TWO KINDS OF REASONING 1. Deductive Logic Logic is the study of arguments. An argument in logic consists of two things: 1. A set of propositions – the premises Which are presented as reasons or support for: 2. A further proposition – the conclusion 1 What are propositions? Propositions are identified by English sentences. A proposition is the claim made by a sentence. Logic analyzes propositions, i.e. definite claims. Logic does not analyze: 1. Questions (what time is it?) 2. Commands (close the door.) 3. Requests (hand me my briefcase.) 4. Exclamations (ah hah!) Etc. The problem (for logic) with these things is that they are neither true nor false. Logic only studies things that are true-orfalse – in other words, propositions. 2 Here is an example of an argument: All humans are mortal. Socrates is human. Therefore: Socrates is mortal. (premises) (conclusion) An argument is good when it is truth preserving, in other words when: It is logically impossible for the conclusion to be false given that the premises are true (anyone who accepts your premises must accept your conclusion). Such arguments are called deductively valid (or, more simply, valid). An invalid argument is an argument that is not valid, i.e. an argument where it is possible for the premises to be true and the conclusion false. 3 Validity can be seen more easily if we look at the logical form (structure) of an argument. What is logical form? To begin, consider these arguments: Either John went to the store or Sue did. John did not go to the store. So, Sue did. Either Yogi is a dog or Yogi is a bear. Yogi is not a dog. So, Yogi is a bear. Now, these are different arguments but they have something in common. 4 Form vs. content J: John went to the store S: Sue went to the Store B: Yogi is a bear D: Yogi is a dog This gives us: J or S Not J So: D or B Not D So: S D These arguments differ in content (we use different letters to represent different propositions). 5 But if we ignore content we can see that they have the same form: p or q Not p So, q Here we let p and q stand for any proposition whatsoever. 6 Grammatical versus Logical Form The grammatical form of a proposition (or of an argument) is the structure of the proposition (or argument) as indicated by the surface grammar of its natural language The logical form of a proposition (or of an argument) is the logically effective structure of the proposition (or argument) as indicated by the meanings of the logical terms it contains 7 Example "Tom, Dick and Harry lifted the box" Grammatical form (Tom, Dick, Harry) lifted the box Potential logical forms (Tom, Dick, Harry) lifted the box (Tom lifted the box) and (Dick lifted the box) and (Harry lifted the box) 8 Another Example "I see nobody on the road," said Alice. "I only wish I had such eyes," the King remarked in a fretful tone. "To be able to see Nobody! And at that distance too! Why, it's as much as I can do to see real people, by this light!" Grammatical forms I see somebody on the road I see nobody on the road Logical forms I see somebody on the road It is not the case that (I see somebody on the road) 9 Consider our previous example (on page 3). It had the following form: All p’s are q’s S is a p So: S is a q This is obviously valid. 10 Don’t confuse the following: Propositions are true or false. For example: Ottawa is the capital of Canada: true. Kingston is the capital of Ontario: false. But: Arguments are valid or invalid. There is no such thing as a valid or invalid proposition. There is no such thing as a true or false argument. 11 An invalid argument can have any combination of true or false premises and a true or false conclusion: All bears are mammals (true) All mammals are warm-blooded Therefore: Toronto is the capital of Ontario (true) If New York is in Canada then it is in North America. (true) New York is in North America. Therefore: New York is in Canada. (false) Etc… In these arguments, it is possible for the premises to be true yet the conclusion false. They are invalid. 12 A deductively valid argument may not have: 1. All true premises and a false conclusion A deductively valid argument may have: 2. one or more false premises and a false conclusion 3. one or more false premises and a true conclusion 4. all true premises and a true conclusion 13 For example: If Toronto is in NY, then it is in France. Toronto is in NY. So: Toronto is in France. This argument is truth preserving because if the premises are true then the conclusion must be true. However, the argument is not sound. 14 An argument is sound if and only if: 1. It is valid and 2. All its premises are true Example: The Prime Minister lives in Ottawa. Ottawa is in Ontario. Therefore: The Prime Minister lives in Ontario. Sound arguments are the best. They are what we want in everyday life. So, we can criticize an argument for having false premises (unsound) or for being a bad piece of reasoning (invalid). 15 However, logic cannot tell us which propositions are true (we must investigate the world to find that out). So: Logic cannot tell us whether an argument is sound. (There are two exceptions to this rule which we shall discuss shortly.) Logic can tell us whether the premises and conclusion are logically related so as to be truth preserving. Logic can determine good reasoning. Logic can tell us whether an argument is valid. Why? Good reasoning does not depend on how the world is; it just depends on the logical relation between premises and conclusion. 16 Deductive validity is a very strict notion. Deductive logic rejects an argument even if it is merely possible for the premises to be true and the conclusion false. We might think of it this way: If there is any risk of an argument leading you astray, deductive logic rejects the argument. It doesn’t matter how small the risk is. Valid arguments are risk-free arguments. 