the duty holders. To the extent that there is universal and strong moral justification for states to secure the right and there is moral justification for an international institution to attempt to get states to do this, all states and all persons have some share in the duties to bring about and or maintain and comply with the institution. To be clear, this account does not require the existence of states or international institutions recognizing the right in question, it requires only that the An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy T. Christiano 4 creation of these institutions is strongly morally justified. So in the absence of an international institution or even of a functioning state, one may still say that the human right exists since one is saying that the construction of these institutions is morally justified. And I think one may even say that the right is violated or infringed by those who block the construction of these institutions. Some have argued that human rights are essentially connected to the responsibilities of political institutions either states or international institutions. On these views a person’s human right to life is not violated by a murder for which we do not hold the state or state-like institutions responsible. But it is violated when the state does it or condones it or seriously fails in its responsibility to protect persons from it.vi And there is no human right unless international institutions are morally justified in being concerned with them.vii I will not claim that these are necessary conditions for human rights in order to avoid needless controversy. By an institution having a strong moral justification I mean that there are particularly urgent moral goods at stake and the institution is an essential arrangement for protecting those urgent moral goods.viii An institution has a moral justification when it is desirable that it be constructed in order to protect morally urgent goods. I will not settle here for a particular account of the basis of moral justification that holds for international human rights. I will not rule out the possibility that some human rights are morally justified by virtue of protecting natural rights. Some human rights may be grounded in the requirements of a minimally decent human life, others may be grounded in facts about what kinds of institutions best protect human interests. My inclination is to take a pluralistic approach to the grounds of human rights. ix An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy T. Christiano 5 What I do want to say is that at least some of what we call human rights are rights of persons, universal in scope, as specified by strongly morally justified institution and morally justified international political institutions that have the responsibilities to protect and promote fundamental human interests, other morally urgent concerns among persons or other human rights. They are well-grounded international standards for defining the basic rights of persons in political societies. These are the universal rights of persons that international institutions must try to protect. So not only do we need morally justified institutions, it must be the case that the institutions specify rights that are to be protected. There may be morally justified international institutions that help avoid interstate wars or even civil wars but this does not imply that there is a human right to avoidance of war. The international institutions must specify the right in a plausible way. If an international institution protects some good such as environmental protection through various limitations on producers of pollutants, this is not sufficient for a human right. The institution that is strongly morally justified must specify a right. The human right to democracy that I will argue for is of this type. The idea is that there is a strong moral justification for states being minimally egalitarian democracies. And there is moral justification for having international institutions that respect, protect and promote the right of each person to participate in minimally egalitarian democratic decision-making concerning their society. By “minimally egalitarian democracy” I mean a democracy that has a formal or informal constitutional structure that ensures that persons have formally equal votes, equal opportunities to run for office, and equal opportunities to determine the agenda of decision-making. In such a society there must be robust competition among parties so that a variety of parties have a significant An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy T. Christiano 6 presence in the legislature. And there must be a high level of participation of the populace in the electoral process. To have a human right to democracy is to have a right to participate as an equal in such a society. Such a society need not be fully just by any means nor need it live up fully to the ideals of democracy. For that reason I call it minimally egalitarian. Such a society need not be fully liberal either since it may restrict non political activities and violate liberal rights that are not connected to the democratic process. But this society is not merely majoritarian with universal suffrage. Minorities must have some protection and a significant place in the legislature and there must be free and fair competition for power among a variety of groups that compete on an equal footing. To have a human right to democracy then is for it to be strongly morally justified that the state of which one is a member be organized as a minimally egalitarian democracy in which one has an equal right. And it requires that international institutions be so organized as to respect, promote and assist in the development of minimally egalitarian democracies. Through these international institutions all human beings share in duties to assist in the creation, maintenance and enhancement of democratic collective decision making in the political institutions of all persons. This conception of some human rights as strongly morally justified institutions first at the state level and then morally justified at the international level is supported by the facts of the international practice of human rights we observe. Many if not most of the human rights we observe in the international practice have roughly this structure. They impose upon states the duties to realize certain fundamental moral goods by protecting various rights and they impose on the international community the duties to An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy T. Christiano 7 help states do this. x If we can successfully make an argument to the effect that there is strong moral justification for states to be minimally democratic and that international institutions are morally justified in promoting and protecting democracy then we have an argument for a human right to democracy that fits within the mainstream concept of human rights. The Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy The main instrumental argument for a human right to democracy comes in three parts. I employ a set of two empirical arguments for the thesis that there is a human right to democracy. The first part of the argument is the domestic peace argument. The domestic peace argument says that democracy is a normally reliable method by which the least controversial of human rights are protected and non-democratic societies are normally unreliable in this respect. The second empirical part of the argument is the international significance argument. It argues that international institutions have good moral reasons to be concerned with whether a society is democratic or not. It depends on a conception of the international system and of the capacities of democracies that is empirically based but controversial. The two arguments together support the thesis that there is strong moral justification for states to be democratic in the minimally egalitarian sense and that there is moral justification for international institutions and other states to respect, protect and assist in the creation of minimally democratic societies. The third part of the argument goes beyond the claim that democracy is a reliable means for protecting human rights. It must specify a plausible right. I draw an analogy with another human right that is largely instrumentally based and that is the right to a fair An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy T. Christiano 8 trial. What is important about the right to a fair trial is that fair trials are imperfect but reliable methods of assessing the guilt and innocence of persons. But the right to a fair trial gives persons rights to defend their rights against those who would curtail them. Not only do fair trials protect rights, they do so by giving persons opportunities and choices by means of which they can defend their rights. It is not just that others have a duty to help the purported right holder, they have duties to give the purported right holder opportunities and choices, with which they may defend themselves. And this marks out the right to a fair trial as a genuine right. And I want to say that something very similar can be asserted of democracy. After the elaboration of the basic three part argument, I will provide a fourth supporting set of empirical arguments that purport to show that democracy is not bad for other basic rights that individuals hold. Thus the argument for the right to democracy is not defeated by any highly problematic effects democracy might have for other rights. The Domestic Peace Argument The domestic peace argument is based on a number of studies of the impact of democracy on human rights. They give strong evidence for the thesis that minimally egalitarian democracies reliably protect personal or physical integrity rights and societies that are not minimally democratic do not reliably protect these especially urgent rights. And they argue that democracy is an important cause of this protection. The domestic peace argument has four main elements: (1) a very strong correlation between minimally egalitarian democracy and the protection of personal integrity rights and the normal failure of non-democracies to protect these rights; (2) the identification of democracy as a An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy T. Christiano 9 key independent variable in explaining the protection of personal integrity rights; (3) a sequencing argument showing that newly minted minimally egalitarian democracies achieve their protection of personal integrity rights fully only after a period of about five years after they come into existence; and (4) a model that explains how minimally egalitarian democracies protect human rights and non-democracies do not. These four elements, I believe, give us good reason for thinking that minimally egalitarian democracy has the effect of protecting human rights and other societies do not. Rights of personal integrity are rights not to be murdered or disappeared by the state, state sponsored agents or state-like agents, rights not to be imprisoned for political reasons or tortured by the state, state sponsored agents or state-like agents. They are all rights held against the state primarily. Personal integrity rights are given a special urgency in the international system and are uncontroversial in international society. They receive special protection in the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights. These rights are described as non-derogable rights in the covenant, which means they may not be suspended even in times of severe crisis.xi And some of these rights have the status of jus cogens norms in international law, norms so fundamental that no state can agree to contravene them.xii Furthermore, these rights are universally accepted among philosophers as among the minimal list of human rights. Hence, the first empirical argument establishes that minimally egalitarian democracies are strongly morally justified state institutions by virtue of the fact that they reliably protect rights of the greatest urgency while societies that fall short of this standard do not. Here are the four elements of the argument. (1) A number of scholars have attempted large-scale statistical studies of the best predictors of the protection of the An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy T. Christiano 10 rights to physical or personal integrity, which are the least controversial of all the human rights. Steven Poe et al. have argued from probably the largest of such studies that democracy is among the most important predictors of the protection of the human right to personal integrity behind a previous history of protection or violation of personal integrity and civil conflict. The studies have argued that there is a general linear and negative relationship between democracy and state violence.xiii What this means is that the more democracy there is, the less repression of the human rights to personal integrity there is. This conception of greater and lesser democracy is operationalized in two data sets. The first is the Polity IV dataset and country reports. These datasets attempt to define a continuum of democratic institutions in particular years from 0 to 10 wherein the United States and most western European countries come out to be 10 and Russia and Ukraine in 2006 turn out to be about 7 each along with El Salvador and Columbia.xiv The second is the Vanhanen Index of Democratization, which measures the proportion of the population that participates in elections and the proportion of votes received by all minority parties.xv In both of these sets, democracy is treated as a continuous variable on a scale from quite weak democracies to very strong ones. And the violations of personal integrity rights are measured for each country every year in what is called the Political Terror Scale. The political terror scale is a kind of aggregate measure of the violations of the different rights of personal integrity described above. The data on which the terror scale is constructed come from Amnesty International’s yearly country reports and the US State Department’s yearly reports. The numerical measures are constructed from these reports.xvi These datasets and the criteria they use deserve greater study and analysis An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy T. Christiano 11 than philosophers and political theorists have so far given them.xvii One major result of this research is that there is a strong inverse relationship between democracy and state violence such that the more democracy one has the less state violence there is. The other kind of result is that in multiple regression analyses, democracy emerges as a very important independent variable explaining the reduction in state violence. More recent studies have suggested that the picture is more complex and much more interesting than this. In these studies of the relation between democracy and repression of the human rights to personal integrity, it has been argued that the relationship between democracy and human rights violations exhibits an important discontinuity that has not shown up in previous studies. The idea is that only once democracy has reached a certain threshold of quality on the scale does the linear negative relationship between democracy and violations of personal integrity rights emerge and then it emerges as a very steep inverse relationship. Roughly speaking, the basic threshold seems to be (i) the constitutional order meets a minimal threshold of electoral accountability of the legislature to the population and the executive is accountable to the electorate. (ii) Electoral processes are competitive in the sense that more than one party contests elections and has a significant presence in the legislature and these contests are free and fair in the sense that special obstacles are not put in the way of any of the individuals or parties in the electoral process and (iii) there is a fairly high level of participation in the populace in elections.xviii These criteria are a combination of the Polity IV criteria and the Vanhanen index. They match the threshold at which minimally egalitarian democracy appears. The level roughly at which a serious linear and negative relationship between democracy and human rights violations appears is at the Polity IV An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy T. Christiano 12 level of 7, which Russia and the Ukraine satisfied in 2006. Up to that point the relationship is roughly that of a flat line, which suggests that differences in regime do not make much difference to levels of violation of human rights to personal integrity. After that point a steep downward sloping curve expresses a very strong inverse relationship between the increasing quality of democracy and numbers of violations of human rights to personal integrity. (See figure 1 p. 547 and table 1 p. 548 in Davenport and Armstrong) The very same threshold effect is evident in using the Vanhanen index as in the use of Polity IV index. (2) In multivariate analyses, minimally egalitarian democracy turns out to be a very strong independent variable explaining the protection of human rights to personal integrity. It is important to remember that there are some other factors associated with a negative relationship with state violations of human rights. Population size has a small effect on level of violations of personal integrity rights. Other factors often discussed are a highly active international civil society movement in relation to the state involved, war (civil and interstate) and per capita GDP. International nongovernmental organizations (INGO’s) are thought to be effective against human rights violations.xix This is an important result, but it must be remembered that the influence of these INGO’s is generally through the domestic institutions of the societies and thus most often through democratic regimes. Per capita GDP has also been associated with lessening of human rights violations. But it seems to play a significantly smaller role than minimally egalitarian democracy from the multiple regression analyses.xx Furthermore, one thing that is important to note is that democracies tend to have a strong positive association with per An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy T. Christiano 13 capita economic growth. Here the research by Adam Przeworski and colleagues has argued quite convincingly that democracies tend to outperform dictatorships in terms of per capita growth by a very significant margin and this result holds when controlling for many different variables.xxi Przeworski et al’s argument is different from the human rights arguments above in that the Przeworski argument relies on a dichotomous separation between democracy and dictatorship while the others are not dichotomous. The one similarity is that the threshold point in which democracies start to do much better than any other form of rule is not very far from the threshold point dividing democracies from dictatorships in the Przeworski argument. Another important independent variable explaining human rights violations is war both interstate and civil war as well as violent resistance to the state. But interstate war appears not to have as large an impact as minimally egalitarian democracy on the violation of personal integrity rights. Civil war seems to be the most important factor of all in explaining human rights violations, even greater than minimally egalitarian democracy. But, while states tend to increase repressive activity and violations of personal integrity rights under these conditions, democratic societies tend to do so much less than other kinds of states. So even under the harshest of adverse circumstances, democracies have a significant effect in reducing state violations of personal integrity rights.xxii But the most important point is that when one controls for all of these different variables in multiple regression analyses, minimally egalitarian democracy emerges as the most important variable after previous repression and civil war. Furthermore, (3) there is a clear and measurable effect over time of the effect of introducing minimally egalitarian democracy in a society on the level of violations of An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy T. Christiano 14 personal integrity rights in that society. Violations of personal integrity rights taper off quite significantly within about 5 years of the introduction of high quality democracy. xxiii And violations of personal integrity rights increase quite dramatically within five years of a loss of high quality democracy. This sequencing argument adds some weight to the argument that minimally egalitarian democracy is a significant cause of the decrease in violations of human rights to personal integrity. It suggests that it is democracy that is bringing about the protection of these rights and not vice versa. The conclusion of the above arguments is that democracy (once it reaches the level of minimally egalitarian democracy) is a really good bet for the protection of the human rights to personal integrity, in contrast to other forms of government. To be sure, it is not a strictly necessary condition nor is it a strictly sufficient condition. But it is certainly, among different forms of government, the one that is strongly associated with the protection of human rights to personal integrity. In what follows I want to pause briefly to discuss some difficulties with this argument and then I want to discuss an interpretation of the evidence. Some Worries about the Statistical Arguments As with any statistical argument, it could turn out that there is another more important independent variable that explains the importance of democracy in a way that undermines the causal importance of democracy. For instance this possible variable may explain the presence of both democracy and low state repression and may suggest that democracy plays no causal role. Not every possible variable has been considered and some potentially explanatory variables are very hard to get a grip on. So the arguments An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy T. Christiano 15 presented above must necessarily be considered tentative. But no such variable has turned up as yet and so I think we may say that we have evidence for the causal impact of democracy on human rights protection. Another more immediate worry is that what is measured by the Political Terror Scale may overlap too much with what is measured by the Polity IV measures. For instance, the PTS counts political imprisonment as a violation of personal or physical integrity. But surely many and perhaps most instances of political imprisonment would also qualify as violations of freedom of speech or freedom of association. They would probably count as undermining the freedom and fairness of the elections (not all since some opponents of a regime may not be interested in competing in elections). And of course many instances of torture, killings and disappearances by the state could qualify as undermining free and fair elections. So we have a danger here of triviality if the two data sets do not use sufficiently distinct criteria. If the overlap of these elements is too great then the whole argument is undermined.xxiv This needs to be carefully examined. Caution is clearly in order here. But there are three mitigating considerations on this worry. First, the Vanhanen Index of Democratization seems to give us roughly the same results as the Polity IV index and it does not use anything that might intersect with the personal integrity rights as criteria. It combines proportion of the adult population that participates and proportion of total votes to minority parties, to give a measure of democracy. Second, torture, extra-judicial murder and disappearance is often inflicted by states for non-political reasons as when suspected criminals are tortured in detention centers. This is the reason why the United States (which is an outlier in these arguments) scores a 3 on the Political Terror Scale while being a 10 on Polity IV. And some An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy T. Christiano 16 opponents of a regime may not be interested in competing in elections, so political imprisonment need not be against potential opponents in an election. Third, the five year lag effect that we noted above suggests that democracies that score 10 on the Polity IV score go through initial phases where they still engage in violations of physical integrity. Equal Participation There have been some efforts at figuring out what it is about high quality democracy that has this effect. There is