Political Structure, Mass Public, and the Generation of Consent: Propositions and Hypotheses Jaechun Kim Abstract The findings of the DP are very robust, but scholars have yet to produce alternate theories that better explain the strong empirical regularities of the DP findings. In an attempt to thoroughly address the DP phenomenon, this paper examine the mechanism by which the foreign policy decisions of elites, domestic political structure, and public consent interact with one another in a democracy. This paper also attempts to assess how such factors as the popular value system, the distinct national mood of the time, and the public’s normative concern affect the “consent-generating” process in a democratic state. In so doing, I attempt to demonstrate that the mechanism whereby elites are constrained by democratic political institutions and the way the consent of the public is created are two elements essential for a more comprehensive understanding of how war and peace decisions are made in democracies. DP(Democratic Peace) scholarship, which sprang from the simple empirical finding that democracies rarely fight one another, has evolved as a “progressive research program” as enunciated by Imre Lakatos. A host of theories intended to explain the DP phenomenon has exceeded its original claim to explain a variety of other phenomena of interest to students of International Relations. This paper is an endeavor to extend a series of “consilience studies” that have been conducted since the inception of DP findings. As with other such studies, this paper attempts to compare and refine the existing explanations of DP (i.e., normative and institutional interpretations), rather than testing or challenging the validity of the DP phenomenon. Key Words: Foreign Policy Making, US Foreign Policy, Democratic Peace, International Security Democratic Peace: The Current State of the Debate Democratic Peace is a “strong probabilistic observation, rather than absolute law” (Russett & Starr, 2000, p. 93) that assesses that democracies rarely fight one another, although they may aggress against non-democratic states. The strong empirical findings of DP scholarship have withstood a host of tests employing different rating schemes for 1 democracy and advanced quantitative techniques.1 In addition to the joint effect of democracy, proponents of DP now claim that, generally speaking, democracies are inherently more peaceful – the monadic proposition that was once rejected even by the most ardent proponents of DP.2 According to Lakatos (1970), scientific theories are embedded in research programs that contain inviolable, “hard-core” assumptions and initial conditions that define their scope. These programs include two other very important elements: “auxiliary” hypotheses and a “positive heuristic” that tell scientists what sorts of additional hypotheses to entertain and how to go about conducting research. A research program is a set of methodological rules telling us what paths of research to avoid and what paths to follow. In the course of research, however, anomalies are bound to appear; predictions of the theory therefore can be falsified. Reactions from scientists are to protect hardcore assumptions by constructing auxiliary ones that can explain anomalies. Yet, any research program can invent such auxiliary assumptions on an ad hoc basis. The key test for the research program is to establish whether or not these auxiliary assumptions are “progressive” – that is, whether their invention leads to the discovery of new facts.3 From this Lakatosian perspective, the so-called DP theories have been helpful in “puzzle solving” in the field of International Relations. The scholarly works employing the theories of DP have enabled us to assess important issues more accurately, or provided 1 According to Russett and Starr (2000), the DP result is robust even using the rating scale of Vanhanen (1984, 1990). Vanhanen’s scale of democracy is one of a handful of longitudinal efforts outside Western academic circles to rate democracy cross-nationally. 2 “Though there are elements of plausibility in the argument that democracies are inherently peaceful, it contains too many holes, and is accompanied by too many exceptions, to be usable as a major theoretical building block” (Russett, 1993, pp 30-31). 3 Lakatos developed this conception to assess development in natural science theories, particularly physics. Thus, we should supplement this test with a “softer,” interpretative version. 2 answers to formerly unsolved puzzles. In this sense, it is certain that the DP meets the standard of a scientific research program as enunciated by Imre Lakatos. As Russett and Starr (pp. 99-102) point out, the basic DP proposition has served as a platform for the development of a variety of theories other than the dyadic, joint effect of democracy. Furthermore, Russett and his colleagues seek to move beyond the DP toward Kantian peace, suggesting that economic interdependence and international organizations – the other two legs of the Kantian tripod – are also crucial, independent factors leading to peace.4 Nonetheless, scholars remain divided on the mechanism whereby democracies attain and retain peace among themselves. In this sense, DP is an empirical observation (or statement) still in search of satisfactory theories and explanations; the dyadic phenomenon of DP remains under-theorized. Structural and Cultural Explanations The central claim of DP scholarship is that it is the very nature of domestic democratic political structure that accounts for “zones of peace” among democracies. Arguably, there are two strands of causal logic to DP (Maoz & Russett, 1993; Layne, 1994). One attributes the absence of war among democracies to democratic institutional constraints: the restraining effects of public opinion, or those of the checks and balances embedded in a democratic state’s domestic political institutions (institutional/structural explanation). Other theories posit that democratic norms and culture – peaceful conflict resolution norms and culture shared by elites (Dixon, 1993, 1994, 1998) or mass public 4 See for example Oneal and Russett (forthcoming in 2001). 3 (Owen, 1995, 1997) in democracies – account for the absence of war between democratic states (normative/cultural explanations). Admittedly, it is not always appropriate to separate institutional and cultural explanations. To some scholars, the definition of institution consists of norms of appropriate behavior and rules defining role expectations. As Ray (1995, p. 37) argues, “the distinction between the cultural and the structural explanation of democratic peace does not seem either stark or crucial, nor does the evidence seem to indicate that one is clearly superior to the other.” The two factors may be complementary; “culture conditions institutions, and institutions shape culture (Russett & Starr, p. 99).”5 Nonetheless, as Maoz and Russett (1993) point out earlier, these two explanations emphasize the two different facets of democracies that may be responsible for the DP phenomenon. The tension between the structural and cultural explanations has its roots in two fundamentally different approaches seen in political science. As Reiter and Stam (1998c, p. 1) argue, “the structural model is based on fundamentally economic, rationalist assumptions about the nature of politics, and the normative model is based on fundamentally sociological and social psychological assumptions.” Thus, the structural explanation focuses on the interaction between self-interested rational actors and the democratic political institutions. The motivation to stay in power affects the elites’ foreign policy decisions, whereas the public merely wants to avoid the costs incurred by war. From this perspective institutions are important in strategic context, imposing 5 To a certain extent, this dichotomous approach to explain DP has hampered the development of sound theories. First, as Russett and Starr (2000) point out, a contending approach tends to obscure interactive and overlapping dynamics of culture and institution that lead to peace among democracies. In fact, several studies have attempted to synthesize these two approaches. Second, as Most and Starr (1989) and Russett and Starr (2000) suggest, each explanation can be relevant in different contexts. 