Given how important it is to successfully interpret facial expressions in our daily interactions with each other, it is intriguing to consider how the audience engages with puppetry, when puppets lack facial expressions. So important are facial expressions considered that the person voicing the parts (tayu) in some puppetry theatres (e.g., the Japanese form of Banraku) is made visible to the audience, so the tayu’s face can be seen demonstrating the facial expressions lacking on the puppets. For other forms of puppetry this is not the case, and yet people find themselves entertained despite a lack of emotional facial expressions. In considering how this is possible, I have drawn from my background in cognitive psychology, and here I will make some suggestions drawing from recent research in neuroscience. One possibility is suggested by the question’s reference to “exaggerated body language”. It might be that the puppets’ caricatured body movements compensate for the lack of facial expression. In fact, just as we are extremely good at facial recognition (e.g., we have a specialized area in the brain called the fusiform face area), we are also talented in reading bodies. For example, studies in neuroscience have indicated that the brain has body-selective areas in the occipitotemporal regions dubbed: the extrastriate body area and the fusiform body area. It has been proposed by researchers (such as Downing & Peelen, 2011), that these areas provide a perceptual framework that “allows other cortical systems to exploit the rich, socially relevant information that is conveyed by the bodyi”. However, even if the body movements do compensate for lack of facial expression, it is likely that a number of factors contribute to our ability to relate to puppets. Two other factors that may lead to successful engagement in enjoying puppet theatre are the brain’s mirror neurons, and our level of motivation and attention. I’ll start by discussing mirror neurons. Mirror neurons are a type of brain cell that have been found to respond both to a person’s action and to their observation of someone else performing the actionii. For example, these cells will fire (become active) when I grab a glass of water and also when I see you grab the glass of water. This means if I watch you pick up the glass, both you and I have these cells firing, even though you alone are performing the action. It is as if my cells “mirror” your actions. The implication is that these cells may help account for our ability to empathize, as not only do they mirror the behaviour, they can also distinguish between intentions. So if you pick up the glass in order to take a drink, as opposed to picking it up in order to clear the table, these neurons also detect thisiii. Furthermore, research with human participants indicates that there is automatic imitation, where reaction times reveal that “healthy adult humans are prone, in an unwilled and unreasoned way, to copy the actions of othersiv”. In a sense, we are also puppets! If we then consider this information in the context of a person watching puppet theatre, we can see how empathy may well occur for the puppet despite its lack of facial expressions. The puppets exaggerated movements are going to be clearly noticed by the audience and their mirror neurons are going to fire in response. If a puppet is seen to fall over, the audience’s mirror neurons fire just as if they had experienced the calamity, leading to sympathy for the fallen. While these mirror neurons can help us understand the audience’s ability to read intentions and empathize, we also need to consider the audience’s own intentions, including their motivation and attention to the puppet theatre. The poet Samuel Taylor Coleridge coined the term “suspension of disbelief” when he wrote of his idea for the Lyrical Ballads: "…my endeavours should be directed to persons and characters supernatural, or at least romantic, yet so as to transfer from our inward nature a human interest and a semblance of truth sufficient to procure for these shadows of imagination that willing suspension of disbelief for the moment, which constitutes poetic faith." In the case of viewing puppet theatre, the audience (especially adults) will be fully aware that the puppets are not real, but by choosing to attend a show they are engaging in the drama, and a willing suspension of disbelief takes place that allows for the puppets to be accepted for real during the performance (even when strings are clearly visible). Hence, the audience is motivated to believe or have poetic faith. This motivation will then direct their attention to the theatrically relevant details, such as the puppets actions, and away from irrelevant details, such as the puppets strings. Inattentional blindness research has shown that when people focus attention on relevant details, irrelevant details are inhibited and often fail to reach awareness v. Hence, clues that might appear to reveal the fiction are likely to be ignored. In summary, I have presented three factors that can help explain why audiences are successfully entertained by puppet theatre, despite exaggerated movements and lack of facial expressions. The first factor is that we have brain areas specialized to recognise bodies and body movements, so the exaggerated movements may compensate for facial expressions. The second factor is that we have mirror neurons that detect actions as if they were our own, including recognising intentions. This may explain our ability to empathize with the puppets. Finally, the third factor is that audience members are motivated to suspend disbelief. This directs their attention to relevant details critical to the story, while ignoring irrelevant details that might otherwise compromise belief. These considerations come from considering the knowledge provided by cognitive psychology, but I’m sure there are many other factors that contribute to this phenomenon, and that other perspectives may shed further light. i Downing, P., & Peelen, M. (2011). The role of occipitotemporal body-selective regions in person perception. Cognitive Neuroscience, 2, 186-226. ii Di Pellegrino, G., Fadiga, L., Fogassi, L., Gallese, V., & Rizzolatti, G. (1992). Understanding motor events: a neurophysiological study. Experimental Brain Research, 91, 176-180. iii Blakeslee, Sandra, (2006). Cells That Read Minds, New York Times, Science, January 10, iv Heyes, C. (2011). Automatic Imitation. Psychological Bulletin, 137, 463-83 v Mack, A., & Rock, I. (1998). Inattentional Blindness. MIT Press.