Semantics: Handout 11 Extension vs. Intension Yılmaz Kılıçaslan December 17, 2009 1 Introduction In the previous lecture, we treated tense and modal operators syncategorematically. When describing the relevant languages (i.e. L2t and L2mt), we did not, for example, define a denotation for the symbol F directly, but only a denotation of the whole expression F in terms of the interpretation of the expression . Could we not assign a denotation separately to F in such a way that the denotation of F could be determined entirely on the basis of the denotation of F and the denotation of ? This would parallel the way in which we gave a denotation for it-is-not-the-case-that in L1E in such a way that the denotation of it-is-not-thecase-that was the result of applying the function denoted by it-is-not-the-case-that to the denotation of . However, a little thought suffices to see that this cannot be done for F. This is simply because the denotation of is a truth value but the truth value of F is independent of the truth value of . In the subsequent section, we will see several cases where the denotation of a natural language phrase cannot be explained in terms of the denotation of its parts. 2 Cases Awaiting Reconciliation with the Principle of Compositionality 2.1 Non-truth functional operators The denotation of at any time depends merely on the denotation (truth value) of at that same time. For this reason, negation is said to be a truth-functional operator.The tense operators, on the other hand, are non-truth-functional. F may be true at a given time whether or not is true at that time; the same is true of formulas of the form P. The following pairs of sentences illustrate this point (examples cited by Thomason 1974, to establish the same point): (1) a. Iceland is covered with a glacier. b. Africa is covered with a glacier. (2) a. Iceland was (once) covered with a glacier. b. Africa was (once) covered with a glacier. Though (1a) and (1b) are both false at the present time, (2a) is now true but (2b) is now false. Obviously, the denotations of F and P at a time t will depend on other things besides the denotation (i.e. truth value) of at t; specifically they will depend on the denotation of at other times. Hence, as long as the semantic interpretation of a sentence is confined to a truth value, as what we have done up to this point, it is not possible to give a compositional treatment to the semantics of tensed sentences. 1 The first philosopher to confront the problem pointed out above was Gottlob Frege (Frege 1893). But, he noticed the problem with modal operators, not tenses. The way he put the problem has been known as Frege’s puzzle about identity. Most systems of logic with an identity predicate contain a law (the so-called Leibnitz Law) that the result of substituting in any formula one name for another name denoting the same individual results in a formula that is true if and only if the original formula was true. Thus to take a natural language example, ‘Morning Star’ and ‘Evening Star’ are two different names that denote the same entity: the planet Venus.1 Therefore, the sentence (3) The Morning Star is not visible now. is true just in case the sentence (4) The Evening Star is not visible now. is true. However, contrast sentence (5) and (6): (5) Necessarily, the Morning Star is the Morning Star. (6) Necessarily, the Morning Star is the Evening Star. Sentence (5) is true because (7) The Morning Star is the Morning Star. is a logically true sentence, an instance of the axiom a = a (for any name a) in predicate logic with identity. However, (6) is not ture according to Frege, since the sentence (8) The Morning Star is the Evening Star. expresses a contingent fact, not a matter of logical necessity. In other words, (7) can be known to be true simply by understanding the meaning of its words. It is a priori (i.e. describes a statement which we can know to be true or false independently of sense experience). The same cannot be said about (8). We have to discover whether it is true by some sort of sensory observation. It is a posteriori (i.e. describes a statement which we can know to be true or false only by sense experience). It follows that in a context created by the necessity operator, , it is not always possible to substitute a name for another name denoting the same entity. Thus, the operator produces another case where the denotation of the whole expression is not strictly a function of the denotation of the parts. (Recall that in the rules given when describing L2t or L2mt, the denotation of did not depend just on the denotation of at that index but on ’s denotation at other indices as well.) 1 But, as Robert Lane (2004) Points out, it was not always known that this is the case. Sailors would refer to the first star to appear at night at certain times during the year as the Evening Star, and the last star to disappear in the morning at other times during the year as the Morning Star, without realizing that the Morning Star and the Evening Star are actually one and the same object. 