4 constraints on self-interested behavior, whereas institutions in normative theories not only constrain but also constitute the behavior and preferences of political actors.6 At an earlier stage in the development of DP theories, it appeared as if the institutional/structural explanations had been rejected in favor of normative/cultural explanations on the grounds that democracies historically have been just as war-prone as non-democracies (Layne, 1994). The previous consensus was that an institutional constraint argument in its most straightforward form can only explain the monadic level phenomenon – democracies are inherently more peaceful than non-democracies.7 Although theoretically rich and deductively well constructed, this monadic-level explanation had not been empirically supported by many scholarly works.8 As a result, the explanations based on democratic norms and culture came to bear much of the burden of proof for the DP. Several scholars (Bueno de Mesquita & Lalman, 1992; Owen, 1995; Ray, 1995; Rousseau et al., 1996) attempted to synthesize (wittingly or unwittingly) these two groups of arguments in explaining DP. But the logic of their arguments tends to be tilted in favor of democratic norms and culture.9 A near-consensus emerged that the dyadic phenomenon of DP can only be confirmed by “shared” norms or culture in paired 6 The normative explanations of DP have two different theoretical origins. One is ideological (Owen, 1997; Dixon, 1994) and the other is social/constructivist (Starr, 1997; Risse-Kappen, 1995). See also Reiter and Stam (1998c). 7 Bueno de Mesquita and his colleagues, in a recent article to American Political Science Review, claim that institutional-constraint argument in its most basic form can explain dyadic phenomena of democratic peace (Bueno de Mesquita et al., 1999a). 8 However, several scholars have maintained that democracies in general are more peaceful than nondemocracies. See Rummel (1997) and Benoit (1996). 9 Bueno de Mesquita and Lalman (1992) seem to play down cultural explanations in favor of structural ones, but in fact their logic of explanation implicitly hinges on “shared knowledge” of democratic elites that each will be constrained to disdain the overt use of military force. More recent works of Bueno de Mesquita and his colleagues emphasize the aspect that leaders in democracies are motivated to avoid the possibility of electoral punishments (Bueno de Mesquita et al., 1995; 1997; 1999a; 1999b) 5 democracies. For example, upon reviewing the research on the DP proposition, Chan concluded that “normative explanations of the democratic peace have been shown to be more persuasive than structural explanations” and that “normative explanations have faired better in research” (Chan, 1997, pp. 77-78). Maoz and Russett (1993) also concluded that the normative argument is superior in its explanatory and predictive capacity to the institutional one. Although theoretical bases for the existing theories of DP premised on normative explanations may be relatively well developed, they are not entirely self-evident; dyadic phenomenon of DP still lacks coherent explanations. To demonstrate that existing DP theories leave a lot to be desired, I will evaluate two of the most sophisticated theoretical works in DP scholarship: Owen’s normative - institutional synthesis (1995) and Risse-Kappen’s constructivist explanation (1995). Owen’s Normative - Institutional Synthesis In “How Liberalism Produces Democratic Peace,” Owen (1995) distinguishes himself from his predecessors in that: (a) he makes an explicit attempt to synthesize the institutional and normative arguments and (b) he takes into account the importance of perceptions. Owen defines a liberal democracy as a state “where liberalism is the dominant ideology and citizens have leverage over war decisions.” However, what matters for Owen is not how scholars define democracy, but rather how the populace understands the character of other regimes. That is, the all-important criterion is whether one “liberal” country recognizes its rival as a kindred spirit. If so, she will be disposed to behave decently. If not, however, all bets are off. Such subjectivity helps to explain some of the “close calls,” including the Spanish-American War of 1898. Although Spain had 6 universal male suffrage, Americans did not regard it as a liberal country like their own. Likewise, Germany under Wilhelmine II had some claim to rank among world democracies, but few West Europeans viewed her that way.10 Although Owen’s institutional-normative synthesis refined the causal logic of the DP, it is not without its shortcomings. First, he seems to place too much confidence in the mass public of liberal democracy. He argues that the mass public in a liberal democracy always shares an ideological affinity toward other liberal democracies, whereas elites in a liberal democracy can be illiberal, thereby becoming belligerent with other liberal democracies. But he fails to explain this theoretical asymmetry; if elites do not have an ideological predilection toward other democracies, why should we expect to see the mass public embrace it? He argues that: “Liberal constituents will not change their assessment of foreign states unless those states change their institutions . . . and that statesmen will be constrained (by democratic institutions) to follow liberal policy” (pp. 103-104, emphasis added). However, there have been several instances in which a liberal public’s perception of another country was determined not so much by the other country’s institutional change as by statesmen’s manipulations of the image. As Oren (1995) argues, before World War I, some U.S. social scientists perceived Germany as a member of a select group of the most progressive polities. It was following 1917 – after U.S. statesmen, notably Woodrow Wilson, and other elite groups changed their view of Germany – that the U.S. public started to perceive her as a non-democratic regime. 10 The problem is that such differences of perception do persist in the contemporary era. The Palestinian National Authority reckons itself as democratic, but Israelis may think otherwise. Israel reckons itself as democratic, but Palestinians under occupation scoff. Some Americans still do not view Asian democracies such as Japan, South Korea, Taiwan, and Singapore as fully “liberal” democracies. 