Relational Autonomy and the Right Not to Know Debate Dorit Barlevy Erasmus Mundus Applied Ethics Thesis Spring 2010 -1- TABLE OF CONTENTS CHAPTER 1 – Introduction 3 CHAPTER 2 – The Principle of Autonomy and an Ethic of Care Approach 8 2.1 Autonomy 9 2.2 Care Ethics in Brief 13 CHAPTER 3 – A Review of Literature Dealing with the Right Not to Know Debate 15 3.1 Ost and Strasser 16 3.2 Chadwick 20 3.3 Andorno 25 CHAPTER 4 – An Element Not Adequately Addressed 29 4.1 Stigma 31 CHAPTER 5 – Relational Autonomy and Its Application to the Debate 38 5.1 Shallow Versus Deep Conceptions of Relational Autonomy 41 CHAPTER 6 – Conclusion 47 6.1 Further Applications 50 REFERENCES 52 -2- Introduction -3- There seems to be philosophical consensus that knowledge is inherently good in and of itself (Chadwick, Levin & Schickle, p 3). If knowledge is such a “good” thing, then it is understandable for persons to desire having it. Thus our modern world is shaped by the generation and acquisition of ever-increasing amounts of information. But is knowledge always a “good” thing? After all, there are differences between good news and bad news. Furthermore, there are the well-known expressions of “no news is good news” and “ignorance is bliss.” So instead of perceiving knowledge to be a “good” thing, it should really be viewed as morally neutral and that the attitude one adopts towards that knowledge to be socially conditioned (Chadwick, p 18). Additionally, knowledge is not merely an ends, but can be a means to other things. Knowledge can most definitely be understood as empowering individuals. With the assistance of knowledge, one can avoid making decisions that lead to bad outcomes and instead choose those options that will more likely result in positive outcomes (ibid). Certainly it would seem that a reasonable person would want to know all relevant facts before making any decision. However such a line of reasoning does not account for the harm that knowledge can cause – such as psychological distress and/or misery – or the costs involved in the acquisition of knowledge (Strasser, p 268) – such as time to find out information, psychological distress due to receipt of information, or a conferred responsibility to impart such information to others. Therefore, one could reasonably decline to acquire certain information in order to prevent such harm and personal costs. Furthermore, despite the moral neutrality of knowledge, moral concerns can arise regarding the use of acquired knowledge, such as with the case of research involving radioactivity and the eventual application of that knowledge to create the atomic bomb (Shickle, p 72). Moral concerns also arise due to the fact that the acquisition of knowledge can confer a certain level of responsibility – possibly a moral responsibility to put that knowledge to good use. Could someone rightfully claim that the burden of acquiring a certain piece of knowledge carries too much of a responsibility for him/her and thus should be able to claim a right to remain ignorant? -4- In an era of greater patient autonomy and empowerment, the right not to know is often applied to cases of genetic testing whereby a patient is not required to perform a genetic test (see WMA Statement on Genetics and Medicine). This right arises due to a number of reasons including consideration of the impact such information revealed through genetic tests has on the individual patient and the very real threat of discrimination by health insurance companies. Additionally, the results of a genetic test have health implications for a limited scope of persons – primarily the individual patient requesting the test, blood-relatives and any of his/her offspring. Genetic diseases, therefore, are not as communicable (and hence less “dangerous”) as infectious (air or blood-borne) diseases. Much debate exists over whether such a right not to know does in fact exist and most commonly the debate revolves around the interpretation of principles of autonomy. In reviewing the literature thus written on this subject, I noticed that discussion is focused on a classical definition of autonomy (which I will shortly elaborate upon). However, absent from the literature is discussion of relational autonomy and how it can be applicable to the right not to know debate. It is interesting that this particular approach to autonomy is not discussed with respect to the debate because genetic information is “relational” by its very nature – in that it is applicable to all those that share the same genes (i.e. blood relatives). Therefore, it is with this thesis that I wish to investigate whether the principle of relational autonomy can enhance and contribute to the right not to know debate. For purposes of brevity, I shall mainly focus on relational autonomy with respect to genetic testing, especially due to its inherent “relationality.” I defend the stance that a right not to know can exist when in the third chapter I review the most well-known arguments involved in the right not to know debate, beginning with the discourse between David Ost and Mark Strasser. Ost argues that the right not to know cannot exist based on theories of autonomy, because in order to be autonomous one must be rational and the adamant request to remain ignorant is in and of itself irrational. Meanwhile, Strasser focuses on the harm principle and the probability rather than certainty of harm that would result in not knowing information. Ruth Chadwick’s -5- writings claim a right not to know can be founded on principles of autonomy and selfdetermination. She also briefly discusses others’ right to know another’s genetic information. Finally, Roberto Andorno writes in support of the right not to know, based on principles of autonomy, but contends that because the right is neither absolute nor implicit then it must be explicitly “activated.” For the fourth chapter I draw attention to a concept which I feel does not get adequately addressed in the right not to know debate, namely that of stigmatization. I expound upon the components of stigma and their related implications based upon the specific writings and definitions of Bruce Link and Jo Phelan which I believe convincingly portray the realities of this often latent phenomenon. Understood within a framework of relational autonomy, fear of this phenomenon can often subconsciously influence an individual towards choosing to not know certain information. In chapter five I present my idea of how the relational approach to autonomy can provide additional insight to the right not to know debate. It is in this chapter that I go into depth on the relational approach to autonomy, sprinkling the discussion with a care of ethics perspective. Furthermore, I present my theorized concepts of shallow and deep relational autonomy and determine whether such a theory enriches elements of the debate. (My hope is that the reader will be able to follow my train of thought in tackling this issue where I at first conceive of these two conceptions of relational autonomy and then realize that they do not apply so easily and therefore tweak them, by placing them on ends of a continuum, in order to create a more apt theory. I should note that with this theory I am not attempting to make any ground-shattering revelations, but rather to explore ways of looking at the debate that I believe have not yet been tried, especially in an effort to incorporate what I believe to be a latent yet highly influential social phenomenon that affects individuals’ decision making processes.) And in the sixth and final chapter I summarize the findings and discuss possible further applications of the right not to know. Specifically, I take a look at various diagnostic tests, such as those which determine the status of communicable diseases. Such a -6- discussion goes further than previous discussions in the thesis that will have thus far been limited to genetic testing. But before I delve into the right not to know debate, I wish to take a moment to elaborate a bit on the concept of autonomy, especially owing to the fact that so much of the debate regarding the right not to know revolves around it. Additionally, in the next chapter I expound upon an ethics of care approach, which gives theoretical support to the concept of relational autonomy. I intend to use both the concepts of relational autonomy and its supporting