empirical support for the thesis that a democratic political/legal system protects the human rights of persons because it gives equal rights of participation to each of those persons. All the features of minimally egalitarian democracy are important in the protection of human rights, including the kinds of constraints on executive and legislative power we associate with checks and balances. But the component that seems most important in explaining democratic protection of human rights to personal integrity is the variable of free and fair multiparty competition and not constraints on the executive.xxv The key seems to be the exercise of popular control over the legislature and executive. The threshold point above which democracies begin to protect human rights very effectively is one that picks out democracies that are egalitarian in the sense that they guarantee equality in the vote, equality in the process of party formation and equality of opportunity to run for office. And these equalities are sufficiently effective that there is very significant competition among competing groups in the society for power and influence. This strikes me as an important result that points to the importance of equality in the protection of the human rights to personal integrity. An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy T. Christiano 17 The empirical literature does not refer to equality in the process of decision making. It focuses on the importance of free and fair elections with robust multiparty competition as well as the accountability of legislative and executive offices to the population. I interpret the idea of free and fair competition among a multiplicity of political parties as a realization of equal opportunity to run for office and to influence collective decision-making. The reason for this is that the criteria of free and fair elections are that there are no obstacles set up by the political system to the competition of political parties for the votes of citizens. Some have argued that a consultative hierarchical regime that has universal suffrage but that is corporatist in structure (i.e. politically organized into functional or religious groups) and that employs highly discriminatory criteria for the holding of government offices can protect human rights to personal integrity. On John Rawls and Joshua Cohen’s account, a consultative hierarchical regime has essentially three features. One, the regime makes decisions in a way that is accountable to all the members of society. Citizens may be represented functionally or territorially or in some other way but all must be included. Two, everyone has a right to dissent from or appeal the decisions of the regime. Three, the regime is committed to giving public reasons for its decisions in terms of a widely shared common good conception of justice. One thing that is essential to this picture is that it does not require equality among citizens either in the opportunity to run for office or to influence collective decisions. An elite is responsible for running the society though it must consult with the representatives of the citizens.xxvi Defenders of inegalitarian regimes have little empirical evidence to stand on. On the scale of democracies that is employed by the Polity IV data set, the closest to a An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy T. Christiano 18 consultation hierarchy in John Rawls’s sense is what the Polity IV manual somewhat tendentiously calls an “incoherent regime.” Such a regime has some important features of democracy but combines them with features of autocratic regimes. The combination that seems to correspond to the consultation hierarchy is one in which there is universal suffrage and an only partially competitive electoral system that employs a very incompletely competitive system for recruiting executive officers and legislative representatives. The electoral system gives everyone a vote in legislative elections but it requires that popularly unaccountable elites rigorously vet candidates in terms of political, ideological or religious beliefs. So it seriously limits free and fair multiparty competition. It does allow a plurality of candidates who have genuine disagreements but within a narrow range. Executive officers are appointed by a process that only partially includes the people as a whole. The selection process is dominated by persons who are not popularly elected but hold their positions by virtue of some religious or ideological qualification.xxvii They do take themselves to be accountable to the people in the sense of having to give reasons for policies when challenged. And those reasons are given in terms of the common good and the particular priorities of the regime. But rulers are not the equals of the people they rule, though they do sometimes come under the rule of law or at least a common set of duties. They have a privileged relation to the political regime they rule.xxviii Ideologically based states like China and the Soviet Union as well as Islamic states such as Iran would seem to qualify as consultation hierarchies on this account, in terms of the structure of collective decision-making.xxix It seems very clear from the large scale statistical studies that have been made that these kinds of regimes simply do not protect human rights very well even of the most An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy T. Christiano 19 uncontroversial kind. Indeed, nearly every regime that falls short of minimally egalitarian democracy is likely to be a serious violator of human rights of the uncontroversial sort. There is no conceptual or a metaphysical impossibility here. It is possible for there to be a decent consultation hierarchy, it is just very unlikely. One suspects that when a consultative hierarchical regime does not violate human rights, it is because of some kind of anomalous luck. Oman is sometimes mentioned as a regime of this sort, though its political system is closer to an absolute monarchy. Its sultan has over the last forty years been relatively light on political repression and violence and has attempted to open up some avenues for broad participation in the society.xxx But this seems to depend on the will of the sultan. In Rawls’s terms it seems that a decent consultation hierarchy is not a stable well-ordered society.xxxi Rawls’s “decent consultation hierarchy”, a hierarchical regime with incomplete participation of the members of society that protects basic human rights, is a kind of social-political anomaly. The normal operation of a consultation hierarchy is incompatible with the protection of the basic human rights involved with decency. Partly this conviction results from the fact that we have a good model for how this works, which also seems to be borne out by the evidence. This is the last component of the argument (4). The basic model is that minimally egalitarian political institutions effectively make rulers accountable to their citizens in an egalitarian way; they constrain the rulers and give them incentives not to violate human rights as well as incentives to call out others who are rights violators. The basic assumption behind this is that people very strongly do not want to be tortured nor do they want those who are close to them to An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy T. Christiano 20 be tortured. Furthermore, most people do not want others to be tortured and some people very strongly do not want others to be tortured. And the same holds for the other rights of personal integrity. The reason why this has such an impact in an egalitarian democracy so much greater than in other societies in which there is universal suffrage is because a minimally egalitarian society in some sense maximizes the number of possible coalitions that can mobilize against human rights violations and damage the political fortunes of politicians who violate them. It also encourages competition among different groups that spurs them to make greater efforts at uncovering rights violations. The plurality and competition among different groups ensures two things in particular. One it ensures that the society over time is reasonably transparent, since everyone is making an effort to reveal problems particularly in the activities of their opponents. So the society is fairly open. Furthermore, these competing groups have the capacities to mobilize citizens in such a way as to punish politicians who violate rights egregiously. In autocracies, in contrast, to the extent that competition among opposing groups is stifled, the facts of human rights violations are much more difficult to uncover. And so the very existence of human rights violations often retains the status of hearsay. Furthermore, to the extent that rulers are independent of popular control, they cease to be accountable and the relative importance of their other goals may override their concern to protect human rights. In democracies, politicians have reason to fear losing power when they violate human rights, in autocracies the sanctions may be quite minimal. And in societies where there are severe limits to who can politically oppose the regime, the chances of forming coalitions to fight human rights violations is correspondingly diminished and so the rulers are to that extent less accountable and thus less apt to fear defeat if they violate human An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy T. Christiano 21 rights. The fact that it is the participation and competition elements of democracy that have the most effect in protecting human rights gives some support to this model.xxxii Now the four elements of the argument for the instrumental value of minimally egalitarian democracy are in place. We have seen that (1) minimally egalitarian democracies are correlated with the protection of personal integrity rights and other societies are not; (2) minimally egalitarian democracy is an important independent variable that explains protection of these rights; (3) there is evidence for the idea that normally one must first introduce minimally egalitarian democracy before protection of human rights becomes complete; and (4) we have a model for why minimally egalitarian democracy has these effects and other societies do not. Now we can see why there is a very strong moral justification for bringing about, or sustaining minimally egalitarian democracy. That justification is grounded in the protection of rights that are at the core of the human rights system and virtually universally recognized as fundamental human rights. Given the threshold effects, the independent influence when controlling for other variables, the sequencing of democracy first human rights protection later, and the model that makes sense of how democracies protect human rights better than other societies, we have good reason to think that minimally egalitarian democracy is a normally necessary condition for the protection of human rights to personal integrity. One thing should be noted before we continue. The regimes that score highest on the Polity IV measure of democracy are by no means perfectly just societies. They may be unjust in a variety of ways. They may not fully live up to democratic ideals as when the influence of money gives disproportionate power to the wealthy. They may not have An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy T. Christiano 22 ideal methods of decision making, if for example one regards proportional representation as more just than single member district representation. They will inevitably pass unjust legislation since they are characterized by a great deal of disagreement. In these respects then, these societies may be far from fully just. Their democratic credentials, though very strong on the various empirical measures of democracy, may only imply that they meet a minimum threshold of justice.xxxiii The International Significance of Democracy for Human Rights I have argued that there is strong moral justification for states to be minimally egalitarian democracies that is grounded in the fact that democracies are normally necessary for the protection of the human rights of personal integrity. In this section I will defend the second step in the instrumental argument for a human right to democracy. I will argue that there is moral justification for the international community