7 German institutions per se had not changed as much as the subjective coding rules of U.S. observers. This suggests that the mass public’s perceptions of enemy or friend can be manipulated by elites in democracy according to the need – whether that need is derived from international systemic pressures or from rational self-interests rooted in domestic politics.11 As Owen (p. 103) himself points out, “if (the above) hypothesis is not borne out, the democratic peace is illusory, because power politics or some other force would actually be determining what label liberals attached to foreign states.” Risse-Kappen’s Constructivist Argument Owen’s explanation, like those of his predecessors, fails to specify the mechanism whereby one democracy develops positive perceptions of other democracies, but not of non-democracies.12 How and why do democracies come to know that other democracies are equally peaceful and can, therefore, be trusted? Constructivism is well suited to explain the processes that lead to the development of such positive identifications.13 After all, “shared” norms and culture presuppose a prior experience of interaction and learning, areas that constructivists take seriously. Risse-Kappen argues: Enmity as well as friendship in the international system neither result from some inherent features of the international distribution of power, as realists would assume, nor from the domestic structures of states as such, as liberals argue. Rather, it is socially constructed . . . The democratic peace . . . results from a rule 11 There is a body of public opinion literature describing the public as merely the malleable target of public relations efforts by the decision-making elites. According to this literature, the actual direction of causality always runs from policy makers to the public rather than vice versa. See Ginsburg (1988) and Margolis and Mauser (1989). However, there is an apparent limit to the degree to which elites in democracies can manipulate the mass public’s perceptions. I will come back to this point in the latter part of this chapter. 12 Like other DP scholars, Owen simply assumes that a liberal populace will trust states they consider liberal and mistrust those they consider illiberal (p. 103). 13 For more of constructivist approach to DP, see Peceny (1997). 8 learned through the processes of interaction, namely to infer aggressiveness or peacefulness from the degree of violence inherent in the domestic political structure of one’s opponent (p. 503). There is little doubt that peacefulness as well as enmity can be learned through international interactions. But Risse-Kappen’s constructivist explanation is not entirely convincing as to “why democracies create their enemies and their friends – them and us – by inferring either aggressive or defensive motives (only) from the domestic structures of their counterparts” (p. 506). That is, why is it that domestic political orders and norms shape the identities of actors in the international realm? Why not economic orders such as capitalism? Why not geographic concepts such as West vs. East, North vs. South? Why not gender and race? His answer is that “values and norms pertaining to questions of governance are likely to shape identities in the realm of the political – be it domestic or international” (pp. 506-507). But this indeed is a big assumption because it places domestic political structure in an ontologically superior position in explaining states’ identity formation process via international interaction. What factors dominate states’ identities in a given area of interaction needs to be examined through empirical investigation. Interaction at the systemic level does change state identities and interests, but why does this identity formation process have to be constrained mainly by the perceived image of states’ domestic political structures? It is certain that the interaction of states and identity formation does not occur in a vacuum; states are not socialized into new preferences instantaneously. For this reason, we need to have a more rigorous theory of static preference before a theory of dynamic interaction (Moravcsik, 1996). There is little doubt that the domestic political structure of opposing states – i.e., whether an opposing state is a democracy or autocracy – matters greatly to a 9 democracy.14 But it is not entirely convincing that preferences (that democracies bring to a given area of interaction) and identities (produced and reproduced via international interaction) are determined predominantly by how the state-society relationship is structured in other countries. Second-level variables other than “domestic political structure,” such as ethnicity, language, and religion, appear to be equally important in determining the enmity and friendship in some inter-state interactions. It is also not clear why the process of socialization invariably ensues from the bottom up. Risse-Kappen believes that states externalize the internal behavioral norms in their interactions with other democracies.15 But there is no a priori theoretical rationale to preclude the possibility that the causal direction may actually be the reverse, that is, the possibility that the states internalize the external norm – be it peaceful or hostile. In fact, Wendt’s constructivist position is that peaceful inter-state interactions and practices can lead states to significant redefinitions of interests and preferences. Wendt (1999) argues that egoistic, self-regarding preferences of states are the product of historically contingent ideas and interactions, which can be transcended by engaging in new practices. Thus, if states peacefully interact with one another and instantiate new ideational structures, chances are that more states will be “socialized” into adopting more peaceful and “other-regarding” norms.16 If the states only externalize internal norms, as opposed to internalizing external 14 Thus, it will be difficult for a democracy to create an enemy image of other democracies. The learning and evolutionary processes are not limited to the interactions among democracies. In explaining why the evolutionary processes and learning occur only among democracies, Risse-Kappen defaults to institutional constraint issues, such as the publicity of decision making and the interdependence arguments. Nonetheless, there remains the possibility that free trade may bring about democracy as well as wealth, which in turn may produce peace (Free Trade Wealth and Democracy Peace). The possibility of this is called the problem of “omitted variable” and “spurious relation” (Gates et al., 1996). For more on the effects of trade on peace, see Oneal et al. (1996). Yet, Oneal and Russett (1997) proved that democracy has pacifying effects even after controlling for the trade effect. 