ethics of care approach when tackling the right not to know debate in my own way. -7- The Principle of Autonomy and an Ethic of Care Approach -8- 2.1 AUTONOMY The definition of autonomy is literally “self rule” and as the prominent philosopher Onora O’Neill highlights, “[m]ost contemporary accounts of autonomy see it as a form of independence” (O’Neil, p 28) from something or other. It is important to not mistakenly equate autonomy with the mere ability to choose. The classical interpretation of autonomy views it generally as a capacity or trait that individuals may have to varying degrees, which s/he can exhibit by acting in individualistic and rationalistic ways. The focus of this interpretation is on freedom of will and rationality. Thus, one can only be fully autonomous when s/he acts independent of any and all outside influences in a right and appropriate way, as deemed (reasonable) by society. Such a common view of autonomy is far too simplistic to note the slight and varied innuendos concerned with such a broad concept as autonomy. For a more detailed analysis I now turn to the ideas proposed by the American social and political philosopher Joel Feinberg who suggests there are four specific ways that the term “autonomy” can be used (see Maartje Schermer’s The Different Faces of Autonomy). First of all, the term can refer to the capacity for self-government. This capacity is a matter of degree depending upon one’s ability to make rational choices. As an actual condition, “autonomy” refers to the possession and practice of certain virtues that generate the idea of self-government. In this sense, “autonomy” is not a characteristic of specific actions or choices, but rather a global property of persons. One could group these first two uses of the term “autonomy” into what are known as authenticity models of autonomy. Such models suggest that in order for a person to be autonomous s/he must “really be him/herself.” As we will shortly see, these models contend that one must either become truly self-aware (i.e. by subjecting one’s actions to critical self-reflection) or develop a “real” identity and act in accordance to that identity. Of course, one large problem with such models is that some can abusively claim that because someone does not act authentically or in accordance with his/her supposed own true self, then it is preferable or even necessary to interfere with his/her actions (in order to correct a person’s adherence to his/her true self). -9- Another usage of the term “autonomy” is as a character ideal, referring to a set of virtues that determine the actual condition of autonomy. The particular virtues should culminate in the identity of an authentic individual who, as a member of a community, is ideally capable of making sovereign decisions. Finally, when the term “autonomy” is used as a right to sovereign authority it refers to the right for one to make and act upon one’s own choices without interference by others. In her dissertation, The Different Faces of Autonomy, Maartje Schermer suggests that Feinberg might have missed another use of “autonomy” whereby it could refer to a right not to be treated as if one did not have any actual autonomy. In other words, she claims that the term “autonomy” could also refer to a right to respect. Unfortunately, while she does not further elaborate on this supposition, one could assume that she means autonomy can be seen as an inherent characteristic of persons that qualifies them to have moral worth and thereby respect as an individual of a community. Now in relation to the use of “autonomy” as an actual condition, Ronald Dworkin and Harry Frankfurt developed a “split-level self” theory of autonomy. This theory dictates that persons can have desires on two distinct levels: lower-order and higher-order desires. The former refers to desires to do something (i.e. actions), whereas the latter pertains to the desire to have certain lower-order desires. According to Dworkin’s theory, autonomy is only achieved when a person’s higher-order desires are congruent with his/her lowerorder desires and that one’s process of identification remains independent from subverting influences such as manipulation or coercion. It is worthy to mention, as Schermer does, that Dworkin developed his theory at a time when behaviorist psychology was at its peak of popularity and thus wanted to explain why certain techniques for behavior control, such as hypnosis, conditioning and subliminal suggestion, could actually undermine autonomy. “As he phrases it, autonomy is the capacity to reflect critically upon one’s motivational structure and to make changes in that structure” (Schermer, p 22). In this way, Feinberg’s distinction between autonomy as an actual condition versus a capacity (specifically for critical self-reflection) becomes blurred. But - 10 - then again, both of these two uses of the term autonomy can be combined into the group of authenticity models of autonomy. Regardless, Dworkin’s revised theory continues that autonomy can only be assessed over a period of time. The reason for this specification is due to the obvious fact that one’s preferences or choices can change over time, especially due to maturity, experience and reflection. Consistent with this theory is John Christman’s “historical” account of autonomy whereby one should focus on how a person comes to have the desires or preferences that s/he now holds. Going further than Dworkin in elaborating on the criteria for self-reflection, Christman claims that such a thought process must involve no self-deception and be minimally rational. It seems that Christman specifically emphasizes this criteria in order to align autonomous decision making with one’s “gut” feeling, or intuition, thereby bypassing the need for rational thought processes, which could betray one’s deeply held true feelings. This of course seems to directly contradict Feinberg’s outline of the use of “autonomy” as a capacity, which fundamentally depends on the degree to one’s competence – as in the ability to make rational choices. Therefore there seems to be a bit of disagreement in the philosophical discourse as to whether the principle of autonomy requires rationality or not. (In the next chapter, with the discourse between Ost and Strasser, we will see further disagreement as to whether rationality is fundamental to the specific right not to know debate.) Anyhow, in returning to Schermer’s comprehensive literature review, she notes that unlike the aforementioned authors, George Agich subscribes to a theory of autonomy that highlights its dynamic character. Agich postulates that “autonomous or authentic choices and actions are those that spring from and are consistent with a person’s developed identity” (Schermer, p 23). While he acknowledges that critical self-reflection is important, it is not necessary for every action in order for a person to be considered autonomous. Instead, Agrich and others that subscribe to a developmental perspective on autonomy stress the necessity for consistency between actions and one’s own identity. In other words, autonomy is a process rather than a condition whereby one must have a developed identity and s/he acts in accordance with that identity. - 11 - While all these various classifications can be made in order to differentiate the various uses and inuendos of the term “autonomy,” one should equally bear in mind that it is a composite notion. As exhibited in the previous brief analysis of the concept of autonomy, sometimes the differentiations conflict with one another. However, as a composite notion, all these separate definitions need not be exclusionary. Instead, they may be complementary to one another or even overlapping, especially due to the blurring lines of distinction that the various categories possess. Thus far, the discussions of autonomy have focused mainly on the individual and his/her specific preferences. Granted, some of the literature review thus far has contemplated and highlighted the importance of the process by which one comes to have his/her specific preferences. However, such literature has focused on the individual processes at work in the selection of one’s preferences, such as with self critical reflection. In contrast, a more contemporary relational approach to autonomy focuses on how individuals are embedded within complex