as a whole to attempt to respect, protect and promote the existence of minimally egalitarian democracies. The first main premise of this argument is grounded in the idea that the international system works at the moment primarily as a system of reciprocity. States are willing to perform their duties under international law to the extent that they can expect other states to go along as well or to the extent that they think that they will be sanctioned for nonperformance by other states. This does not imply that states merely act in their selfinterests. They may be willing to reciprocate in certain conditions in which they must make some sacrifices. And they are often only willing to sanction other states for violations of international law or norms.xxxiv But in the main, the whole system and most of its parts have to be working in the long run interests of each political society. An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy T. Christiano 23 The main point I want to draw from this conception of the international system is the idea that (1) the international system (states and international law and organizations) effectively enforces only reciprocating treaties.xxxv What I mean by this is that states or international institutions will punish or sanction other states in the international system for violation of international law when the sanctioning states (either within the international institutions or independent of such institutions) have some substantial interest in doing so. The emphasis on the international system in this premise is meant to allow for the fact that sometimes international law is enforced by states on themselves through their domestic legal systems. This would not be a case of the international system enforcing international law; it is a case of the domestic legal system enforcing international law. This distinction will be of some significance in what follows. The next premise is that (2) human rights treaties are not reciprocating treaties. They consist primarily in treaties that say you must not violate the human rights of your citizens and we must not violate the human rights of our citizens. They usually do not have the form of “you do something for us and we will do something for you”. The consequence is that states have a lot less at stake in protecting human rights or at least the human rights of citizens of other states. There is an exception to this rule of great interest. At least in form, international humanitarian law seems to have a kind of reciprocating character. Laws against the mistreatment of prisoners and sometimes of civilian populations in the context of war do seem to have a reciprocating character. And this character is often noted in the context of war. If we mistreat the soldiers of our opponents in war, they will feel less compunction about mistreating our soldiers in war. If they mistreat our civilian population during war, An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy T. Christiano 24 we will feel less compunction about mistreating their civilian populations during war. The logic of international humanitarian law is quite unclear to me so I will not have much to say about this here, though further reflection may show that it is more important than I am suggesting. There is some evidence regarding democracies in wartime and it is quite mixed. Democracies are not better in following the laws of war than other societies except when they have ratified treaties concerning the laws of war. Then they are substantially better at acting in accord with the laws of war than other societies even if their opponents in war have not ratified the treaties.xxxvi And all states tend to act in accord with the laws of war much more when their opponents do and tend to violate the laws when their opponents do not. But I will not pursue this issue here. If it is true that the international system only enforces reciprocating treaties and human rights treaties (at least those that deal with human rights in peacetime) are not reciprocating treaties, then the international system will not enforce human rights treaties. It may be useful here to note that while this does not paint a pretty picture of the international system it does not imply that the system is evil or that states are evil. For this non-enforcement of human rights treaties may be an implication of the fact that states are primarily devoted to the establishment of justice within their jurisdictions and act as representatives of their peoples when dealing with other societies. Ideally, they take themselves to be advancing justice for their own peoples and to be advancing the interests of their own peoples. These are good aims in themselves. And we can have some respect for the restraint that states display when they do not try to advance justice for other peoples or their interests. This is because states have no obvious mechanisms by which they can be made accountable to the interests or opinions of those who are not An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy T. Christiano 25 citizens, at least none when the state of which those people are members is not considered. Or if we do not wish to praise states for this restraint we can still see that there is something desirable in the fact that states, constituted as they currently are, do not take a deep interest in the citizens of other states except as they are represented by other states. The desirability of this restraint has its limits, as in the case of neglect of largescale genocide or ethnic cleansing, but there is in the normal case something good about this.xxxvii In the last ten years a body of evidence has developed that supports these contentions about the nature of the international system. Some international relations theorists and legal thinkers have described what they call the “realist insight” concerning human rights treaties.xxxviii They have argued that human rights treaties do not generally make much difference to the human rights performance of the states that have signed on to them except under special conditions. Oona Hathaway has argued that human rights treaties do not make much difference to human rights performance. Indeed she marshals a body of statistical evidence that suggests that the signing of human rights treaties actually worsens the human rights records of the worst offenders of human rights while improving the human rights records of those states that already protect human rights through their domestic legal systems.xxxix Emily Hafner-Burton and Beth Simmons come to roughly similar conclusions concerning the ability of the international system to protect human rights.xl Some have concluded from this type of evidence that in fact human rights treaties have no impact whatsoever. Eric Posner and Jack Goldsmith have argued this on the basis of a broadly realist approach to human rights law.xli They argue that international An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy T. Christiano 26 law works when it achieves genuine coordination but not otherwise. For them, human rights law is essentially cheap talk that serves to camouflage bad behavior at worst and has no effect at best. And this kind of view is probably the norm in international relations theory at the moment. But the above observations about the inertia of the international system regarding human rights leaves open an interesting space in which international human rights law can have some impact. Indeed, the observations of much current scholarship on human rights law is that it has an impact on societies but mainly through the domestic institutions of those societies. Human Rights Treaties and Domestic Institutions The argument of much recent work is that human rights law has an impact through the domestic legal and political systems of societies. And the thought has been that it is those societies with strong rule of law and democratic institutions that are likely to have the most impact on human rights performance. The kind of domestic political/legal system that is effective in enforcing human rights treaties is a democratic political/legal system. And for societies in which there is little or no democracy or rule of law, the effect of human rights law is often very little and in many cases there is evidence that the human rights records get worse.xlii The basic logic behind this very robust set of results is that international treaties enable domestic constituencies to bring forth claims against governments in the name of the human rights treaties. The democratic system ensures that these domestic constituencies are well organized and have the kind of effectiveness that is necessary to An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy T. Christiano 27 make use of the norms of international human rights law to advance their interests. The perhaps unsurprising conclusion is that those who are most likely to be protected by human rights norms are the ones who are most likely to try to make sure they are enforced. But democratic societies also enable other concerned groups effectively to mobilize against human rights abuses, as we saw in the case of the recent torture scandals in the United States. And it is in democratic societies that these groups are permitted to come forward and press their claims and it is in these societies that these groups are well organized and politically effective. Hence they can mobilize in domestic political forums for change or for improvements in human rights treatment. Furthermore, it is in democratic societies where the claims of these groups are respected in courts when they are brought to court and where they are enforced by courts in a variety of ways. Beth Simmons states that “stable democracies’” human rights performance is not affected by ratification of human rights treaties. By a “stable democracy” she means a democracy that has not fallen below 8 in the Polity IV data set since World War II. She argues that ratification of human rights treaties has an effect on the human rights performance of “partial/transitional democracies,” which are defined as all those countries that are not stable and not autocracies. She argues that stable democracies protect human rights whether or not they ratify human rights treaties. Partial/transitional democracies are ones that improve their human rights records as a result of ratification. Once they make the transition to democracy, constituencies are able to mobilize to protect human rights and the treaties are a resource they can use to do this as well as a means of educating the populace to prefer the protection of human rights.xliii Here the model of a minimally egalitarian democracy seems to come into play. Politicians in An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy T. Christiano 28 democracies that are newly minted and reasonably high quality agree to human rights treaties because they think that this will lock in human rights protections. And the reason why these might lock in human rights protections is because later politicians will fear being thrown out of office as a consequence of violating human rights norms that are enshrined in treaties the state has ratified. Democracies enable a great variety of constituencies to mobilize and thus maximize the chances that a later politician’s career will be damaged if he or she ignores human rights standards. These data look quite similar to the data noted above that give evidence of a significant increase in human rights protection within five years of a society becoming high quality democracies. They suggest in a distinct way how democracy of a high quality sort can improve the protection of personal integrity rights. There is some complexity here that is difficult to sort out. The categorization of democracies is troubling. It does not map on easily to the distinction between high quality and low quality democracies. And it seems to lump together very different societies. France is one of the partial/transitional democracies as well as Haiti.xliv As a consequence, some of these societies are high quality democracies at the moment and others are not. I am tempted to say that recently minted high quality democracies are principally responsible for the showing that partial/transitional democracies improve on their human rights treatment when they ratify human rights treaties. But