Paper presented at the 2005 meeting of Sex Acher, Tel Aviv University Sexuality, Subjectivity and Object Perversion Uri Hadar Why does the sex drive have a special status among drives in shaping personality and mental life? How does the singularity of sexuality informs the notion of sexual aberration? These two questions initiate theoretical psychoanalysis as well as inform its rite of passage from a biological to a cultural discipline. The first steps in addressing these questions were presented in the "three essays". There, and from there on, the answers have been placed firmly in the domain of the object, namely, the domain of things that the drive seeks in order to be satisfied, its addressees. It is the nature of its objects, their variety, their suitability, that makes the sexual drive special among drives. My contribution will trace this perspective on sexuality, namely, the specialness of the sex drive and its relation to the notion of sexual aberration. In the three essays the sex drive is characterized as the only drive that tends to expand beyond the object that affords its immediate satisfaction. In the words of Freud, “it is only in the rarest instances that the psychical valuation that is set on the sexual object, as being the goal of the sexual instinct, stops short at its genitals. The appreciation extends to the whole body of the sexual object and tends to involve every sensation derived from it. The same overvaluation spreads over into the psychological sphere: the subject becomes, as it were, intellectually infatuated…” (p. 61 in the Pelican edition). So the object is not compact and can not be limited to the other’s genitalia, and that by sharp contrast with other drives: “a light is thrown on the nature of the sexual instinct by the fact that it permits of so much variation in its objects and such a cheapening of them- which hunger, with its far more retention of its objects, would only permit in the most extreme circumstances” (p. 60 in the Pelican edition). Here lies the difference between sex and sexuality: if you get satisfied through contact with the other's genitalia it is sex, but if you get satisfied imagining his or her bottom, then it's a totally different story: it is sexuality. And it is also the point of bifurcation from other drives: one cannot imagine that the phantasy of a spoon will lead to the satisfaction of hunger, but one can easily imagine that analogous phantasies will lead to sexual satisfaction: the phantasy of an organ that neighbors on the genitals (in a metonymic trajectory) or of objects that iconically represent the genitals (in a metaphoric trajectory). The knee in one famous movie, black underpants in another. In the "three essays" this lack of compactness of the sexual drive marks the uniqueness of sex among drives, but it also provides the crucial condition of perverse mentation, both normal and pathological. In fact one can grasp the incompact nature of sexuality by thinking of it as inherently perverse. So inherent is the incompactness of sex in psychoanalysis that by the time of Melanie Klein the restriction of the sexual object to the other's genitals is conceived of as pathological- as a regression to part objects. Similarly, the restriction of the aim of sex to the deposition of sperms in the region of the vagina-come-cervix is equally pathological- despite the adherence to it in much of the American culture (which adherence allowed a president to wholeheartedly claim that he "never had sex with this woman") From the three essays onwards, the psychoanalysis of sexuality has developed in two separate itineraries: one that stresses non-compactness and one that attempts to determine norms. I should like to point some landmarks in the former itinerary. My next station here is the quantum leap from the physicality of the object to its mentality. Soon after the 3 essays Freud came to realize the importance for the child of his or her mother's love and entered it into the mental matrix as a distinct motivational factor. The love of/from the object- distinct from object love- became the main building stone of self esteem and a sense of self but not, in and of itself, of sexuality. Yet, as a motivational factor the love from the object reached a constitutive status. This move came to a climax in "civilization and its discontents", where the fear of death could not be ascribed- as in the early theories- to instincts of survival, because death has taken place as an instinct in its own right. The fear of death had to be construed as a libidinal force, so it was ascribed to the fear of loss of the love of the object. The logical line here was that if the object's love constitutes the self and its value, than its loss involves the loss of self, involves death. In the 1950s, Lacan has re-entered this idea into the analysis of sexuality as such: desire, he said, is always for the desire of the other. Sexuality not only incorporates the wish of the other but is actually predicated upon it. What we want when we desire is for the other to want us. The object has taken here- I think for the first time in psychoanalysis- its position as a subject. Lacan, in that sense, is the first radical intersubjective thinker. Note that the Lacanian shift to the other implies a shift from the notion of drive to the notion of desire and wish, but this shift is not so revolutionary. It featured in 17th century discussion of physical forces (push versus pull) and is inherent in the legend of the Sirens and their irresistible singing. This intersubjective perspective on sexuality totally transforms the notion of object perversion: it now must relate to manipulation of the desire of the other- especially the attempts to eliminate it as constitutive of sexuality- rather than any physical or genderial characteristics of the object. Of course, desire for non-human objects- animate or inanimate- will still be considered perverse (by virtue of eliminating the other's desire). Similarly, rape will be considered perverse- even the paradigmatic perversion- but not homosexual or sadomasochistic practices. At the same time, we'll have a whole range of very ordinary sexual practices that incorporate perverse mentation, the need or wish to remove from our sexual imagination the desire of the other. To be provocative, the whole history of patriarchal notions of sexuality promotes perverse practices, as does the wish to achieve orgasms. However, I find the re-definiition of perversion here a bit tiresome and leave it at that. The last landmark of the incompactcness project which I want to mention here is that of Jean Laplanche. Laplanche takes the role of the other in sexuality a step further than Lacan: For him sexuality is always already the desire of the other. The child first encounters sexuality through the desire of adults. At the time of her first encounter, the child does not have the mental apparatus to process this domain of mental representation and leaves it as a foreign body. Sexuality at this stage does not connect to the rest of the child's psyche and remains marked as 'other', as belonging with the other. In adolescence the subject has already the required mental apparatus to decode the earlier contents, and this is his/her main route of awakening sexuality. However, for Laplanche sexuality always retains its nature as belonging to another. It is always given to expropriation by otherness. Sex preserves a core experienced of it as uncanny, as threatening to the subject in one way or another. Now, the problem with the above intersubjective formulations is that their notion of sexuality is disembodied. For Freud the love of/from the object is distinct from sexuality because it is disembodied, while sexuality is always embodied. This remains a problem for the incompactness project. However, it is this project that Lacan sums up by saying that a sexual relation is impossible. It is impossible, firstly, because the sex drive always expands beyond the strictly sexual, beyond genitalia; secondly, this line of thought necessarily leads to extending sexuality beyond the body, indeed, even beyond sex; and thirdly, sexuality is always given to confiscation, to losing its subject. Fortunately, of course, this also means that sexuality can not be exhausted, it is inherently indefatigable. Which is nice.