webs of social and cultural relationships and how these relations affect one’s identity and choices. The relational approach to autonomy finds fault with the classical ideal of the autonomous individual as being so atomistic and self-sufficient that any external values, social practices, relationship and/or communities are conceived as threatening or compromising one’s autonomy (Mackenzie & Stoljar, p 6). Instead, relational autonomy comprehends an individual’s identity and decisions as interdependent with his/her social environment. Examining autonomy from a relational standpoint offers two main types of conceptions: the constitutively or intrinsically relational conception focuses on the social constitution of the agent or the social nature of the capacity of autonomy itself, while the causally relational conception focuses on the ways in which socialization and social relationships impede or enhance autonomy (Mackenzie & Stoljar, p 22). Hence, by taking a casually relational approach to autonomy, which acknowledges that socio-cultural factors can either rightfully or wrongfully influence one’s autonomy, I wish to take a comprehensive look at the power and role that social stigma can play on - 12 - one’s personal choices. At this point however, I will now turn to a brief overview of the care perspective which coheres with a relational account of autonomy (Verkerk, p 289). I should note that I plan on using both a relational autonomy approach and its supportive ethic of care perspective later on when examining the right not to know debate in further detail. 2.2 CARE ETHICS IN BRIEF An ethic of care “treats care as central for understanding the nature of morality” (Timmons, 224). When one cares for another, ideally they would care about the individual. Caring about someone often times entails metaphorically placing oneself in the shoes of the individual for which s/he cares about. In this way, the ethic of care approach emphasizes empathy and I believe that it is this capacity which makes us uniquely human. Furthermore, we could all stand to be more empathetic, especially when we want to better understand others, which I believe is an endeavor of societies that strive for peaceful and harmonious relations. Care ethics’ emphasis on empathy corresponds to an emphasis on moral responsibility owed towards others. Therefore, like relational autonomy, which views moral questions in terms of responsibilities rather than rights due to its focus on interdependence, care ethics also places considerable emphasis on one’s responsibilities for others. This leads to care ethics’ inclination towards concern about considerable harm, in contrast to liberals’ stress of honoring individuals’ rights regardless of the damage that can be inflicted upon others (i.e. their psychological well-being). Now as Timmons suggests, care ethics can be understood as embracive of a virtue pluralism, whereby it underscores the importance of connection and attachment. This perspective views the “good life” as having relationships with others – friends, family and community. It is also in this way that care ethics corresponds to a relational approach to autonomy whereby the idea of human interdependency is so central. Owing - 13 - to this correspondence, I intend to incorporate this perspective when analyzing the right not to know debate, particularly when dealing with issues of stigma. Due to the crucial and basic role it gives to feeling, care ethics can also be understood as a form of sentimentalism (Slote, p 106). Having said that, one might ask if the perspective is irrational by its very definition, seeing as feelings can be thought of in stark contrast to the impartiality of logic. However, while some feelings can be classified as irrational, they are not definitively so. Furthermore, feelings can be subject to various tests to determine whether they are rational and valid especially when a moral perspective is based upon them. I mention this issue because, as we will see in the next chapter, rationality is understood as a central component of autonomy, which in turn forms the basis of many arguments in favor of a right not to know. - 14 - A Review of Literature Dealing with the Right Not to Know Debate - 15 - For the purposes of familiarizing the reader with the concepts and issues that are most often linked to discussions about the right not to know and to support the notion that a right not to know can exist I shall now review some key pieces of literature that have thus far been written on the subject. Consequently the reader will find it evident, as I continually note throughout, that one particular yet common social phenomenon, namely stigmatization, is either neglected or not adequately addressed in such writings. Hence in subsequent chapters I take a closer look at the phenomenon itself, its implications and propose approaching the issue with a principle of relational autonomy that sufficiently deals with the dilemma of stigma. I begin this chapter by looking at one of the first published philosophical debates on the topic of the right not to know. Ost, who argues against a right not to know, attacks the stance that such a right can be supported by a principle of autonomy, understood as a capacity or actual condition that necessitates rationality. In contrast, Strasser supports a right not to know based on the harm principle. From this discussion I turn to the writings of Chadwick – one of the more renowned writers on the topic of a right not to know, especially with regard to genetic testing. While her leanings are in support of a right not to know, based upon principles of autonomy and self-determination, she recognizes the conflict that exists between individual rights and individual responsibility. I conclude the chapter with the more contemporary writings of Andorno, who acknowledges a right not to know, but specifies its limits. Andorno augments the debate by stipulating that the right not to know must be explicitly “activated” by an individual who wishes to not know information. 3.1 OST AND STRASSER David Ost argues that a right not to know cannot exist by connecting the debate of the right to know versus a right not to know information to the concept of autonomy and its relation to rationality. Ost begins by building his argument around Thomas Aquinas’ assertion that the concept of autonomy is founded on the ideas of rationality and freedom of will. According to Aquinas’ formula, one is autonomous if and only if s/he is rational and free of will. Therefore if one is irrational or constrained, i.e. not free of will, s/he - 16 - cannot be autonomous. Of course constraint can be either external or internal. External constraints can come in the form of government laws that prevent people from committing certain actions. On the other hand, internal constraints such as personal feelings of guilt or responsibility towards others can also prevent people from acting in certain ways. Ost specifies that libertarians emphasize the importance of liberty by focusing on defining autonomy as being free from external constraints. On the other hand, others, like Kant, emphasize the need to be free from internal constraint. This camp contends that the process by which one frees oneself from internal constraint – i.e. via critical self-reflection – can even assist an individual in increasing his/her rational reasoning. Both libertarian and Kantian interpretations of autonomy suggest that physicians cannot impose unwanted information on a patient. While Ost notes this implication he also quickly marginalizes it in order to focus on the apparent irrationality of an individual who refuses information. As he theorizes, if the refusal of information is irrational, then it cannot be an autonomous choice because the main element necessary for the capacity or condition of autonomy is missing (i.e. rationality) and hence the individual’s autonomy is not being violated when one acts against his/her expressed desire not to be informed. Ost comes to comprehend that an individual who insistently refuses to be informed of information, which others (i.e. rational persons) might find to be relevant or even beneficial to the individual, does so on the basis of one of only two possible grounds, both of which are irrational. The first possible interpretation is that the individual’s intentions are so fixed