this might be a tendentious reading of the evidence presented. The conclusion is not as secure from the data that Simmons has provided given her peculiar division of the relevant cases. So this particular piece of the argument remains uncertain to me. An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy T. Christiano 29 By contrast, in non-democratic societies the domestic constituencies of these human rights treaties are either repressed or they find it very hard to organize. Furthermore, I surmise that courts in non-democratic societies are less enthusiastic about protecting the rights of persons even when they are enshrined in law. There simply isn’t the pressure to do so and there is every pressure against doing so. This is borne out by the fact that the human rights treaties don’t have any impact or even have negative impact in these societies. In these cases, the treaties serve as a kind of “cheap talk” that often serves to camouflage actual human rights treatment at least in the short run. This is indeed what is observed in these societies. And since the international system does not have a great deal of impact because states are largely preoccupied with their own interests, one key factor in the protection of human rights is democracy. Democracy and International Institutions Though human rights generally don’t seem to be particularly well protected by the international system, there are two reasons to think that democracy can be so protected. They are the democratic peace argument and the democratic compliance argument. The democratic peace thesis is the idea that democracies do not go to war with one another. The definition of war, as I understand it, requires a thousand battlefield deaths or more. There are very few exceptions to the democratic peace hypothesis and they are controversial and complex. Most international relations scholars accept the democratic peace hypothesis, and many describe it as one of the most robust results in international relations theory. The statistical evidence for it seems to be pretty overwhelming. The democratic peace hypothesis does not imply that democracies do not An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy T. Christiano 30 go to war with other societies. They don’t go to war with each other.xlv The democratic peace thesis provides support for the thesis that it is a global collective good that democracy be widespread since war is one of the most damaging kinds of events that can occur to human societies. Moreover, since war is itself a serious catalyst for human rights violations, an international system that diminishes the prospects for war diminishes the likelihood for human rights violations. Similarly, democracies are more likely to observe treaties than nondemocracies.xlvi Here the idea is that democratic governments are more likely to comply with international treaties than non-democratic governments and they are also more likely to create and sustain international institutions than non democracies. Since societies have interests in international treaties being observed and international institutions being sustained, and democracy is an important pillar of the stability of these institutions, the maintenance of democracy is an important global collective good (in this case, perhaps a public good, since all states benefit from the maintenance of international law and institutions). So unlike the standard human rights there are interests in the international community at large in realizing and maintaining democratic forms of government to the extent that it can. As a consequence, a scheme of international law that enshrines a legal human right to democracy and makes efforts to create, maintain and support democracies not only makes use of the best institutional device known to protect human rights, it also achieves a certain stability in that protection since most of the members of that system have a reason to preserve it. From this I think we can conclude that democracy is the An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy T. Christiano 31 lynchpin in getting international institutions to be genuinely concerned with human rights. From these claims, I think we have a good argument for the second step in the argument for a human right to democracy. We have good reason to think that the international community is morally justified in attempting to respect, protect and assist in the creation of democracies. This is because (1) minimally egalitarian democracies are normally necessary institutional schemes for protecting human rights of personal integrity and (2) the international system has a genuine interest in respecting, protecting and promoting democracy. It is through the promotion of minimally egalitarian democracies that the international community has the best chance of protecting and promoting the protection of basic human rights. The Right to Defend One’s Rights One might wonder whether the means for promoting a right are always things to which one has a right. I agree that this would not follow. One problem with this inference is that it may merely be that more democracy is a good to be promoted for the sake of better rights protection. In response, the structure of the connection between democracy and human rights is that minimally egalitarian democracy is normally necessary for the protection of rights of personal integrity. More democracy is not merely better for the protection of rights; a certain level is normally necessary. The threshold effect is what helps make the transition between saying we are talking about a good and saying we are talking about a right. An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy T. Christiano 32 A second concern may be illustrated with the following example. One may have duties to bring about peace because this is a means by which rights are protected but it is not clear that there is a right to peace, even though there may be a duty to try to secure it. In reply to this concern we should say that the thing that is instrumentally important to the protection of uncontroversial and weighty human rights itself has the institutional structure of a right. It is a kind of political right. Minimally egalitarian democracy itself is a system of equal rights the effective capacities to exercise of which are responsible for the protection of human rights. The thing that protects human rights gives individuals choices concerning how to protect their rights and those of others. If you want to protect human rights in a particular society you don’t do it directly; you must normally set up a system of equal rights to participate in collective decision-making in that society. Then individuals can protect themselves by choosing how to use these rights. So the duty to secure the rights to personal integrity in a society must go through the granting of opportunities and choices to the members of the society in question. In this respect the right to democracy is similar to the right to a fair trial, which has a primarily instrumental justification. Democracy and fair trials are not merely means to protecting one’s rights. They serve this protective function by granting rights to choose to act in lawful ways in defense of one’s rights and this gives its character as a right.xlvii Finally the right of democracy argued for here is essentially a protective right in that the possession of this right is essential to the protection of other rights. And the structure of the argument depends on the idea that there is widespread agreement on and great urgency to the rights of personal integrity; they are fundamental rights in that they An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy T. Christiano 33 are not derived from their capacity to assist in the protection of other rights. The right to democracy may also be fundamental but that is not the conclusion of this paper. Possible Worries One worry with the above reasoning is whether the international is generally capable of bringing about democracy. Charles Beitz has observed that the evidence that shows that democracy beyond a certain threshold of quality protects human rights also shows that democracies beneath that threshold are as likely to engage in violations of personal integrity as other regimes and that civil war and conflict are likely to generate increased repression. Many regimes get stuck in hybrid and unsatisfactory states in their attempts to make the transition to full democracy. Furthermore, trying to bring about a high quality democratic regime from the outside is likely not to be very successful. As a consequence, he argues that to try to bring about democratic regimes of high quality is likely to be a highly precarious and problematic activity. As a consequence, he thinks that it is not morally desirable for international institutions to be engaged in promoting democracy at least as a general matter. And for this reason he thinks that there may be no human right to democracy.xlviii My first response to this reasoning is that it would seem also to cut against counting the rights against torture, political imprisonment and state murder as human rights. For it appears that the usual way of achieving the protection of these rights is through a change of regime, if the above reasoning is correct. And in any case, many regimes will fiercely resist the push to get them to protect human rights. But, by hypothesis, such actions will likely bring about violence and human rights violations in An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy T. Christiano 34 the process and may not succeed. International institutions can often do very little to help. Second, I do not think the objection succeeds. The basic problem here is that we must distinguish between when a person’s duty to perform some or any particular act to fulfill a right is overridden or defeated and when the right against that person does not exist. Consider a case of the police trying to extract a captive from a captor. The captive has a right that the police do what they can to extract him safely. But there will be circumstances where the police ought to do nothing lest the captor kill the captive. The captive does not thereby lose the right against the police to be free. Though the police ought not to do anything in the circumstances, they still have a genuine duty to help the captive. Perhaps in the circumstances, they have a duty to think about how to extricate the captive without harming him. I would think that something like this could hold in the case of democracy. It may be the case that the best thing the international community can do to push a nondemocracy in a particular circumstance is nothing because the non-democratic elites would react with such ferocity or because they could manage to stall the transition in a highly unsatisfactory and violent middle state. But this would not be a reason for thinking that the international community was not morally justified in trying to do whatever it could to bring about democracy. I do not take the fact that attempts at reform might be met with violence or might fail to defeat the idea that there are human rights at stake. But I do think that there are interesting moral questions about what one may risk and what one may not risk in trying to bring about greater human rights protection. There are circumstances in which the An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy T. Christiano 35 magnitude of human rights violations that might arise from trying to make a transition to a human rights respecting society are such that the efforts at reform are not worth the moral costs. But this does not defeat the idea that there are human rights at stake. A second worry is whether democracy does better in some respects but worse in others. If democracy does better in terms of protection of human rights to personal integrity but it does worse on other rights, perhaps there is still reason to think that democracy is not a human right. But it does not appear that there are any respects in which democracy does worse. In terms of civil rights more generally, democracy seems to do better. One respect in which some have thought that people are worse off under democracy is in the avoidance of poverty. This would, in my view, be a serious mark against democracy if it tended to do worse by the poor than more