16 Nonetheless, although the conflict may inhibit democracy, it is harder to imagine that peace in any one 15 10 norms, and if socialization comes mainly from the bottom up, rather than from the top down, it is indeed unfortunate, because democracies and perceived non-democracies (or illiberal democracies for that matter) would seldom be capable of building up trust and a shared norm of non-aggression through practice and interaction. Implications of Covert War Findings to the Current State of the Debate The review of both Owen and Risse-Kappen’s works suggests that the existing theories based on normative interpretations fail to provide compelling explanations of the DP phenomenon. Both explanations pay insufficient attention to the mechanism by which decision makers are constrained by democratic political institutions and a dynamic “consent-generation” process in a democratic state. Forsythe (1992) claims that the U.S. has resorted to the covert use of force against elected, arguably democratic governments in Iran (1953), Guatemala (1954), Indonesia (1958), Brazil (1960s), Chile (1973), and Nicaragua (1980s). It seems this finding further undermines the elites’ norm or culturebased explanations of the DP. A series of covert operations, such as massive interference in democratic political processes, the use of political propaganda, economic destabilization programs, and instigation of terrorism, are not the kinds of acts that normative theory would expect the elites in democracies to engage in against other democratically elected governments. I now follow with an assessment of the theoretical implications of this covert war finding for the DP. Two separate questions generate from the covert war findings that are of relevance to DP scholarship. First, why did one democracy (the U.S.) resort to the dyad can promote democratic norms and institutions. I owe this point to Russett. 11 covert use of force, as with overt use of force, in destabilizing or overthrowing other democratically elected governments? How does one explain a sub-war level of violence rather than a peaceful resolution of conflict in this paring – i.e., why something rather than nothing? But it seems that sophisticated DP theories have answers to such questions. Democracy is a continuous rather than a dichotomous variable; states are democratic to lesser or greater degrees. In this sense, it is not appropriate to classify states into two distinct categories: democracies and non-democracies. Sophisticated DP theories claim that only well established democracies do not fight against one another. That is, such theories predict that well established democracies will virtually never fight each other, whereas well established democracies and extremely autocratic states are most likely to make war against each other (a difference effect). Similarly, a highly democratic state and a state near the middle of the democratic/autocratic spectrum might be considerably more likely to enter into war.17 Thus, it can come as no surprise that a well established democracy (such as the U.S.) would use mid-level covert force, as with overt force, against states that fall in the middle of the democracy/autocracy spectrum. According to the ratings of a Polity98 dataset, among the six states in Forsythe’s cases, only Chile (1972) and Brazil (1960) fared well in terms of the democracy/autocracy scale; the other four states could hardly qualify as established democracies at the time of U.S. covert intervention.18 Compared to Polity98, Vanhanen’s rating gives relatively favorable scores to Nicaragua from 1984 to 1989. But one can still notice differences between the The “difference effect” of this dyad may be less than that of dyads of fully democratic and autocratic states, but still the difference remains substantial. All of these statements are supported empirically (see Oneal & Russett, 1998). 18 The Dominican Republic under the rule of Bosch (1963) also came very close to meeting the objective standards required for liberal democracy. 17 12 democracy scores for the target countries of the U.S. covert actions and those for the well-established Western democracies such as the U.S., France, and Canada.19 Nonetheless, several target states fared better than Spain right before the outbreak of the Spanish-American War (see Table 1). Table 1 Democracy Scores for Selected States According to Polity98 and Vanhanen’s Poliarchy Dataset Country Year Polity98 DEMOC Iran Guatemala Indonesia Brazil Dominican Republic Chile Nicaragua U.S.A. France Canada Spain 1952 1953 1957 1960 1963 1972 1984 1995 1995 1995 1896-1898 3 4 2 6 8 6 1 10 10 10 6 AUTOC 4 2 3 0 0 0 2 0 0 0 2 Vanhanen’s Index of Democracy 0.53 5.45 8.76 9.99 13.08 19.78 11.45 23.41 33.77 27.22 1.18 In short, these findings do not contradict dyadic phenomena of democratic peace postulates. Sophisticated DP theories have no difficulty in dismissing these covert war findings on definitional grounds – the target countries were not genuine, liberal democracies and the incidents failed to produce sufficient battle deaths to qualify as inter- 19 The Polity98 project extends Polity III through 1998 and contains corrections to the Polity III data. Ted Gurr and Keith Jaggers are the principle investigators. See Jaggers and Gurr (1995) for the authoritative description of Polity III. The data were downloaded from www.bsos.umd.edu/cidcm/polity/. Most of the empirical DP works have adopted the democracy ratings of Polity III. Vanhanen’s index of democracy was retrieved from the Poliarchy dataset, compiled by Tatu Vanhanen, that covers 187 countries over the period 1810 to 1998. The current version of the dataset is 1.2 and available for downloading at www.svt.ntnu.no/iss/data/vanhanen/. 13 state wars.20 The second question that arises from the covert war findings is: Why covert use of force instead of open war? Forsythe (1992) is relatively quiet about the implications of his findings to DP theory and dismisses the matter on the grounds that the target nations did not qualify as mature liberal democracies. Given that the targets were not “real” democracies and the covert engagements did not qualify as inter-state wars, both in terms of lives and financial resources expended, the question still stands: Why have the democracies fought secret wars? I believe more robust DP theories can help us solve this puzzle.21 One plausible answer to this question revolves around the possibility that using covert actions may allow elites in democracies to evade the constraints inherent in democratic political institutions. Propositions: Political Structure, Mass Public, and the Generation of Consent The following propositions constitute key assumptions for the theoretical frameworks through which we can analyze the decisions related to using force abroad. Using this framework, we can establish several hypotheses that will have testable implications. PROPOSITION 1. An institutional mechanism whereby the public can constrain the elite’s behavior exists in democracies. PROPOSITION 2. The initial (default) preference of the public is “no war” (rational selfinterest). 20 However, it should be noted that target states such as Chile had a fairly long tradition of liberal democracy. With regard to the response that covert action does not qualify as inter-state war, Sorenson (1992, p. 405) pointed out, “As the events in Central American in the 1980s show, covert involvement with economic and military and ‘expert’ support for opposition forces can develop to a point where the distinction between such activities and open war becomes fairly academic.” Most DP researchers have adopted the definition of “interstate war” devised by the Correlates of War project, which stipulates that only military conflict between independent states producing at least 1,000 battle deaths (i.e., the deaths of soldiers) will count as an interstate war. 21 As discussed earlier, strong theories of DP have helped us understand phenomena other than DP. 14 PROPOSITION 3. Perceptions of the public, however, can be manipulated via news/propaganda. First, I propose that elites in democracies are institutionally constrained by the public. In democracies, political institutions provide the mechanism whereby the public sets the