and unalterable that they act in an obsessive manner and hence may be classified as irrational. Ost’s second formulated interpretation is that the individual may claim to know what he cannot know prior to another’s disclosure of information, but claiming to know what one cannot know is contradictory and therefore irrational. Furthermore, Ost suggests that patients have an obligation to be informed due to their autonomous agency. Ost specifically views autonomy as an inalienable status rather than a right. If rationality is a necessary component of autonomy, then acting irrationally whereby one refuses receiving (relevant) information is a violation of autonomy. Therefore, Ost deduces that as autonomous agents, individuals must be informed. - 17 - However, he continues by claiming that physicians shouldn’t necessarily bully their patients into receiving information. On the contrary, he highlights an important point in that there are two value-orientations in the way one can act. When one acts humanely, s/he acts in a way to minimize pain, harm or discomfort resulting from the human condition which we all share. This orientation results from an underlying motive of compassion. In contrast, when one acts humanistically, s/he acts in ways that project the ideals of what human actions and choices ought to be (i.e. free, self-determining, responsible). This orientation results from an underlying motive of respect. Ost maintains that medicine’s aim is humanistic but should be tempered by the principle of humaneness, so that physicians ought to “assist patients to achieve the optimal level of autonomy possible to them” (Ost, p 310) in a sensitive fashion. As a result, the practical implication of such trajectories is that patients ought to be informed but not bullied into knowing information. A physician’s tactics of persuasion would thus be essential and justified in order to help an unwilling patient realize the importance of knowing information that s/he initially wishes not to know. Additionally, it is interesting to note that an ethic of care can comprehend such persuasions as “compassionate interference,” whereby the physician’s actions can be thought of “as a form of care in which the patient has an opportunity to become autonomous” (Verkerk, p 293). Such actions are criticized as being a form of “modern paternalism” (ibid) and clearly run counter to Feinberg’s aforementioned classification of autonomy as a right to sovereign authority without interference by others. Mark Strasser responds to Ost’s argument by proposing that individuals can claim a right to remain uinformed due to John Stuart Mill’s emphasis on liberty and his formulated harm principle. Strasser does not refute Ost’s contention that rationality is a central component of autonomy. However he differs from Ost in thinking that one who refuses information can do so for rational reasons. Strasser begins his reasoning by concurring with Ost that the ascertainment of whether an individual has relevant information is problematic because the standards by which to make such judgments are heavily culturally dependent and therefore one standard cannot be universalized for all societies and all situations. Strasser continues by citing Mill’s contention that the one making a - 18 - decision is the only one who can judge the sufficiency of his/her own motives that may induce the individual to incur a risk. Furthermore, considering that liberty consists of doing what one desires, others are not in a position to (justifiably) override an individual’s decision to take on certain risks knowingly. Such a claim is not the same as maintaining that the individual who refuses to be informed of certain information professes to know what another will disclose (i.e. what s/he could not possibly know). Rather, the argument follows that what one already knows warrants one to take a risk and forego “the opportunity to become apprised of [ ] (possibly) unknown information” (Strasser, p 270). Additionally, Strasser contends that usually there is only a probability rather than a certainty that harm will arise if an individual remains ignorant about a certain piece of information (upon his/her specific insistence because there remains the possibility that the agent would have made the same choice even after acquiring the additionally relevant information. The question then becomes whether ignorance will result in certain or probable harm. (One could equally ask whether knowledge will result in certain or probable harm and the following analysis shall remain the same.) Strasser theorizes that ignorance can only result in probable harm because there is always the chance that the ignorant agent will act “rightly” and that the informed agent will act “wrongly.” If it is only probable harm, then one returns to Mill’s assertion – only the agent alone can decide whether his/her motives are sufficient to justify taking the risk and not being apprised of certain information. Strasser continues his critique of Ost’s argument by claiming that there is no such thing as a patient’s duty to be informed, in contrast to a physician’s duty to inform a patient, but that duty of course is coupled with providing treatment or procedures which the patient has a right to accept or refuse. Strasser bases this critique on the hypothetical situation of proxy consent, whereby parents refuse to be informed of certain information in the best interests of their child (especially when time is of the essence) and thus relegate decision-making to the physician. Considering the rather specific nature of the example with which he utilizes, it is not obvious that such an argument would equally apply to a scenario of genetic testing. Nevertheless, Strasser resumes by stating that while there is no such thing as a “duty to listen,” the refusal to hear information may not - 19 - always be justified. Therefore, he advocates for providing patients with “relevant information about the relevant information” (Strasser, p 274) in order for them to decide for themselves whether they wish to receive the relevant information, and hence be justified in taking a risk and foregoing the information. For example, a physician might be in possession of certain information about the patient that could harm his/her chances of survival or recovery, or could render a weak individual so frightened that s/he ceases to function rationally. In such circumstances, Strasser might argue that the physician ought to inform the patient that by sharing such information with him/her could lead to such disastrous outcomes and might actually lead one to be very rational in choosing to decline receiving the relevant information. However, this approach can be easily criticized as being absurd because if the physician reveals to the patient that s/he has information that is relevant to the patient but could cause harm to the patient were s/he to become aware of it, then isn’t the cat proverbially out of the bag that the physician has bad news? Such suggestions are based on scenarios whereby the patient has undergone some sort of diagnostic testing. However, this does not address situations prior to testing, whereby the patient has to decide whether or not to undergo a certain (genetic) test which will reveal certain information about the individual. Knowledge is not yet known by anyone, or more specifically by the physician, for him/her to give an individual (i.e. the patient) relevant information about the known information. To address the right to know versus right not to know debate in such cases whereby an individual has not undergone diagnostic testing, I shall now turn to Ruth Chadwick’s writings. 