2 2.2 Opaque Positions Syntactic constructions where co-designative names cannot be substituted for each other while preserving truth values (i.e. without violating Leibnitz’ Law) are called oblique constructions or referentially opaque constructions, as opposed to the more “ordinary” referentially transparent constructions for which Leibnitz’ Law holds. In addition to sentences with modals, we have also the complements of verbs like believe, think, hope, imagine, say etc. that display a referentially opaque behaviour. Consider the following pair of sentences: (9) a. John believes that the Morning Star is the Morning Star. b. John believes that the Morning Star is the Evening Star. Assuming that the invidual named ‘John’ is a perfectly rational person when it comes to principles of identity but is nevertheless somewhat benighted astronomicaly, (9a) might be true while (9b) is false. Clearly, Leibnitz’ Law does not hold in the given context. If that were the case, (9b) would have the same truth value as (9a) from which it differs only by ‘the Morning Star’ substituted for the co-designator ‘the Evening Star’. Another frequently discussed opaque position is the object position of transitive verbs like want, seek, need, etc. Even though there is no single individual whose name could be substituted for the object phrase in this position while preserving truth value, the whole statement can be true. Consider the sentence below: (10) John needs a friend. In one reading at least, the denotation of the whole sentence cannot be explained in terms of the denotation of its parts as far as only an individual can serve as the denotation of an indefinite. This is what linguists would call the non-specific reading of (10), the reading in which there is no particular friend that John needs. Interestingly, the use of case morphology in the direct object position of Turkish sentences seems to closely relate to whether the object phrase is interpreted to be specific or non-specific: (11) a. Oya bir avukat ari-yor. one lawyer seek-prok ‘Oya is seeking a lawyer.’ b. Oya bir avukat-i ari-yor. one lawyer-acc seek-prok ‘Oya is seeking a lawyer.’ Of the two sentences above only (a) (the one with an object carrying case morphology) can receive a specific interpretation, an interpretation where there is a particular lawyer sought by Oya.2 2 Enç (1991) argues that Turkish is a language where specificity is overtly marked in the direct object positions. According to her, direct objects bearing the accusative case suffix, -yI, are specific, whereas those without case morphology are non-specific in this language. Taking this classification as a point of departure, she developes a view of specificity where this notion is equated with Pesetsky’s (1987) notion of D(iscourse)-linking. 3 2.3 Some Adjectives Displaying a Different Semantic Behaviour Even though “referential opacity” is not applicaple where they occur, certain adjectives (and also adverbs) do not allow for a ‘straightforward’ compositional treatment, either. A straightforward approach to the semantics of an adjective is to to take its denotation to be a set, just as the denotation of intransitive verbs and nouns. This seems to work well for either the predicative or attributive position in many cases. Consider the following sentence: (12) Some young minister is talkative. (12) can be said to be true just in case there is an individual that is a member of the set denoted by young and of the set of ministers, and that individual is in the set denoted by talkative. However, the truth conditions for the sentence (13) Some former minister was talkative. cannot be given in the same way. The denotation of the subject cannot be defined as the individual that is both in the set of ministers and in the set of “individuals that are former”. This latter phrase is simply meaningless. In order to give a compositional treatment for the semantics of phrases containing adjectives such as former and alleged, we need to consider as meaning of such adjectives something richer than a mere set of individuals at a certain index. In fact, a similar step is required for all other cases discussed in this section in order to be analyzable in line with the Principle of Compositionality. In what follows, we will look at a distinction proposed to solve similar problems of compositionality. 3 Sense vs. Reference (or Intension vs. Extension) Frege’s solution to problems of the type exemplified above lay in his distinction between between the sense of an expression and its reference or denominatum. The term intension later came to be used for sense, and the term extension for reference. The reference of an expression for Frege corresponded to what we have uniformly termed the denotation of an expression (e.g. a truth value in the case of sentences, a set in the case in the case of adjectives, nouns or verbs, etc.). The sense corresponded to what we might intuitively think of as the “meaning” of the espression as distinct from its denotation. The sense of an expression is supposed to determine what its reference is in any possible state of affairs. Armed with this distinnction, Frege attempted to solve the problem of non-referential contexts (modal contexts, belief contexts, etc.) by saying that expressions of natural language have a kind of “ambiguity” in that sometimes an expression has a “normal” denotation (i.e. the kind of denotation we have been assigning to expressions of our formal languages), but in certain circumstances an expression “denotes” what is ordinarily its sense. The idea is that two sentences having the same denotation, for instance, in isolation (e.g. (7) and (8)) may have different senses when embedded in modal or belief contexts (e.g. in (9a) and (9b)) so that the denotation of the whole sentence can be a function of the “denotations” of its parts. As such expressions “denote” different senses in non-referential contexts, they cannot be substituted for each other in such contexts. 