parameters within which the decision-making elites should act. Elites may influence the public over the short run, but in the long run, elites must operate within the parameters set by the public or risk being replaced by new elites. This is the most important trait that distinguishes democracies from non-democracies. Therefore, foreign policy decisions of democracies reflect in general the will of the public. The extent to which the public affects particular foreign policy decisions hinges on a number of intervening variables.22 Nonetheless, such salient foreign policy issues as the war and peace decisions cannot be made without the contemporaneous consent of the public in democracies. Some (e.g., Morgan & Schweback, 1992) argue that the public’s ability to constrain elites is not confined to democracies; even elites in autocracies cannot forego the will of the public in waging war.23 Christopher Layne (1994) argues that institutional constraint is associated with, but not exclusive to, democracies. In contrast to these claims, I posit that the most important characteristics that distinguish democratic from other forms of regimes are the domestic political institutions that aggregate the preferences of the society, namely the mass public. 22 These intervening variables will include: (1) the salience of the issue, (2) the stage of policy development, (3) the beliefs of elites and the public regarding the role of the public in foreign policy making process, (4) the quality of decision makers’ leadership and the public’s political skills, and (5) the availability of information. 23 Morgan and Schweback (1992) differentiate “constrained” and “unconstrained” democracies and argue that “democracies, whether constrained or not, have not fought one another but constrained democracies and constrained non-democracies have in fact fought 3 wars. This is consistent with the political culture argument.” However, their distinction between constrained and unconstrained democracies is inappropriate 15 Second, I assume that the mass public by default is not overly enthusiastic about war-making efforts by the elites. After all, it is their money and blood that are at stake when their country becomes embroiled in any war. Studies (Mueller, 1973, 1994) have shown that individuals in a democracy are extremely sensitive to casualties. Simply put, people prefer life to death, and democratic institutions provide mechanisms that work to constrain leaders in order to ensure this basic desire. For reasons specified in Propositions 1 and 2, democracies usually fight less costly and shorter wars (Siverson, 1995; Bennet & Stam, 1998b) and are in general more likely to win the wars they initiate (Lake, 1992; Reiter & Stam, 1998a) than non-democracies. Although the general public by default prefers peace to war, there are many cases in which this initial consideration or the preference of the mass public is overshadowed by other concerns, such as deep-rooted enmity, nationalism, ethnicity, religion, or morality. In some cases, the mass public may more enthusiastically demand war than the elites. For example, the American public at the turn of the 20th century called for open warfare against Spain above and beyond the governing elites before the outbreak of the Spanish-American War. In such cases, the democratic system of governance may discourage the peaceful resolution of conflicts. In other cases, however, the public may be reluctant to enter into war whereas elites may think that making war is inevitable and even desirable for the national interest. The institutional constraint argument of early liberals in its straightforward form predicts that the opinions of the mass public will prevail in such cases. But this has not always happened. Elites in democracies may try to rally the mass public to induce contemporary consent for their war-making efforts. In order to do so, the creation of an enemy image because elites in a democracy by definition are constrained. 16 may be necessary. As Oren (1995) argues, American elites manipulated the image of Germany in order to mobilize the mass public’s support for war against Germany. Before the Wilson administration launched a large-scale propaganda campaign, the American public in general was isolationist and saw no reason to become involved in a hitherto European war. To initiate Operation Desert Storm, the Bush administration took great pains to surmount the constraints initially imposed by Congress and the mass public by creating an enemy image of Saddam Hussein. 24 Thus, my third proposition is that the perceptions, if not the preferences, of the mass public in democracies can be manipulated by elites via news and propaganda. Naturally, there is an obvious limit to the degree to which elites in democracies can manipulate the perceptions of the public. For example, it would be extremely difficult, if not impossible, for contemporary American elites to conjure up enemy images of such states as Canada and Britain. The U.S., Britain, and Canada have long enjoyed close ties and share the same domestic political structure (i.e., liberal democracy), language, ethnic affinity, and religion – critical referents in determining between national enmity and friendship. Value, Mood, and the Creation of Consent In contrast to the elite’s norm-based explanations of DP, Owen ascribes more 24 A key aspect of the whole Gulf War was how the Bush administration prepared the American public to accept its decision. One method was to convince the American people that the Kuwaitis were the victims of horrendous atrocities and Sadam Hussein was “another Hitler.” The Washington-based Hill and Knowlton (H&K) public relations firm played a major role in this effort. H&K was paid $5.6 million to improve Kuwait’s image in the U.S. after the Iraqi invasion in August l990. President Bush himself declared many times in public that Hussein was “another Hitler.” In October 1990, President Bush said to a group of reporters: “Good God, this is the 1990s and you see this man (Hussein) starving out small embassies . . . There’s a parallel between what Hitler did to Poland and what Saddam Hussein has done to Kuwait.” See Vancouver Sun, October 23, 1990. Initially, U.S. public opinion was not enthusiastic about entering into war against Iraq (Bennett & Paletz, 1994). 17 explanatory power to the mass public than to the elites in his interpretation of DP (Owen, 1995, 1997). Nonetheless, Owen’s ideological distinction of liberal/illiberal mass public does not seem to provide an adequate yardstick to gauge war-proneness of the mass public, and hence to explain DP. Most of all, Owen’s argument fails to appreciate one very important point: Liberalism as a mass belief system is not monolithic. For example, liberalism and nationalism are not flatly contradictory concepts and accommodation between the two is possible; in fact, liberalism and nationalism have often been intimately linked to one another (Braumoeller, 1997, pp. 381-382). As far as beliefs about legitimacy of the use of force are concerned, the type of liberalism that has arisen in the Soviet successor states is more likely to create opportunities for more conflicts rather than inducing peace among these states (Braumoeller, 1997). Like the 19th century nationalist liberals, the raison d’être of the liberals in the former Soviet states is national selfdetermination. Thus, the liberals in these states are among those most ready to die – and kill, if necessary – for their nation’s independence (Braumoeller, pp. 382-83). Snyder and Ballentine (1996) also point out the sudden spread of democratic and liberal ideas in the Soviet successor states might facilitate elites’ attempt at intense nationalist mythmaking.25 Theoretical inadequacy of the Liberal/Nonliberal distinction forces Owen to place greater emphasis on “perception.” This in turn has limited the explanatory scope of the original DP theory’s claim, because it is not the democracy per se but the perception that ipso facto contributes to peace among states. This line of argument may also slide into 25 Mansfield and Snyder (1995) argue that immature democracies may grow more likely to go to war, although DP may exist between mature, stable democracies. One of the reasons is that, in nascent democracies, elite groups often use appeals to nationalism as they compete for domestic power. 