3.2 CHADWICK Chadwick examines both sides of the debate by first claiming that at least four central concepts are central to the issue: autonomy, confidentiality, privacy and solidarity. Arguments for the right not to know tend to be based on considerations of privacy, integrity and self-determination, while the counter-arguments emphasize solidarity and responsibility. (Since the right to know and the right not to know are opposing viewpoints, the counter arguments for a right not to know double as supporting - 20 - arguments for a right to know, and vice versa.) The information in question tends to be of a highly personal and sensitive nature (i.e. genetic make-up). Before delving into the heart of the discussion, Chadwick first establishes that there is a right for individuals to know such information (i.e. one’s own genetic status) based on principles of autonomy and self-determination, whereby the receipt of certain information can assist an individual in making certain decisions (possibly even reproductive in nature) and taking or not taking certain actions. The right for others to know another’s genetic status is less clear cut. It is commonly accepted that one’s medical information is personal and thus should remain restricted to the knowledge of the individual and the physician (and other relevant healthcare team members). However in the case of genetic information, respecting one’s autonomy and confidentiality could affect the individual’s relatives and/or partner in their capacity to make autonomous reproductive decisions. If one follows Mill’s harm principle which dictates that one’s liberty should be limited only when the exercise of that liberty harms others, then respecting one’s autonomous choice to keep certain genetic information confidential from others could harm those others’ “right to make reproductive decisions in the light of as much information as possible” (Chadwick, p 16). But can anyone rightfully make such a claim to know as much information as possible in order to make reproductive decisions? The amount of information that can be generated regarding one’s reproductive choices is heavily dependent upon context – both historical and social. Technological advances have certainly increased Western population’s ability to make more informed decisions about reproduction, but it is not mandatory to employ them for all individuals thinking about reproduction. Furthermore, some societies do not yet have the technological expertise that other societies have. One society’s means to information is not necessarily equal to another’s. So the phrase “as much information as possible” is unclear as to whether it refers to a global or local context. The right of institutions, such as insurance companies, to know an individual’s genetic status is also questionable depending on how one views such institutions – as either nothing more than a capitalistic business or one that also serves a social purpose. Of - 21 - particular concern in this matter is that of genetic discrimination, whereby insurance companies reject providing coverage or charge exorbitant fees for coverage to individuals that have a genetic predisposition or suffer from a genetically-based disease. Genetic discrimination is a very real and serious threat to liberal society’s focus and goal of equality. Chadwick conjectures that the right not to know is typically claimed by an individual who does not want to have access to information about him/herself, as a response to others’ claims to have that information. She then proceeds to list and briefly outline the various arguments in support of a right not to know. The negative approach leads one to find the arguments for a right to know to be inadequate and fear that the right to know might become an imperative, forcing everyone to undergo testing. Another approach focuses on the human condition as one of limited knowledge and therefore there can be no duty to know. This line of reasoning is fairly weak because it does not necessarily follow that from this human condition an individual has the right not to know a certain piece of information when that knowledge is available. Chadwick continues by focusing on a number of consequentialist arguments in favor of the right not to know. The first of these arguments is that being informed of a certain piece of information can cause harm. This harm could come in the form of psychological distress – perhaps even to the point rendering the individual incapable of maintaining his/her rationality or even ability to make autonomous decisions, the idea of which, as noted above, has been put forward by Ost. Psychological distress from knowing the unpleasant results of a genetic test could significantly affect the quality of one’s life for the worse and therefore constitute a harm. Chadwick then aptly mentions the commonly drawn distinction between knowledge, which is considered to be morally neutral, and its use or the attitude we adopt towards it, which is socially conditioned. Taking this distinction into account, one could argue that harm could easily be avoided in receiving certain information by simply changing his/her perspective of the information, by perhaps approaching new knowledge with a positive attitude. Of course such a suggestion is easier said than done, especially considering culturally hegemonic forces at work. (I - 22 - shall further elaborate on this aspect in the next chapter.) Consequentialists will be most interested in determining whether the overall benefits of acquiring knowledge – such as helping one to avoid bad outcomes and choose good ones – outweigh its disadvantages – such as harming the individual’s psyche. Chadwick suggests that perhaps certain kinds of misery should be given special weight in such consequentialist calculations. (While some might argue that making such considerations to certain kinds of misery seems to highlight an individualistic approach to the matter, I contend that it supports an ethic of care approach, which emphasizes a principle of solidarity in that an individual is encouraged to empathize with another’s perceptions of pain.) One could also possibly associate the right not to know with the right to hope if infringing on a patient’s wish to remain ignorant of certain information will lead one to become certain of something that flies in the face of his/her hopes. This of course leads one to ask if the right to hope – and therefore by association, the right not to know – is actually a matter of allowing persons to delude themselves of certain realities. Aside from psychological distress, the harm to an individual resulting from being informed about certain genetic information could also be in the form of serious social consequences for him/her in terms of stigmatization and discrimination. Chadwick is quick to note that this point can only strictly be made in restricting the access of others to the genetic information rather than in the argument for the right not to know. Clearly the possibility of discrimination can only support restricting access of others to one’s genetic information, but I disagree with Chadwick regarding stigmatization. As I will further elaborate on in the next chapter, stigmatization can be internalized, to the point that receiving certain information can shatter one’s sense of self and thus psychologically harm the individual. This sense of self plays an important role in the last two consequentialist arguments supporting the right not to know. If one were to comprehend autonomy in terms of empowerment – enabling individuals to feel empowered – then not all (genetic) knowledge is necessarily empowering. A certain diagnosis could possibly cause an individual to feel restricted in his/her choices or as I briefly mentioned above, destroy - 23 - that individual’s sense of self. Therefore, the right not to know could actually protect one’s autonomy or sense of self. (It is worthy to note that this analysis blurs the aforementioned distinction of autonomy as a capacity versus a right to sovereign authority.) Additionally, genetic information can be construed as an intrusion into an individual’s private sphere, most often deemed by liberal society as inviolable. Due to the often concealed nature of genetic information, persons may develop a sense of self or identity that is incongruent with their genetic status. The right not to know therefore begs the question whether an individual ought to be compelled to modify his/her sense of self in an undesirable way by being informed of his/her genetic status against his/her will. On the other hand, is it “right” to allow persons’ desire to retain their (possibly misguided) self-images to trump other considerations, such as solidarity, responsibility and public health? Chadwick also elucidates on two arguments opposing the right not to know. One can view the right not to know as an overly individualistic approach to ethical issues and thus defies values of solidarity and responsibility owed to others – both values that greatly contribute to a society’s social