1 THEORY OF MIND AND THE SOCIAL DESIGN OF THE MIND An OPEN MIND workshop Bucharest June 14-15, 2013 ABSTRACTS OF INVITED PAPERS _________________________________________________ R. Peter Hobson and Jessica A. Hobson (University College London) Interpersonal engagement, communication, and understanding: What leads to what? We shall set a critique of classic Theory of Mind theorizing within a broad conceptual framework. How does biology prepare an individual to embed in culture? How far do interpersonal engagements provide the basis for intrapsychic development (and vice versa)? How far is human embodied relatedness (with cognitive, affective and motivational aspects) foundational for the development of relatively separable components of thought, feeling and motive? We suggest that the biologically given propensity to identify with the attitudes of others plays a pivotal role in the developmental story – and we shall cite evidence from autism to illustrate what follows when this propensity is fragile. Patricia Ganea (University of Toronto) Mapping language to the mind: Toddlers’ understanding of the mentalistic and representational nature of language Language can be used to communicate one’s beliefs about reality and thus it provides a means to assess children’s understanding of the relation between verbal statements, beliefs and reality. When do young children develop the understanding that the language they hear is a reflection of a person’s mental state, rather than a direct reflection of what is perceptually accessible? In this talk I will present several recent studies that use language as a medium for assessing toddlers’ sensitivity to others’ mental content. I will first discuss a series of findings indicating that comprehension of references to things that are not visible is related to developments in representational ability and intentional understanding. Then I will present research showing that by their second birthday toddlers have come to realize the mentalistic aspect of language use and show surprise when language violates what people know about reality. Further I will show that toddlers can use language to update their representation of an absent object and contrast this with their ability to update their representation of other people’s mental states via language. ______________________________________________________ Josef Perner (University of Salzburg) 2 Object of Thought meets Object Objects of thought are simply the things we think about, inspired by the notion of discourse referents as things we talk about. I elaborate empirically the notion that objects of thought have to be anchored to external objects (Kamp 1990), which is typically an automatic, unreflective process that is not itself an object of thought. Given sensible assumptions about anchoring it can mimic pragmatic concerns without having to represent speaker and listener intentions or knowledge. I will illustrate this with an example from mutual exclusivity research. Some tasks, however, require that the anchoring becomes itself an object of thought. This ability emerges in development around 4 years of age and can account for the fact that at this age children start to master various perspectivetaking tasks. I illustrate this with their success on false belief tasks and their understanding identity statements. There is also evidence that anchoring awareness reliably activates a particular brain region: left inferior parietal lobe (IPL). Gyorgy Gergely (Central European University) Ostension, Epistemsic Trust, and Deferential Beliefs: The social origins and cultural transmission of cognitively opaque knowledge about kinds In this talk I’ll discuss the evolutionary origins and adaptive role of cognitive opacity of beliefs in human conceptual and cultural development in light of new evidence from preverbal infants’ early understanding of ostensive communicative demonstrations of cultural knowledge about artefact and social kinds. The issue of opaque beliefs was originally ignited by Dan Sperber’s (1997) proposal that humans’ evolved a cognitive attitude to acquire and hold ‘reflective semipropositional’ beliefs justified by deference to the authority of their source. I’ll argue that evidence showing young infants’ preparedness to interpret ostensive demonstrative displays as making reference to abstract kinds provides strong support for Sperber’s insight. Natural pedagogy theory (Gergely & Csibra, 2006) proposed that selective pressure for trust-based ostensively guided communicative transmission of relevant cultural knowledge was first created by the emergence of hominid tool use and tool manufacturing technologies whose cognitive opacity for naïve observational learners represented a learneability problem of relevance selection that endangered their intergenerational transmission. Here I’ll extend this argument to the domain of ‘distributed social technologies’ or ‘collaborative tools’ involving cooperatively performed coordinated means actions with complementary roles to achieve joint goals (Tomasello, 2008). I’ll argue that early emerging socially distributed collaborative cultural skills and practices of our hunter-gatherer ancestors – such as hunting or making and using fire – also represent cogent examples of cognitively opaque cultural skills whose intergenerational transmission requires ostensive 3 communicative relevance-guidance. I’ll speculate that new evidence about early hominid adaptations to cooked food (Wrangham, 2009) suggests that cognitively opaque socially distributed technologies of making, keeping, and using fire may have emerged as early as 1.8m years ago which may have necessitated the coevolution of early forms of ostensive communicative skills of pedagogical knowledge transfer. ______________________________________________________ Hannes Rakoczy (University of Gottingen) How human children and non-human primates represent regularities and rules: the difference made by social norms and theory of mind Much recent research in cognitive development has shown that the core of our adult way of viewing the natural world is already in place early in ontogeny. Even infants conceive of their environment as made up of enduring objects and governed by general regularities that they swiftly infer from limited observations. In this talk, I will first report new comparative work showing far-reaching commonalities in these core cognitive capacities in human children and nonhuman primates. Just like human infants, non-human primates engage in basic forms of intuitive statistical reasoning and inductive learning of regularities. And they do not just reason about regularities and relations of superficial features of objects and events. Rather, much like human children, apes are psychological essentialists: they individuate objects according to their deep, essential properties that are responsible for their identity and that are more informative for predicting and explaining the regularities in the objects’ behavior than surface features. In the second part, I report new developmental work that shows that young children’s inductive learning crucially goes beyond that of non-human primates in not being confined to carving the world at its statistical joints. Human inductive learning is not only about the extraction of descriptive regularities. Rather, from very early in development, children swiftly engage in rational inductive learning of prescriptive rules and norms from limited observations – learning about what one ought to do rather than about what generally happens. In several domains (such as pretend play, games, language use, ownership, morality), young children have been found to infer, understand and actively enforce agent-neutral rules applying to themselves and others alike. Their grasp of such norms is rather sophisticated: they understand, for example, that such norms are context-relative and arbitrary 4 to a greater or lesser degree and that some such rules (so-called constitutive ones) actually bring into existence socially constructed objects and facts; and their reasoning about such social norms is systematically integrated with other forms of social cognition such as Theory of Mind from early on– in contrast, for example, to strong modularist claims about different forms of social cognition. Humans and other primates thus share a basic natural worldview – conceiving of the world as made up of natural objects defined by their essential properties and governed by general regularities. Humans’ core worldview, however, goes far beyond this in including distinctively social and normative categories. ___________________________________________________ Wolfgang Prinz (Max Planck Institute for Human Cognition and Brain Sciences) How mirrors make minds This talk addresses putative mechanisms underlying the social making of human mentality. At the heart of the discussion is the notion of social mirroring which has a long tradition in social philosophy and social anthropology. Taking the existence of mirror-like devices in minds and brains for granted, I argue that social mirroring is a prerequisite for the constitution of mental self and, hence, subjectivity. However, the fact that self and subjectivity are socially created should not be taken to indicate that they are illusory. Social facts are as real as natural facts are: Social theory creates functional reality. ______________________________________________________ Radu Bogdan (Tulane University and University of Bucharest) Intuitive Psychology as Mind Designer There are several ways – evolutionary, developmental and conceptual -- in which it can be plausibly argued that intuitive psychology is a mind designer. On this occasion I propose to focus on a particular developmental argument that starts from the hypothesis that there are three major phases and versions of intuitive psychology in the human ontogeny –- an infantile and implicit sense of other minds, a naïve psychology of early childhood and a commonsense psychology of later childhood and adulthood. The main argument is that at each phase each particular version of intuitive psychology is essentially if not uniquely responsible for specific and novel mental acquisitions.