4 4 Formalization of the Sense vs. Reference Distinction The first attempt to formalize the notion of sense was made by Rudolf Carnap (1947). Since the meaning of an utterance is supposed to determine its extension, Carnap suggested that the sense of an expression (for which he substituted the term intension of an expression) is simply a function from possible states of affairs which gives, for any particular state of affairs, the denotation of the expression (which Carnap called the extension of the expression) at that state of affairs. With the advent of Kripke’s semantics for modal logic (taking possible worlds as indices), it became possible for the first time to give an unproblematic formal definition of intension for formalized languages. For our formal languages that employ coordinate semantics, we will want to take an intension as a function from indices to extensions; in this way we will be able treat the “meanings” of indexical expressions uniformly with that of all other expressions. We assume, for simplicity, that indices are just ordered pairs consisting of a possible world and a time (as in L2mt). Individual concepts: A name denotes an individual at each index. Hence, the intension of a name is a function from indices to individuals (intuitively, a function which gives for each context the person denoted by the name at that context). It is traditional to call such an intension an individual concept or the concept of a particular name. For example, if Miss America (or simply m) is a name, then the concept of Miss America is that function which for each index (i.e. for each world and time) gives the person picked out by the name at that world and time. For the actual world these are, for each time, the persons who actually were, are, or will be Miss America, and for different world coordinates, these are persons who would be or would have been Miss America had the world been different in various ways from the way it actually is. Since “ordinary” names (unlike Miss America) denote the same individual at various times and even in different worlds according to some philosophical views on naming, their sense will simply be a constant function, even though it has been a matter of some philosophical dispute whether names should have an intension as well as an extension. Properties (of individuals): A one-place predicate denotes a set of individuals (or equivalently, the characteristic function of a set of individuals) at each index. Thus the intension of a predicate will be the function that gives, for each index, the set (or characteristic function thereof) denoted at that index. Such an intension will be called a property. Thus the property corresponding to the English is asleep can be thought of as the function which gives, for each possible situation, the set of individuals that are asleep in that situation. Propositions: A formula denotes a truth value at each index. Hence the intension of a formula is a function from indices to truth values, and such an intension will be called a proposition. Since a function from any set into {0, 1} is the characteristic function of some subset of that set, a proposition as just defined “characterizes” a set of indices; i.e. a proposition maps all the indices at which a formula is true into 1, and maps all other indices into 0. Thus it characterizes the set of indices at which the formula is true, and on this view it is common to equate a proposition with a set of indices (in the same way as the function denoted by a predicate is equated with the set of individuals that function characterizes). We should also note that variables, as well as constants, are supposed to be provided with intensions. But recall that the extension (i.e. denotation) of a variable is always supplied by 5 the value assignment g and thus does not differ from one index to the next. Thus the intension of a variable will be a constant function on indices, in particular, one that gives at any index whatever g assigns to that variable. PS: The content of this handout is adopted from Dowty et al (1981). References Carnap, R. (1947) Meaning and Necessity. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Dowty D.R., Wall R. E. and Peters S. (1981) Introduction to Montague Semantics. Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Kluwer Academic Publishers. Enç, M. (1991) The semantics of specificity. Linguistic Inquiry 22, 1-26. Lane, R. (2004) Lecture notes in analytic philosophy. In Robert Lane’s Homepage (www.westga.edu/~rlane/analytic/lecture_philLanguage2.html). Pesetsky, D. (1987) Wh-in-situ: movement and unselective binding. The Representation of Indefinites Thomason, R.H. (1974) Introduction. Formal Philosophy: Selected Papers by Richard Montague, R.H. Thomason (ed.). New Haven: Yale University Press, 1-69. 6