cohesion. If certain knowledge has consequences for others, then it can be deemed irresponsible of a person to choose to not know such knowledge. Secondly, Chadwick mentions Walter Zimmerli’s suggestion “that public health considerations provide an argument against a right not to know” (Chadwick, p 20), and brings up Peter Widmer’s belief that “a sense of responsibility in the society at large begins with awareness on the part of the individual” (Chadwick, p 21). But then again, liberal democratic societies cannot impose a duty of solidarity on its citizens. She concludes her review of the right not to know debate by noting the recent shift towards a communitarian approach to ethics and medical ethics, which emphasizes the significance of community and responsibility. This communitarian approach has special relevance in genetic testing due to its inherent emphasis on relatedness. Moreover, Chadwick finds that the urge to charge individuals with the responsibility to know their genetic information and share it with loved ones follows from the idea of supplementing or even replacing individual rights with considerations of individual responsibilities. - 24 - Ultimately the debate rests on the opposition between individual rights and individual responsibilities. 3.3 ANDORNO Now Roberto Andorno constructs an argument in support of the right not to know one’s genetic status, theoretically based upon the principle of autonomy, and yet maintains that such a right is neither necessarily absolute nor always implicit but rather must be explicitly “activated.” Similar to Mairi Levitt’s assertion in The Right to Know and the Right not to Know, Andorno begins by commenting on the predictive power of genetic tests, which has the tendency to outpace the availability of effective treatments and the human ability to cope with knowledge generated from the employment of such tests. Hence, rather than empowering an individual and promoting his/her autonomy (understood here as a right to sovereign authority), the knowledge of one’s genetic status can actually be considered a burden for an individual to bear. Sometimes, due to the relatively retarded rate at which human ability to cope with new unpleasant diagnoses (as compared to the rate at which genetic tests develop and advance), the burden of such knowledge could become so unbearable for an individual that it can lead to severe psychological depression and a seriously negative impact on one’s family life and social relationships in general.1 Andorno claims that for some people, discovering “that they have a genetic condition that places them at a high risk of suffering certain untreatable diseases could so depress them that the quality, joy, and purpose of their lives would literally evaporate” (Andorno, p 435). For this reason, he feels that it would be logical 2 to have such people autonomously choose to not receive such potentially harmful information. While opponents would argue that an individual that refuses such 1 In fact, Kimberly Fulda and Kristine Lykens report on a case where receipt of information regarding a positive carrier status of a dominant genetic disorder led to a son’s suicide, another son to divorcing his wife in order from burdening her or planning a family, and another son leaving his fiancée for the same reason (Fulda & Lykens, p 145). 2 In his article, Adorno writes “it seems reasonable to allow these people to choose not to receive that potentially harmful information and to continue their lives in peace” (my emphasis). Although Adorno never actually uses the term “rational” anywhere in his article but instead uses “reasonable” a number of times, it seems, upon deliberation, that he has incorrectly used the philosophical term and instead meant “rational” or “logical” as I’ve chosen to use in my own paraphrasing here. - 25 - information is living in ignorance and just deluding oneself, Andorno finds the individual to thus be capable of living one’s life “in peace.” Andorno then continues his paper by identifying a number of objections commonly invoked against the right not to know. First off he notes the apparent irrational attitude of one who wishes to remain ignorant because it contradicts with the well established philosophical belief, dating back to the time of Aristotle, that knowledge is intrinsically good. Secondly, some would argue that a right not to know is reminiscent of former times when the patient-physician relationship was characterized as paternalistic towards the patient by keeping him/her ignorant of particular diagnoses and depriving him/her of choice with regards to medical treatment. Since those not-so-distant days the patientphysician relationship has evolved to become one of increasing disclosure and shared decision-making. A patient claiming a right not to know would then completely conflict with physicians’ duty to disclose risks to patients. Furthermore, “the right not to know is criticized as being opposed to patients’ autonomy, given that the exercise of autonomy depends on the ability to understand relevant information and only on this basis to consent to treatment” (Andorno, p 436, emphasis in original). However, an advocate for the right not to know could frame the patient’s autonomy initially in terms of whether or not to know specific information. After that autonomous decision is made, further autonomous decisions could follow regarding treatment, procedures, or how to continue living one’s life. Lastly, Andorno mentions the objection against the right not to know made on the grounds that one choosing to claim such a right works against the principle of solidarity, as elaborated above. Before concentrating on his main thesis Andorno references a number of ethical and legislative instruments that explicitly recognize and defend the right not to know. For example, the Explanatory Report to the European Convention on Human Rights and Biomedicine “justifies the right not to know by saying that ‘patients may have their own reasons for not wishing to know about certain aspects of their health’” (ibid). Additionally, the World Medical Association’s “Declaration on the Rights of the Patient” - 26 - claims that “the patient has the right not to be informed on his/her explicit request, unless required for the protection of another person’s life” (ibid). Andorno then begins responding to the common objections that he previously brought up against the right not to know. He first refutes the assertion that choosing to not know the results of a genetic test can be classified as a kind of return to physician paternalism whence physicians were not required to tell a patient everything. Andorno claims that one should understand autonomy in a wide sense, whereby “people should be free to make their own choices with respect to information” (ibid, my emphasis). Such an interpretation of autonomy sufficiently challenges medical paternalism and results in comprehending the choice to not know as an enhancement of autonomy, rather than a threat or detriment to it. Additionally, this wide interpretation of autonomy leads Andorno to assert that respecting an individual’s autonomy serves as the theoretical foundation of the right not to know “even if the ultimate foundation of this right is the individual’s interest in not being psychologically harmed” (Andorno, p 437, emphasis in original). In other words, the right not to know is most fundamentally based upon the respect for autonomy, in order to ultimately prevent harm to the psychological integrity of the person. Preventing ultimate harm reinforces the biomedical ethical principle of non-maleficence, most often characterized by the Latin phrase primum non nocere, which roughly translates to mean “first, do not harm.” Interestingly enough, Andorno continues by advocating that a patient could reasonably claim a right not to know while agreeing to undergo genetic testing (perhaps for the purposes of public screening). Valid informed consent can still be maintained in such a situation because the patient’s ignorance does not concern the medical practice (i.e. the genetic test), but rather its results. However, in such particular situations (whereby the patient agrees to genetic testing but refuses to know the results) I would argue that there remains a tension between the physician’s duty to warn a patient of known risks versus the patient’s