authoritarian regimes, particularly in poor countries. But there does not appear to be good evidence for this and some have argued the opposite.xlix At the moment, one must say that we do not know whether democracy does better or worse or the same as other regimes in maintaining the welfare of the worst off in poor societies. The weight of the evidence still favors the claim that democracies do no worse in this respect. Another respect in which democracies might be inferior is in terms of overall crime rates. Some might wonder if protection of human rights to personal integrity, which are rights against the state, may not be overemphasized here. If, for example, there are more violent crimes against the person in democratic societies than in non-democratic societies, one may wonder if the protection of persons from states is worth the cost. I think this is a serious worry, but I have not seen evidence that violent crime in high quality democracies is higher than in other societies. Studies need to be made on this An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy T. Christiano 36 subject. A cursory look at the United Nations annual statistics on homicides in countries throughout the world does not suggest that democracies do worse than non-democracies and even suggests that they may do better, but I am not sure about this.l There is a third puzzle about the arguments I have made above. This has to do with the fact that we are making a statistical argument. There are two worries here. One is that the data may naturally disaggregate democracies into different kinds of democracies with empirically identifiable features and that we should look at these smaller subcategories in assessing how we should react to a society. Of course we have already done that partly by distinguishing between minimally egalitarian democracies and democracies that fall below that standard. But within the subcategory of minimally egalitarian democracies, we might decide that some are worth protecting or promoting and others are not. And then we might not have a general human right to democracy (or even minimally egalitarian democracy). Indeed we may discard the idea that the human right has anything necessarily to do with democracy per se.li But the best empirical evidence we have at the moment suggests no such further division. Per capita GDP, population and war have been controlled for and these have not undermined the significant effects of minimally egalitarian democracy. And people have been looking for further ways to disaggregate the category of democracies. They have not found them. So we must at the moment go with the idea that in general one should prefer on the basis of human rights that a society be democratic in a minimally egalitarian way rather than non-democratic. Two, since they are statistical arguments, they allow for outliers that do not conform to the statistical generalization. They allow for individual cases that fall outside An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy T. Christiano 37 the norm. So we can at least imagine the following scenario and know that it is not impossible empirically. Suppose that we live in a minimally egalitarian democracy and there are major human rights violations taking place on a regular basis and we know that were we to bring about an authoritarian regime, the human rights violations would decrease very significantly and no other new human rights violations would arise. This, again, is a very strange case without a doubt, but it is worth reflecting on since it might give us some insight into the structure of the right. My inclination in this case is to say that the human right to democracy would be defeated in this case. It would be defeated in a particular way. The defeater would be an undercutting defeater, so that the right would not merely be overridden as might happen were some weightier consideration to be balanced against it. The defeater would undermine the ground of the right altogether and thus eliminate it without remainder for as long as the circumstances obtained. This is the implication of the fact that the grounds adduced here are essentially instrumental. Once the outcomes of the instrumentally justified institution are known to be not forthcoming and only alternative institutions can produce these outcomes, then the instrumentally justified institution is no longer justified in the circumstances. This seems to me to be the right approach to democracy at least with respect to fundamental human rights, but does it undermine the thesis that there is a human right to democracy? I am not convinced that it does because, one, most (probably all) rights are defeasible. Even the rights not to be tortured or murdered for political reasons can be defeated if the moral considerations on the other side are sufficiently weighty.lii To be sure the rights against torture are not undercut by other considerations, so that makes this An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy T. Christiano 38 form of defeat distinct. But a person’s rights to liberty can be undercut if that person has engaged in serious criminal activity. My second point though is that the comparison with a right to a fair trial may be of use here. For here too we can imagine a case in which a fair trial would without doubt get the wrong outcome for an individual for various reasons and that a trial procedure that was not fair would have a better and more just set of outcomes. We can even imagine that a system of fair trials more generally would produce problematic outcomes under certain circumstances. This possibility is more remote than in the case of democracy, but it is still possible. In this case, it would seem that the right to a fair trial would be undercut by its loss of instrumental value. So I think it is no surprise that rights that enable people normally to defend their rights are undercut in those circumstances where they clearly do not enable people to defend themselves or even undermine that ability and where alternative arrangements would do better.liii Self-Determination Objection The self-determination objection states that the human right to democracy interferes with the legitimate self-determination of peoples. On one conception of self-determination, a people is self-determining when (1) their political institutions accord with political ideals they share and that have survived their critical reflection and (2) when the political institutions are broadly consultative in the sense that all the different groups in society are consulted in the making of decisions.liv The argument is that one must tolerate societies in which the members share different political ideals and which are responsive to the persons in them just as one must tolerate individuals that hold different religious beliefs in domestic societies. It is An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy T. Christiano 39 claimed that some societies share political ideals that are not democratic because they reject egalitarian ideas. If there is a human right to democracy, it is argued, then the international community is morally committed to protecting and promoting minimally egalitarian democracy. But if the international community is committed to protecting and promoting minimally egalitarian democracy, then it does not tolerate non-democratic societies. But non-toleration of non-democracies is a threat to their legitimate selfdetermination. Therefore, the idea that there is a human right to democracy is a threat to the legitimate self-determination of peoples. Responses to the Self-Determination Objection I do not think that a human right to democracy limits a legitimate right to collective selfdetermination. But we must ask what the conditions for legitimacy are here. One, legitimate collective self-determination usually implies that the society respects uncontroversial and very urgent human rights. Two, considerations of legitimate selfdetermination are usually thought to require unanimity or near unanimity on the alternative arrangements. In the absence of unanimity or near unanimity, it is unclear that many would argue against the need for democracy. In this respect the above conditions of near unanimity and broad participation are usually thought to be sufficient but not necessary conditions. We need to explore these two conditions and what our reaction ought to be when one or both are not met. In reply then to the objection, the first thing to note is that if the arguments of this paper are correct then there is substantial reason to think that in tolerating non-democratic societies citizens of democratic societies are tolerating a very high risk of severe An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy T. Christiano 40 violations of uncontroversial and very urgent human rights. If the arguments of this paper are correct, then toleration of non-democracies amounts in the normal case to toleration of severe human rights violations. Normally then, the absence of minimally egalitarian democracy seems to imply the absence of legitimate collective selfdetermination. Furthermore, the second condition is rarely met in societies except if they are minimally egalitarian democracies. Non-democracies do not have near unanimity on their non-democratic character, at least in the modern world. Democracies do have near unanimity on the democratic structure. So it looks like in the usual case in the great majority of societies that are non-democratic, neither condition holds. Hence, these societies do not have legitimate collective self-determination. The severity of this response can be mitigated in a number of different ways. First, we might accept a weaker conception of collective self-determination and a correspondingly weaker conception of international toleration, both of which can be extended to non-democratic societies. We may think that it is important for a variety of reasons for a society to arrive at democratic institutions on its own for the most part. We may think that home-grown democratic institutions are much more stable and satisfying than externally imposed ones. We may think that external intervention to impose democracy is normally not very likely to succeed in the light of the facts that the intervener’s interests do not usually coincide fully with the supposed beneficiary’s interests and the intervener is not accountable to the supposed beneficiary. In this respect we might have an instrumental argument for the weaker notion of collective selfdetermination as non-intervention. And we might have a correspondingly weaker notion of toleration as non-intervention. We might reserve the stronger notion of toleration for An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy T. Christiano 41 democratic societies, where this consists in treating the society with a full kind of equality in the international realm. There are a number of other ways to act on the basis of a human right to democracy than external intervention against contented non-democratic societies (assuming that there are any). We can offer nonessential assistance to other societies only on condition that they take steps to democratize. We can step in, in a variety of ways, when an elite attempts to take over a democratic society by force or by fraud. We can offer assistance to societies struggling to achieve democratic institutions.lv Furthermore, my arguments for the human right to democracy do not require perfect democracy or perfect justice. They defend minimally egalitarian democracy. Hence they do leave significant room for local variation among societies in terms of the kind of democratic system they adopt as well as the justice of the political system they create. They do not resolve all issues and allow for room in which significant disagreement can be expressed and different views can be realized. Minimally egalitarian democracy is compatible with consociational democracy, majoritarian democracy, presidential systems, parliamentary systems, proportional representation and single member district representation as well as other forms of democracy. Furthermore, democratic systems in also have authority to make decisions on issues relating to justice as long as the decisions respect certain limits most notably the fundamental rights of persons. In this sense, the argument I have provided for