17 Three kinds of propositions Logically necessary Can’t be false, no matter how the world is E.g. ‘either John is 6’ tall or John isn’t 6’ tall’ Logically impossible Can’t be true, no matter how the world is E.g. ‘John is 6’ tall and John isn’t 6’ tall’ Logically contingent Neither logically necessary nor impossible – depend the world. E.g. ‘John is 6’ tall’ 18 A proposition is logically necessary if it is true in virtue of its logical form. Examples: p or not p If p, then p It is logically false if it is false in virtue of its logical form. For example: p and not p If p, then not p So, logic can tell us whether a proposition is logically necessary or logically impossible. It cannot tell us whether a contingent proposition is true or false. 19 2. Inductive Logic In many situations you must use risky arguments: 1. Should I major in physics or history? 2. Should I buy stock in company x? 3. Should I open my own business? Etc… The outcomes of your choices are uncertain, so to answer these questions you must reason about risk. Consider this argument: All the history majors I talked to got a good job. So: If I major in history I will get a good job. This argument is invalid: the conclusion could be false even if the premise is true. This argument takes a risk. 20 The previous argument does not seem very good. How about this? Most history majors in this school got good jobs. Therefore: If I major in history I will get a good job. This is still invalid, but seems better than the first one. According to national statistics, 95% of history majors get good jobs. Therefore: If I major in history I will get a good job. This invalid argument seems better still. 21 All of these arguments reason from populations (history majors) to samples from that population (you, if you choose to major in history). 1. We can also reason from samples to wholes: Jane, Sarah and Mike all majored in history and got good jobs. So: All history majors get good jobs. 2. Or from sample to sample: Jane majored in history and she got a good job So: If John majors in history he will get a good job. These are all risky arguments. 22 Question: How can we evaluate these risky arguments? Answer: Using inductive logic. Question: What’s that? Answer: It’s what this course is about. But let’s get started… 23 When we use risky arguments, it is natural to use the word ‘probably’: According to national statistics, 95% of history majors get good jobs. So, probably: If I major in history I will get a good job. Jane, Sarah and Mike all majored in history and got good jobs. So, probably: All history majors get good jobs. If we could come up with a method of assigning numbers to probability values, we could more easily evaluate risky arguments. So: Probability is a fundamental tool for inductive logic. 24 Even if an argument is invalid, it might be inductively strong because the premises make the conclusion probable. The more probable the premises make the conclusion, the stronger the argument. Inductive logic analyses risky arguments using probability ideas. We can think of this pictorially: Arguments: Deductively valid Stronger Degrees of inductive strength weaker Completely worthless 25 Be careful: Not all arguments with the word “probability” are inductive. For example: This die has six faces: 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6. Each face is equally probable. So: The probability of rolling a 3 is 1/6. This argument is valid: it is impossible for the premises to be true and the conclusion false. However: This die has six faces: 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6. In 120 rolls, 3 came up 21 times. So: The probability of rolling a 3 with this die is about 1/6. This argument is invalid: the die could be biased and the results a coincidence. 26 Similarly, not all risky arguments involve probability: 1. INFERENCE TO THE BEST EXPLANATION (ABDUCTION) Everybody who ate at Restaurant X got sick the next day. So: The food must have been spoiled. Here we offer a hypothesis to explain the observed facts. There may be other plausible explanations: (everybody caught a virus that day, etc.) The most plausible explanation is usually accepted: this is an inference to the best explanation: And it is risky (one of the other explanations might be true). 27 2. TESTIMONY My parents say I was born on January 18th. So: I was born on January 18th. It is unlikely that your parents would lie to you about this, but still… This is a risky argument. Your parents could be mistaken, have some reason to lie, etc. Perhaps probability is useful in analyzing some testimony and abduction. Philosophers disagree on these questions. In this course we will only worry about inductive arguments (samples to wholes, wholes to samples, etc.). 28 Decision Theory When we reason about what to believe, this is called theoretical reasoning. Often, however, we reason because we need to make a decision about what to do. This is called practical reasoning. The study of practical reasoning is called decision theory. Since we must make risky decisions, probability theory will be useful in decision theory. 29 How does decision theory work? We decide what to do on the basis of: 1. What we think will probably happen (beliefs). 2. What we want (values). So, decision theory requires probability theory and a theory of values. Values are measured by what are called utilities. Decision theory analyzes risky decisionmaking using ideas of probability and utility. This is a very brief introduction to decision theory. We shall go into more detail later in the course. 30 Homework: Do the exercises at the end of chapters 1 and 2. 31