right to autonomy regarding receipt of information. - 27 - Andorno then discusses the discord between exercising a patient’s right not to know and the potential interest of his/her relative in knowing. He points out that most rights are not absolute and asserts that the right not to know is of no exception. The right not to know is predicated on the condition that there is no risk of serious harm to other persons. Individuals cannot validly claim a right not to know and disclosure to others is warranted if and only if it is necessary to avoid a serious harm to them and some reasonable form of cure or therapy is available. Additionally, due to concern that public genetic screening programs might encourage eugenic practices of systematically aborting affected fetuses (in the case of prenatal genetic testing), the disclosing of genetic information for the benefit of the common good must be tempered by respect for individuals’ rights. Andorno concludes his paper by contending that the right not to know cannot be presumed. Because law and ethics can only operate coherently according to rules, Andorno feels that the established rule ought to be for patients to have a right to know their health status. The right not to know would therefore be an exception to the rule (at least with regard to competent persons). In order for the right not to know to be legitimate, it must be “activated” by the explicit will of the individual; otherwise it would be impossible to determine a priori the wish of the patient and s/he is the best one to judge what are his/her best interests. But one may still inquire as to whether those patients that reject receiving information are really and truly making that decision in accordance with their real interests? Because we make decisions based on a variety of factors, including external factors (e.g. those due to environmental, societal or cultural influences) perhaps a causally relational approach to autonomy can help here and even contribute to the right to know versus right not to know debate. I shall shortly turn to this very matter. But before I do, I wish to first expand upon the concept of stigmatization, which I feel does not get adequately addressed within the literature despite it’s silent yet highly influential nature upon individuals’ decision making processes. - 28 - An Element Not Adequately Addressed - 29 - Thus far, the debate on the right not to know has mainly revolved around the concept of respect for autonomy, specifically based upon the components of rationality and freedom of will. Implicitly, the autonomy that has been invoked in these debates is that of the liberal, Kantian persuasion. Care ethicists take issue with such approaches to autonomy in that they downplay how interactions or relations with others affect one’s ability to think and decide. In the most extreme form of these care ethics critiques, there seems to have been a gradual alignment of the concept of autonomy with individualism, where agents are causally isolated from other agents. The ideal contemporary, Western-based conception of individualistic autonomy is founded on notions of self-sufficiency and independence. However the concept of individual autonomy should be distinguished from individualistic conceptions of individual autonomy. While individual autonomy solely “implies that agents are separate entities with a capacity for autonomy” (Stoljar & Mackenzie, p 8) individualistic autonomy goes further than that by suggesting a character ideal of self-sufficiency and independence whereby values and social practices based on cooperation and interdependence can threaten or even compromise the capacity for autonomy. This stripped down conception of agents views them as atomistic bearers of rights. Kantians would counter that they do not endorse the idea that persons are without social or interpersonal characteristics. On the contrary, they would argue that such commitments and relationships do in fact characterize all humans. Nevertheless, the care ethicist would argue that Kantians simply do not view such ties to be essential to or definitive of one’s identity. Despite care ethicists’ focus and emphasis on the importance of social commitments and relationships, they do not believe that all are essential to humans. Instead, care ethicists find that only the most important commitments and relationships can constitute or be part of what constitutes the identity of a given person (Slote, 74). The biggest drawback of basing arguments in favor of a right not to know on a classic, individual conception of autonomy is its total lack of ability to address the issue of stigma. Although not blaringly obvious, stigma can be highly influential in affecting someone to choose not to know certain information, especially if said information can have a damaging affect on his/her self-identity. Dworkin glosses over certain types of - 30 - behavior that undermine autonomy, such as coercion, but stigma seems to be not as cut and dry. The problem with stigma, as with oppression, is that it can be internalized and thus self-perpetuating, making it difficult for one to just dismiss. Here I would now like to dedicate some space to clarifying what exactly the concept of stigma entails and elaborate on how it can affect one’s choices, particularly in the ways it can incline one to choose not to know information, even if it is about him/herself. Due to its helpfulness in unraveling the various elements and repercussions of stigmatization, I mainly focus on Bruce Link and Jo Phelan’s article, “Conceptualizing Stigma,” with its description of the definitive elements of the concept, elaboration on the social and individual implications, and recommendations for effective deterrence of the phenomenon. 4.1 STIGMA In the aforementioned article, Bruce Link and Jo Phelan begin by discussing how stigma often times has a negative impact on the lives of those that are stigmatized. Due to the multidisciplinary nature of the phenomenon itself, the different theoretical orientations from which researchers approach the concept of stigma results in drastic differences in what the very concept should definitively entail. As Erving Goffman first noted, stigma can simply be seen as the relationship between an attribute and a stereotype. Link and Phelan further elaborate on this simple definition to include five very specific concurrent components: 1) a human difference is distinguished and labeled, 2) negative stereotypes are linked to the labeled persons, 3) labeled persons are placed in distinct categories in order to achieve a degree of separation from others, 4) labeled persons experience status loss and discrimination leading to unequal outcomes, and 5) labeled persons have less access to social, economic, and/or political power. I would like to take a moment to further clarify the implications of some of these components. (The first component seems fairly self-explanatory and therefore does not seem to need further elaboration here.) It should first be emphasized that the second component often occurs automatically. Link and Phelan explain that the automatic nature - 31 - of the second component is very real in that experiments have indicated “that categories and stereotypes are used in making split-second judgments and thus appear to be operating preconsciously” (Link & Phelan, p 369). This aspect is important to stress in order to fully comprehend how we might not even be aware of the presence of stigmatization, especially when reflecting upon what specifically influences our decisionmaking processes. The third component which differentiates stigmatized persons from non-stigmatized persons enables one to think of negatively labeled persons as “fundamentally different from those who don’t share the label” (Link & Phelan, p 370). What’s very significant about this component is how it exemplifies the fact that stigma is not a matter of all-ornothing but rather one of degree. In other words, it’s not that a person can be either stigmatized or not. Instead, “the labeling of human differences can be more or less prominent” (Link & Phelan, p 377). Furthermore, “the strength of the connection between labels and undesirable attributes can be relatively strong or relatively weak” (ibid). Cumulatively what this means is that “some groups can be more stigmatized than others” (ibid). A very