18 tautology: “Relations between democratic states are peaceful because they are informed by a common perception that democracies are peaceful” (Gates et al., 1996, p. 3). Predominant values held by public provides an important clue to the shaping of popular preferences, because responses to policy-relevant information depend on a relatively stable core of values and beliefs that constrain the manner in which information is interpreted.26 But instead of Liberalism as the core mass value system, PostMaterialist/Materialist (or Nationalist) value categories might provide us with more convincing clues to understanding the popular preference concerning war and peace decisions. According to Inglehart (1977, 1990), conditions of security – particularly levels of economic and physical security – during pre-adult socialization are the primary determinant of the values that shape the central aspect of an individual’s outlook on life. Thus, most individuals who grew up amidst economic and physical insecurity develop Materialist values that reflect their early life concerns with satisfying lower-order needs (material well-being and physical security), whereas those who grew up in the affluent, physically secure era are able to progress to higher-order needs (quality of life) that are the basis for Post-Materialist (PM) values. As a result of intergenerational population replacement, Inglehart (1977, 1990, 1994, 2000) argues that the predominant values of Western publics have been shifting from Materialist to Post-Materialist.27 World Values Converse’s classic work on public belief systems (1964) found that the value systems of mass publics show surprisingly little coherent structure. But, by definition, values differ from attitudes in being more general, central, and pervasive; less situation-bound; and more resistant to modification (Robinson & Shaver, 1969, p. 410). Thus, knowledge of the public’s predominant values makes it possible to predict a much broader array of specific public attitudes. 27 The new generation in these countries is distinguished from the old one by two critical, distinctive cohort experiences: “formative affluence” and “formative physical security” (e.g., absence of total war experiences) (Inglehart, 1977, pp. 87-88). Inglehart and Abramson (1994) demonstrate, by a time series analysis, that there has been a statistically significant intergenerational shift toward Post-Materialist values in eight West European countries over last 2 decades. 26 19 Surveys indicate that this value shift occurs in any society that has experienced sufficient economic growth in recent decades resulting in significantly more secure pre-adult experiences for younger birth cohorts compared to those of older cohorts.28 To wage a war, the governing elites in democracies need to procure contemporary consent from the mass public (Reiter & Stam, 2001). The nation-states have often based their claims to legitimacy primarily on their functions in protecting their subjects from foreign states. Throughout history, evoking real or imagined threats to national security and appealing to nationalism have been perennially relied on by governing elites to rally public support for war. History also shows that nationalism as a core mass value system has interfered with the peaceful resolution of inter-state conflicts. But considerations accorded to national defense and nationalist sentiment weigh less heavily among the priorities of Post-Materialist values than of Materialist values (Inglehart, 1977, p. 334). “A further shift toward Post-Materialist values would” entail “a further weakening of support” for nationalism.29 Thus, the prevalence of PM values may make it difficult for the elites in democracies to provoke nationalistic sentiment in attempts to garner the mass public’s consent to go along with a war decision. Elites can “no longer rely on appeals to nationalism and patriotism as much as in the past” (Inglehart, 1977, p. 16). 28 This confirms that societies that have experienced rapid economic growth have much larger intergenerational differences than societies with little or no economic growth (Inglehart & Abramson, 1994). The World Values Survey is a worldwide investigation of sociocultural and political change. It has carried out representative national surveys of the basic values and beliefs of publics in more than 65 societies on all six inhabited continents (Inglehart, 2000). Inglehart operationalizes the concepts of Materialist and Post-Materialist values by asking respondents to choose between various policy goals designed to measure their positions on “need hierarchy.” 29 With an intergenerational shift toward Post-Materialist values, “one of the key symbols of nationalism may have lost much of its potency” (Inglehart, 1977, p. 70). 20 Distinct public mood of the time is another important factor affecting popular preference regarding the war and peace decision.30 For instance, Klingberg (1979, p. 38) divided U.S. foreign policy history into four “extrovert” and four “introvert” phases.31 Introvert phases are characterized by a public reluctance to expand American political and military concerns beyond its own borders, whereas during extrovert phases the public is much more supportive of expansion and extraterritorial political/military involvement. According to Holmes (1985, p. 25), the conclusion of Vietnam marked the beginning of a new introvert phase in the U.S. During such introvert phases, elites in democracies are expected to have difficulty mobilizing public support for military adventures abroad. American presidents who have not adjusted to the change in mood have found themselves in a losing position, like that faced by Woodrow Wilson over the League of Nations and LBJ over Vietnam. Conversely, FDR, during the introvert 1930s, conformed to the public mood on foreign policy to domestic acclaim. Nonetheless, political systems will not automatically adopt foreign policies that reflect the public’s values/moods. Whether or not the public’s preferences will prevail depends on at least two other factors: (a) the political skills of the elites and public, and (b) the state’s institutional structure. The expansion of education, technological innovations, and the development of mass communications seemed to have enhanced the mass public’s “political skills” to influence the making of foreign as well as domestic Holmes (1985, p.2) argues: “Public mood is a dominant force in American foreign policy and limits governmental actions.” Holmes (1985) and Klingberg (1979, 1983) use the term “mood” to explain the generation-long societal swings. This use of “mood” differs from that of Almond (1950), whose use of the term refers to sudden shifts of interest and preferences on the part of the public. 