democracy leaves substantial room for the self-determination of peoples. It does limit that room but so will any conception of human rights. An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy T. Christiano 42 But I think that there is some interest in briefly thinking about the kinds of pure cases of collective self-determination that Rawls and Cohen seem to have in mind. Suppose it is true that the society in question nearly unanimously accepts both nondemocratic rule and the sorts of human rights violations we described and these occur. Or suppose that the society in question nearly unanimously accepts non-democratic rule but not the other kinds of human rights violations and these do not occur (anomalously). What should we think in this case? Must the argument for a human right to democracy imply that these societies must not be tolerated in the weak or the strong sense? It is not clear to me that it does. There are at least two plausible political principles that might be invoked here in support of the right of collective selfdetermination that do not conflict with the human right to democracy. The first principle is the volenti principle: that one does not do injustice voluntarily to oneself. This principle is often used to limit the impact of principles on persons. And if the near unanimity for non-democracy holds perhaps we can say that the people involved are not doing injustice. The second principle may attach to the human right to democracy and may attach to many rights. It says that many rights come with normative powers that permit one to waive the right in question. If we have near unanimity, perhaps we can say that the members of the population of the non-democratic society are exercising the normative powers attached to their rights to democracy to waive the right to democracy. Either of these theoretical alternatives could explain why despite there being a human right to democracy, a particular society need not be democratic. Furthermore, both of these theoretical alternatives explain why the defenders of non-democratic societies maintain the condition of near unanimity. The absence of unanimity would undermine An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy T. Christiano 43 the use of either one of the two principles to support non-democratic regimes. But it would take us beyond the scope of this paper to explore these ideas further. Conclusion I have argued that there is a human right to democracy understood as a minimally egalitarian democracy on the basis of three claims. One, there is strong moral justification for states to realize minimally egalitarian democracy because of the fact that such democracies are normally quite reliable in protecting fundamental human rights of personal integrity. Societies that fall short of minimally egalitarian democracies are normally reliable in not protecting such human rights. Two, there is moral justification for the international community to attempt to protect and promote these democracies because they protect fundamental human rights to which virtually all are committed and because democracies ensure stability and reduce violence overall in the international system. Three, the moral justification is accords an equal right to all members of the society to defend their rights and hence what is justified has the appropriate structure of a right. The argument offered is relentlessly instrumental and mostly empirical. Many might think that there is also a more intrinsic justification for democracy. I do not disagree. But the instrumental argument is of particular importance because, one, it ties the justification of the human right to democracy to rights that are especially urgent and universally recognized. Two, it supplies an argument for democracy on the basis of considerations that are normally beyond the authority of democracy. As I see it, no democracy no matter what the quality has the right to authorize torture, state murder or An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy T. Christiano 44 disappearance, or political imprisonment. These acts fall outside the authority of democracy (though there may be some legitimate role of democracy in defining the exact boundaries of these rights for a particular society). Democracy loses its authority to the extent that it systematically violates these rights.lvi The only moral relationship democracy could have to these rights is a protective one. So it is of great interest to see that in fact minimally egalitarian democracy is the best kind of institutional setup we know of for protecting these rights.lvii i See John Rawls, The Law of Peoples (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999) pp. 71-81. See also Joshua Cohen “Is There A Human Right to Democracy?” in The Egalitarian Conscience, ed. Christina Sypnovich (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006); and see Jon Mandle, Global Justice (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2006), pp. 54-55; and see David Reidy, “Political Authority and Human Rights,” and Allysa Bernstein, “A Human Right to Democracy? Legitimacy and Intervention,” in Rawls’s Law of Peoples: A Realistic Utopia? ed. David Reidy and Rex Martin (Oxford: Blackwell, 2006). ii See, for example, Charles Beitz, The Idea of Human Rights (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009), pp. 174-186 and Andrew Altman and Christopher Wellman, A Liberal Theory of International Justice (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009) pp. 31-2. iii For a sample of some recent work, see James Griffin, On Human Rights (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008), p. 255. iv See Allen Buchanan, Justice, Legitimacy and Self-Determination: Moral Foundations for International Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004), pp. 145-47 where he points to the possibility of this kind of argument. I think something like this kind of argument is also made in part in Henry Shue’s Basic Rights: Subsistence, Affluence and U. S. Foreign Policy rev. ed. (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1996), pp. 74-8. v I am working on this kind of argument in my “An Intrinsic Argument for a Human Right to Democracy,” ms. See also Carol Gould, Globalizing Democracy and Human Rights (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004) and James Bohman’s Democracy An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy T. Christiano 45 Across Borders (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2007) for other distinct attempts to provide intrinsic arguments for democracy. vi See Thomas Pogge, World Poverty and Human Rights (London: Polity Press, 2002). vii See Charles Beitz, The Idea of Human Rights for this two level (states and then international institutions) view of human rights. Beitz’s view is one of necessary and sufficient conditions, I only assert a set of sufficient conditions for a human rights here. viii See L. W. Sumner, The Moral Foundation of Rights (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987) pp. 144-5 for the distinction between weak and strong moral justification of a convention. ix A natural way of thinking of human rights as protecting fundamental human interests is to say that human rights are necessary conditions of a minimally decent human life. But I do not think this will do because not all human rights have this character. This widespread view may give a good account of the right to adequate material subsistence but I doubt that it covers such rights as the right not to be tortured or the right not to be enslaved. Unless “minimally decent” human life is understood in a highly moralized way it is hard to see how having been tortured will necessarily undermine such a life and it seems to be the case that slaves have been able to make decent lives for themselves despite the profoundly oppressive treatment they receive. The attempt to connect all human rights to a minimally decent human life ignores the resilience of human beings in the face of extremely oppressive treatment. In any case, it seems that if we think that human rights are necessary conditions for a minimally decent human life, it seems clear that there is no human right to democracy (unless we have a highly moralized conception of a minimally decent human life). For the view of human rights as necessary conditions for a minimally decent human life, see Allen Buchanan, Justice, Legitimacy and SelfDetermination (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004), James Nickel, Making Sense of Human Rights rev. ed. (Oxford: Blackwell, 2006), Jon Mandle, Global Justice (London: Polity Press, 2006) and David Miller, National Responsibility and Global Justice (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007) for accounts of human rights of this sort. x See Charles Beitz, The Idea of Human Rights (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009) for xi See International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (December 16, 1966, 999 U. N. T. S. 171) Art. 4 xii See Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties (May 23, 1969, U. N. Doc. A/CONF. 39/27), Arts. 53 and 64, which say that any treaty that conflicts with a peremptory norm of international law is void even if the peremptory norm emerges after the treaty is ratified. See also Barry Carter, Phillip R. Trimble and Curtis Bradley, International Law 4th ed. (New York: Aspen Publishers, 2003), p. 107-8. xiii Steven C. Poe; C. Neal Tate; Linda Camp Keith, “Repression of the Human Right to Personal Integrity Revisited: A Global Cross-National Study Covering the Years 19761993,” International Studies Quarterly, Vol. 43, No. 2. (Jun., 1999), pp. 291-313 xiv See Polity IV Project: Political Regime Characteristics and Transitions, 1800-2007 http://www.systemicpeace.org/polity/polity4.htm xv See Tatu Vanhanen, “A New Dataset for Measuring Democracy, 1810-1998,” Journal of Peace Research Vol. 37, n. 2 2000, pp. 251-265 for an account of the Vanhanen method of measuring democracies. An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy T. Christiano xvi 46 Here is a brief description of the political terror scale that is used by Poe et al. as described in Davenport. “Regarding the indicator itself, (Poe, Tate, and Keith 1999, 297) state that, "(t)he application of the criteria to information about... the coding categories and their criteria are: '1'-Countries (within this category are) under a secure rule of law, people are not imprisoned for their views, torture is rare or exceptional (and) political murders are extremely infrequent." Examples include the US, Venezuela 1977 and 1981, and Senegal 1976-1981; '2' (Within this category) "(t)here is a limited amount of imprisonment for nonviolent political activity. However, few persons are affected, torture and beating are exceptional political murder is rare." Examples include Mexico 1976 and 1983 as well as Gambia 1982; '3' (Within this category) "(t)here is extensive political imprisonment, or a recent history of such imprisonment. Execution or other political murders and brutality may be common. Unlimited detention, with or without trial, for political views is accepted." Examples include Cuba 1976, Cameroon 1979, and Poland 1976-1977; '4'-(Within this category) "(t)he practices of (Level 3) are expanded to larger numbers. Murders, disappearances are a common part of life. In spite of its generality, on this level terror affects primarily those who inter- est themselves in politics or ideas." Examples include El Salvador 1978-1992 and Rwanda 1990-1991; and, '5'-(Within this category) "(t)he terrors of (Level 4) have been expanded to the whole population. The leaders of these societies place no limits on the means or thoroughness with which they pursue personal or ideological goals." Examples include Haiti 1991, Sudan 1988, Rwanda 1994-1996, and China 1989.” See Davenport n 11 below, pp. 544-545. xvii See Political Terror Scale 1976-2008 at http://www.politicalterrorscale.org/ for more discussion. And see Reed Wood and Mark Gibney, “The Political Terror Scale (PTS): A Re-introduction and a Comparison to CIRI” Human Rights Quarterly (forthcoming) for a discussion of the methods of measurement. xviii Christian Davenport and David A. Armstrong, II, “Democracy and the Violation of Human Rights: A Statistical Analysis from 1976 to 1996,” American