31 Introvert (1776-1798, 1824-1844, 1871-1891, 1919-1940) and Extrovert (1798-1824, 1844-1871, 18911919, 1940-). Every major war in which the U.S. has become involved has started during an extrovert phase. 30 21 policy.32 Improved political skills enable the mass public to engage in elite-challenging (as opposed to elite-directed) participation in the government’s decision-making process; they strengthen the public’s constraints on elites. We should also note that elites in democracies are not just passive registers of the mass public’s preferences. Quality of leadership plays a big part in inducing the mass public to follow a government’s policy initiatives. Hypotheses The theoretical discussion up to this point leads to the development of the following four preliminary hypotheses that we can test in later studies concerning decisions about war and peace. H1. The public’s identification of an opposing state as a democracy significantly impedes the generation of public consent in support of military action. Previous research has shown that the mass public in one democracy may oppose entering into war against another democracy because of the normative constraints that joint democracy generates. For example, Owen’s case studies (1997) suggest that the mass public identifying the opposing state as a democracy undermines the elites’ effort to generate a consensus for war. From the perspective of “rational choice” theory, the peaceful resolution of conflict with other democracies via international courts or negotiations is less costly to the mass public in democracies. Both the mass public’s normative concerns and rational self-interests influence the consent-generating process; the mass public in a democracy expects and prefers peaceful conflict resolution with other 32 Rising levels of education and the expansion of mass communications will result in an increase in the proportion of populations possessing the skills to cope with politics on a national scale. 22 democracies because of both normative concerns and rational self-interests. The so-called “Joint Democracy” effect is one of the crucial factors affecting the consent generation process on the part of the mass public in a democracy. H2. The predominant value of the mass public or the distinct mood of the time shapes the configuration of the public’s initial preference regarding the overt use of military force abroad. In democratic states where an increasingly large proportion of the public has come to possess PM values, it would be difficult for the elites to appeal to such values as nationalism and patriotism and to mobilize the mass public to enter into war. However, in democratic states where the public’s primary value resembles that of 19th century (liberal) nationalism, it might be relatively easy for the elites to appeal to nationalism and to garner public consent for making war.33 Braumoeller (1997) shows that the DP is particularly vulnerable to national issues in the Soviet successor states. Identification of the opposing state as a democracy undermines the elites’ efforts to create consent for war (H1). But in states where the mass public’s values are predominantly nationalistic, elites may find it relatively easy to elicit the mass public’s consent for war against other democracies, particularly when the issue at stake is susceptible to nationalistic sentiment. From the perspective of the “institutional-consent model,” the predominant value system of the mass public or the distinct mood of the time – as a crucial force affecting the public’s consent-generation process – seems to provide basic clues to understanding under what conditions and when the public yields the contemporary consent for the use of force. Likewise, the mobilization of the public’s consent for the use of force may be easier during extrovert phases than during introvert phases. 33 23 H3. A free press and the development of mass communications restrict the range of information that elites (elected or otherwise) may use to manipulate the public.34 The expansion of communication networks has been made possible by technological innovation. The result has been to make information networks international, and to communicate information rapidly from anywhere in the world. Thus, the free press and the development of communication technologies will restrict the range of information that elites may want to use in an attempt to manipulate the perception of the mass public. Because of such factors as the change in the mass public’s value system, the much improved political savvy of the mass public, and the development of technology and mass communications, I suspect that the nature of DP in the latter half of the 20th century is different from that of DP before WWII to a certain extent.35 With the free flow of information, democracies may have a better chance of identifying fellow democracies.36 H4. If the consent for the open use of military force cannot be generated, elites may use covert action to circumvent the constraints imposed by domestic political institutions. If the elites in democracy somehow succeed in mobilizing the public’s support for the overt use of military force, democratic states can proceed to wage war with opposing states. Thus, the necessary conditions for the initiation of war in democracies are as follows: (a) elites desire to raise a war and (b) the mass public is willing to go along with the elites’ initiative.37 If it is difficult for the elites to garner public consent for the overt 34 For the relationship between the role of a free press and DP, see Van Belle (1997). However, it is hard to make much of an empirical distinction between the strength of DP in the first half of the 20th century and that in the second half. 36 If war were to break out among democracies in 21 st century, “misperception” would no longer be a legitimate excuse for DP theories. 37 In some cases, the mass public may demand war whereas the elites may prefer a peaceful conflict resolution. If the initial preference of the mass public is “war,” this itself may constitute the necessary condition for the initiation of war in democracies. 35 24 use of brute force, elites in democracies may opt to use covert actions to skirt domestic opposition.38 Of course, not every state – or democracy for that matter – is able to engage in covert action. The number of states with covert action capacity is expected to be limited. 38 25 Bibliography Almond, Gabriel. 1950. The American People and Foreign Policy. New York, NY: Hartcourt, Brace. Bennet, Scott, and Allan C. Stam. 1996. “The Duration of Interstate Wars, 1816-1985.” American Political Science Review 90: 239-57. Bennett, Lance W., and David L. Paletz. 1994. Taken by Storm: The Media, Public Opinion, and U.S. Foreign Policy in the Gulf War. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press. Benoit, Kenneth. 1996. “Democracies Really Are More Pacific (in General).” Journal of Conflict Resolution 40: 636-657. Bosch, Juan. 1968. Pentagonism: A Substitute for Imperialism. Translated by Helen R. Lane. New York, NY: Grove Press. Braumoeller, Bear F. 1997. “Deadly Doves: Liberal Nationalism and the Democratic Peace in the Soviet Successor States.” International Studies Quarterly 41: 375-402. Bueno de Mesquita, Bruce, and David Lalman. 