Journal of Political Science, Vol. 48, No. 3 (Jul., 2004), pp. 538-554. See also, Bruce Bueno de Mesquita, G. W. Downs, A. Smith, and F. M. Cherif, “Thinking inside the Box: A Closer Look at Democracy and Human Rights,” International Studies Quarterly 49 (3) 2005: 439-57. For a fuller discussion see, Christian Davenport, State Repression and the Domestic Democratic Peace (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007). xix This is the main distinctive contribution of Hafner-Burton and Tsutui in footnote 2. xx See Davenport and Armstrong, p. 548 and Bueno de Mequita, p. 448. xxi See Adam Przeworski Michael E. Alvarez, Jose Antonio Cheibub, and Fernando Limongi, Democracy and Development: Political Institutions and Well Being in the World 1950-1990 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000) for the most extensive statistical studies of the relationships between democracy and development that I know of. xxii See Christian Davenport, State Repression and the Domestic Democratic Peace chap 5 for an in depth examination of the statistical evidence of democratic violations of personal integrity rights under wartime conditions. xxiii Bueno de Mesquita et al. p. 452. xxiv I thank Gary Goertz for making me less complacent about this issue. An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy T. Christiano 47 This is emphasized both in Bueno de Mesquita et. al.’s paper and in Davenport, State Repression and the Domestic Democratic Peace, chaps 4 and 5. xxvi See See John Rawls, The Law of Peoples (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999), pp. 77-78 and Joshua Cohen, “Is There A Human Right to Democracy?” in The Egalitarian Conscience, ed. Christina Sypnovich (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006), pp. 226-248, esp. 233. xxvii See Joshua Cohen, “Is There A Human Right to Democracy?” for this kind of view. xxviii The one element that is missing is the corporatist structure in which groups are represented in the assemblies. I haven’t found a regime that has these qualities among contemporary regimes. I have assumed that popular elections of the legislature and some executives can stand in for this. But this may make an as yet undetected difference. xxix See Monty Marshall and Keith Jaggers, Polity IV Data Set User’s Manual (2000) Addendum for a discussion of the different regime types. See also the Polity IV Data Set for country descriptions of China and Iran. These features of high quality democracies are emphasized in Davenport, State Repression and the Domestic Democratic Peace chap. 4 as well as in Bueno de Mesquita et al. “Thinking inside the Box,” p. 453. xxx For Oman’s political system, see the country reports of the Polity IV data base and the Freedom House data base. For an account of its relatively light repression of personal integrity rights, see the Political Terror Scale country report for Oman. But see also the significantly less positive country report of freedom house on civil rights in Oman. It is clearly an outlier and this seems to depend on the will of the particular sultan in power. xxxi This seems to satisfy Rawls’s requirement for the case for liberal democracy. He says, “Should the facts of history, …show that hierarchical regimes are always or nearly always, oppressive and deny human rights, the case for liberal democracy is made.” Rawls, The Law of Peoples, p. 79. Joshua Cohen seems to say the same: “If democracy is a requirement for avoiding unacceptable circumstances, we do have a case for it…” (p. 245) xxxii Further confirmation of this can be seen in David Cingranelli and Mikhail Filippov’s “Electoral Rules and Incentives to Protect Human Rights,” The Journal of Politics Vol 72, no. 1 January 2010, Pp. 1-15, where they argue that systems with proportional representation and individual accountability score better on physical integrity rights than single member district representation. xxxiii In this respect, the human right to democracy that I am giving is not maximalist in Joshua Cohen’s sense and leaves ample room for the collective self-determination of peoples. See his “Is there a Human Right to Democracy?” pp. 232-233. xxxiv See Gary Goertz, International Norms and Decision-Making: A Punctuated Equilibrium Model (New York: Rowman and Littlefield, 2003) chap. 11. xxxv See Beth Simmons, Mobilizing for Human Rights (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009) chap. 4. xxxvi See James D. Morrow, “When Do States Follow the Laws of War?” American Political Science Review Vol. 101, N 3, August 2007, pp. 559-572. xxxvii In addition, it should be noted that states do in effect take the citizens of other states into account when they negotiate with those other states. This will play a role in the second main argument of this paper. xxv An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy T. Christiano 48 xxxviii See Beth Simmons, Mobilizing for Human Rights (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009) xxxix See Oona Hathaway, “Do Human Rights Treaties Make a Difference?” Yale Law Journal June 2002, pp. 1935-2042 xl Emily Hafner-Burton and Kiyoteru Tsutsui, “Human Rights in a Globalizing World: The Paradox of Empty Promises” American Journal of Sociology Volume 110 Number 5 (March 2005): 1373–1411. See also Linda Camp Keith, “The United Nations International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights: Does It Make a Difference in Human Rights Behavior?” Journal of Peace Research 36 (1) 1999: 95-118. xli Jack Goldsmith and Eric Posner, The Limits of International Law (New York: Oxford University Press, 2006). xlii See Simmons and Hafner-Burton and Tsutui as well as Hathaway above in footnotes 2 and 3. See also Eric Neumayer, “Do International Human Rights Treaties Improve Respect for Human Rights? Journal of Conflict Resolution Vol. 49 No. 6, December 2005 925-953 and Oona Hathaway, “Why Do Countries Commit to Human Rights Treaties? Journal of Conflict Resolution Volume 51 Number 4 August 2007 588-621 xliii See Simmons, Mobilizing for Human Rights, p. 276. xliv See Simmons, Mobilizing for Human Rights, Appendix 2, pp. 396-7. xlv There is a mountain of evidence in favor of this thesis. Probably the most prominent defender is Bruce Russett and Harvey Starr, “From Democratic Peace to Kantian Peace: Democracy and Conflict in the International System,” Handbook of War Studies II ed. Manus Midlarsky (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 2000): pp. 93-128. xlvi See Beth A. Simmons, “Compliance with International Agreements,” 1 ANN. REV. POL. SCI. 75, 77, 83–85 (1998). xlvii Allen Buchanan has suggested to me that the right to participate as an equal in collective decision-making might be thought to be distinct from the right to a fair trial in one respect. The latter right can be exercised effectively merely as an individual right. But the democratic right requires for its effectiveness that every citizen have this right and that the rights be equal. In this sense the right to democracy has an essentially collective dimension. To illustrate, if I am the only person of a particular group that shares important distinctive interests to have the right to vote, my right to vote will not be exercised effectively because I need others to go along with me for the exercise of my right to be effective. In this respect, one person’s possession of a democratic right depends on others’ possession. But this aspect of the democratic right is also an essential part of the protective capacity of democracy. It is only the minimally equal possession of this right that gives the fullest protection to the other human rights people have. In fact however, the rights to a fair trial also have an essentially collective dimension. For, it is not clear that one can receive a fair trial in a society in which no one else has a fair trial. The others will be frightened by the prospect of arbitrary criminal prosecution. It is true that I can effectively exercise my right to a fair trial without others also exercising their rights but I cannot possess such a right without many others possessing it. The only rights that are genuinely deeply individual are the rights of personal integrity. My right not to be tortured can be protected even while no one else’s is and the same goes for my right to life. In contrast, the rights to freedom either do not An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy T. Christiano 49 exist or cannot be exercised effectively without many others having the same rights. My rights to free expression and free association simply cannot be effectively exercised if many others like me do not have these rights. They all have a collective dimension. xlviii See Charles Beitz, The Idea of Human Rights, 178-180 for this argument. xlix See Przeworski et al. Democracy and Development for a powerful set of arguments that democracies do not do worse than non-democracies in terms of overall growth and that in fact they do significantly better than non-democracies in terms of per capita growth. See also Morton Halperin, Joseph Siegle and Michael Weinstein, “Why Democracies Excel,” Foreign Affairs September/October 2004 pp. 57-71. See also their book The Democracy Advantage 2nd ed. (New York: Routledge, 2010). And Amartya Sen has also argued for the economic virtues of democracy, especially regarding the poor in Development as Freedom (New York: Knopf, 1999). l See the United Nations Crime Trends Statistics on Homicides. li I think this is the gist of Beitz’s objection on p. 179. lii Of course these rights are non-derogable in international law (see ICCPR Article 4 section 2) and I think that makes sense but that is compatible with there being circumstances in which the rights are morally overridden. liii Here we can see that the human right to democracy has a quite different ground from Shue’s basic right to participation. Shue thinks of such a basic right as constitutive of other rights, not merely instrumental to their protection. Of course, Shue also does not defend a right to democracy since he nowhere argues for a right to equal participation. liv This is roughly the conception Joshua Cohen endorses in his “Is There A Human Right to Democracy?” in The Egalitarian Conscience, ed. Christina Sypnovich (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006), pp. 233-234. I compress his three requirements into the second of mine above. The first requirement is expressed on page 234 when he says that since, “ democratic ideas lack substantial resonance in the political culture, or the history and traditions of the country….the value of collective self-determination itself recommends resistance to the idea that the political society should be required to meet the standard expressed in a principle of equal basic liberties…” (234) Rawls seems to think that self-determination is an important consideration underwriting the toleration of decent consultation hierarchies. See The Law of Peoples, p. 61. Another defender of something like a self-determination argument for toleration is Jon Mandle in Global Justice. See also the essays by David Reidy and Allysa Bernstein in Rawls’s Law of Peoples ed. David Reidy and Rex Martin (Oxford: Blackwell, 2004). David Miller is also a defender of the idea of national self-determination, but he seems to think that liberal democracy is an important though not necessary condition of national self-determination. See his On Nationality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995), pp. 89-90. lv For the many ways in which international institutions can act on a human right to democracy see Thomas Franck, Fairness in International Law and Institutions (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996). lvi I defend these theses in my The Constitution of Equality: Democratic Authority and Its Limits (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008) chap. 7. lvii I would like to thank Jerry Gaus, Allen Buchanan, David Schmidtz, Loren Lomasky, Gary Goertz, Kathryn Sikkink, Andrew Williams, Houston Smit, Katherine Barnes, Suzanne Dovi, Louis-Phillipe Hodgson, Alex Verhoeve, David Gibbs, James Nickel, An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy T. Christiano 50 Margaret Gilbert, Cindy Holder, Jeremy Webber, Colin MacLeod and others for very helpful discussion of earlier drafts of this paper and its ideas.