1992. War and Reason. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Bueno de Mesquita, Bruce, and Randolph Siverson. 1995. “War and the Survival of Political Leaders: A Comparative Study of Regime Types and Political Accountability.” The American Political Science Review 89: 841-55 Bueno de Mesquita, Bruce, James Morrow, Randolph Siverson, and Alastair Smith. 1999b. “Policy Failure and Political Survival: The Contribution of Political Institutions.” The Journal of Conflict Resolution 43: 147-61. Bueno de Mesquita, Bruce, James Morrow, Ethan Zorick. 1997. “Capabilities, Perception, and Escalation.” The American Political Science Review 91: 15-27. Chan, Steve. 1997. “In Search of Democratic Peace: Problems and Promise.” Mershon International Studies Review 41: 59-91. Dixon, William, 1994. “Democracy and the Peaceful Settlement of International Conflict.” American Political Science Review 88: 14-32. Forsythe, David P. 1992. “Democracy, War, and Covert Action.” Journal of Peace Research 29: 385-395. 26 Gates, Scott, T. L. Knutset, and J. W. Moses. 1996. “Democracy and Peace: A More Skeptical View.” Journal of Peace Research 33: 1-11. Ginsburg, G. 1988. The Captive Public: How Mass Opinion Promotes State Power. New York, NY: Basic Books. Holmes, J. E. 1985. The Mood/Interest Theory of American Foreign Policy. Lexington, KY: University Press of Kentucky. Inglehart, Ronald, and Paul R. Abramson. 1994. “Economic Security and Value Change.” The American Political Science Review 88: 335-54. Inglehart, Ronald. 1977. The Silent Revolution: Changing Values and Political Styles Among Western Public. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Inglehart, Ronald. 1997. Modernization and Postmodernization: Cultural, Economic, and Political Change in 43 Societies. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Inglehart, Ronald. 2000. “Globalization and Postmodern Values.” Washington Quarterly 23: 215-28. Jaggers, Keith, and Ted R. Gurr. 1995. “Tracking Democracy’s Third Wave with the Polity III Data.” Journal of Peace Research 32: 469-482. Klingberg, Frank L. 1983. Cyclical Trends in American Foreign Policy Moods: The Unfolding of America’s World Role. Lanham, MD: University Press of America. Klingberg, Frank L. 1979. “Cyclical Trends in American Foreign Policy Moods and Their Policy Implications.” In Challenges to America: United States Foreign Policy in the 1980s, eds. C. W. Kegley, Jr. and P. J. McGowan. Beverly Hills, CA: Sage. Lakatos, Imre. 1970. In Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, eds. Imre Lakatos and Alan Musgrave (116-180). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Lake, David. 1992. “Powerful Pacifists: Democratic States and War.” American Political Science Review 86: 24-37. Layne, Christopher. 1994. “Kant or Cant: The Myth of the Democratic Peace.” International Security 19: 5-49. Mansfield, Edward D., and Jack Snyder. 1995. “Democratization and the Danger of War.” International Security 20: 5-38. Maoz, Zeev, and Bruce Russett. 1993. “Normative and Structural Causes of Democratic Peace, 1946-1986.” The American Political Science Review 87: 624-38. 27 Margolis, M., and G. A. Mauser, eds. 1989. Manipulating Public Opinion. Pacific Grove, CA: Brooks/Cole. Moravcsik, Andrew. 1997. “Taking Preferences Seriously: A Liberal Theory of International Politics.” International Organization 51: 513-53. Morgan, T. Clifton, and Valerie Schweback. 1992. “Take Two Democracies and Call Me in the Morning: A Prescription for Peace?” International Interaction 17: 305-20. Most, Benjamin, and Harvey Starr. 1989. Inquiry, Logic, and International Politics. Columbia, SC: University of South Carolina Press. Mueller, John. 1973. War, Presidents, and Public Opinion. New York, NY: Wiley. Mueller, John. 1994. Policy and Opinion in the Gulf War. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press. Oneal, John R., and Bruce Russett. Forthcoming in 2001. Triangulating Peace: Democracy, Interdependence, and International Organizations. New York, NY: Norton. Oneal, John R., and Bruce Russett. 1997. “The Classical Liberals Were Right: Democracy, Interdependence, and Conflict, 1950-1985.” International Studies Quarterly 41: 267-93. Oneal, John R., Frances Oneal, and Zeev Maoz. 1996. “The Liberal Peace: Interdependence, Democracy, and International Conflict, 1950-85.” Journal of Peace Research 33: 11-28. Oren, Ido. 1995. “The Subjectivity of the Democratic Peace: Changing U.S. Perceptions of Imperial Germany.” International Security 20: 147-84. Owen, John M. 1994. “How Liberalism Produces Democratic Peace.” International Security 19: 87-129. Owen, John M. 1997. American Politics and International Security. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Peceny, Mark. 1997. “A Constructivist Interpretation of the Liberal Peace: The Ambiguous Case of the Spanish-American War.” Journal of Peace Research 34: 415-30. Ray, James L. 1995. Democracy and International Conflict. Columbia, SC: University of South Carolina Press. 28 Reiter, Dan, and Allan C. Stam. 1998a. “Democracy, War Initiation, and Victory.” The American Political Science Review 92: 377-89. Reiter, Dan, and Allan C. Stam. 1998c. “A Structural-Consent Model of Domestic Politics and International Conflict.” Unpublished paper. Risse-Kappen, Thomas. 1995. “Democratic Peace – Warlike Democracies? A Social Constructivist Interpretation of the Liberal Argument.” European Journal of International Relations 1: 491-517. Robinson, John P., and Phillip R. Shaver. 1969. Measures of Social Psychological Attitudes. Ann Arbor, MI: Institute for Social Research. Rousseau, David L., Christopher Gelpi, and Paul Huth. 1996. “Assessing the Dyadic Nature of the Democratic Peace, 1918-88.” The American Political Science Review 90: 512-33. Rummel, R. J. 1997. Power Kills: Democracy as a Method of Non-Violence. New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction. Russett, Bruce, and Harvey Starr. 2000, “From Democratic Peace to Kantian Peace: Democracy and Conflict in the International System.” In Handbook of War Studies, eds. Manus Midlarsky. Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press. Russett, Bruce. 1993. Grasping the Democratic Peace: Principles for Post-Cold War. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Siverson, Randolph. 1995. “Democracies and War Participation: In Defense of the Institutional Constraint Argument.” European Journal of International Relations 1: 48189. Snyder, Jack, and Karen Ballentine. 1996. “Nationalism and the Marketplace of Ideas.” International Security 21: 5-40. Sorenson, George. 1992. “Kant and Processes of Democratization: Consequences of Neorealist Thought.” Journal of Peace Research 29: 405-33. Starr, Harvey. 1997. Anarchy, Order, and Integration: How to Manage Interdependence. Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press. Van Belle, Douglas. 1997. “Press Freedom and the Democratic Peace.” Journal of Peace Research 34: 405-14. Vanhanen, Tatu. 1984. The Emergence of Democracy: A Comparative Study of 119 States, 1850 – 1979. Helsinki, Finland: Finnish Society of Sciences and Letters. 29 Vanhanen, Tatu. 1990. The Process of Democratization: A Comparative Study of 147 States, 1980-88. New York, NY: Crane Russak. Wendt, Alexander. 1999. Social Theory of International Politics. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. 30