telling example of this phenomenon is how some highly stigmatized persons “are thought to ‘be’ the thing they are labeled” (Link & Phelan, p 370). More specifically, people that have epilepsy or schizophrenia are described as “epileptics” or “schizophrenics,” whereas the same cannot be said of people with less stigmatized diseases such as cancer, heart disease or influenza. As a slight interjection, a number of factors can influence the degree to which a particular disease may be stigmatized. First of all, the visibility of a disease corresponds with the degree of stigma it can confer onto an afflicted individual. The less conspicuous the symptoms or conditions of a disease are (e.g. physical deformities, visible outbreaks, erratic behaviors) then the greater the impact they can have on others and subsequent interactions with them (Kurzban & Leary, p 190). Next, the frequency with which a disease affects a population can play a role in how stigmatizing it can be for one afflicted by that disease. The rarer the disease, obviously the more stigmatizing it has the potential to be, due to the fact that the general population simply is not familiar with it. The - 32 - “unknown” tends to be approached with a certain amount of hesitation, skepticism, and/or fear. In conjunction with the occurrence of rare diseases, depending upon the specific populations that are affected by the disease and how long a disease has been knowingly around can also affect the degree to which having said disease can be stigmatizing for an individual. If the disease affects an already stigmatized population, then by association, having the disease confers the same stereotypes as those of the stigmatized population. Additionally, the longer a disease has been around, the more familiar it can become to greater amounts of people and thereby approached with less hesitation, skepticism, and/or fear. Thus, outbreaks or discoveries of new diseases tend to confer more stigma, but the effect is lessened with the passage of time and greater familiarity of said disease. Another aspect of a disease that determines its degree of stigma has to do with its affect on morbidity and/or mortality. Diseases that have a cure fare far better than those that do not, in terms of stigmatization; for once one is cured, the stigma associated with the disease vanishes along with the very disease. Additionally, those diseases that do not have a cure are more stigmatizing than diseases that do have a cure due to the fact that having the disease could become a life (or even perhaps a death) sentence. However, if the disease were to have a treatment or therapy, that were to ease the symptoms of the disease for example, this would be less stigmatizing than a disease that had neither cure nor treatment. Finally, but not less influential in terms of stigma, there is the matter of how a disease is transmitted. Communicable diseases are far more stigmatizing than genetically inherited diseases, due to the fact that there is an element of personal responsibility connected to preventing communicable diseases – particularly blood-borne ones. Because air-borne diseases are far harder to prevent the personal transmission of as compared to blood-borne ones, they can be thought of as less stigmatizing than diseases contracted through the exchange of bodily fluids; while at the same time they are more stigmatizing than genetically inherited diseases. Now for the fourth component, “a rationale is constructed for devaluing, rejecting, and excluding” (Link & Phelan, p 371) persons when they are labeled, set apart and linked to undesirable characteristics. This then ultimately leads to the stigmatized person experiencing some form of status loss and/or discrimination. Link and Phelan write that - 33 - one of the most immediate consequences of “successful negative labeling and stereotyping is a general downward placement of a person in a status hierarchy” (ibid) whereby the status of the stigmatized is reduced in the eyes of the stigmatizer. A valid question here would be if the status reduction is merely perceived or actual. However such a metaphysical question need not be answered because it is enough for such a status loss to be perceived by the stigmatizer for the person to legitimately develop a fear of the repercussions of such a status lowering. Hence, in anticipation of the negative effects of a lowered position in a status hierarchy, one begins to fear the personal rejection that is sure to come (if not only perceived to come) from those around them, ranging from close confidants to more removed members of a community. The expectation of stereotyping, also known as “stigma consciousness,” can become part of a person’s world view. When this happens, a slew of serious negative consequences could follow for the stigmatized person, including a compromised quality of life and low self-esteem regardless of whether anyone in the immediate context of the person has engaged in any obvious forms of discrimination (Link & Phelan, p 374). Such negative consequences are intensified by the very real extent to which a drop in status hierarchy leads to negative modifications affecting things like selection of sexual partners or longevity. As another interjection, I would like to take a moment to expand on the concept of stigmatization’s affect on one’s status hierarchy which thereby can affect one’s selection of sexual partners. To me, this seems like a fairly serious means of discrimination. The logic follows that if someone is diagnosed to be a carrier of a certain genetic disorder – specifically a highly stigmatized one – then presumably others (potential sex partners) will not want to choose that person to be their life partner because of the implications it could have on any potential offspring. Such a mindset is highly discriminatory and could therefore lead to an individual realistically and rationally choosing to not want to know such damning information about him/herself. In such specific instances, Chadwick is correct in asserting that the individual who claims a right not to know can be interpreted as a protective response to a partner’s claim to know such information (for the purposes of making better informed reproductive decisions for him/herself). However, while such an interpretation may be true, it can be equally true that the main motivation for the - 34 - individual to choose not to know stems from a fear of rejection from the partner, predicated on the phenomenon of stigmatization. The fifth and final component of stigma that Link and Phelan note, which deals with power differentials between stigmatized and stigmatizer, has not been emphasized by other authors that write on stigma. As Link and Phelan note, “stigmatized groups often engage in the same kinds of stigma-related processes in their thinking about individuals who are not in their stigmatized group” (Link & Phelan, p 376). However it is precisely the power differential that determines who is actually stigmatized because it is the group that possesses the social, cultural, economic and political power that are able to have their cognitions lead to serious discriminatory consequences. A clear example which Link and Phelan provide is that of patients suffering from serious mental illness that label clinicians as “pill pushers.” Due to patients’ lack of social clout as compared to clinicians, it is actually the patients themselves that are stigmatized, on account of their mental illness, rather than the clinicians. The authors furthermore note that the “amount of stigma that people experience will be profoundly shaped by the relative power of the stigmatized and the stigmatizer” (Link & Phelan, p 378). Therefore the greater the power differential between stigmatized and stigmatizer, the greater the stigma will be experienced by the stigmatized. In addition to elaborating on the various components of stigma, Link and Phelan discuss some of the implications of stigmatization. One of these implications deals with the severe persistence of stigma, i.e. the predicament by which “negative consequences of stigma are so difficult to eradicate” (Link & Phelan, p 379). In order to understand why it is so difficult to eradicate the negative consequences of stigma, one first has to understand that stigmatization comes about due to a range of both flexible and extensive mechanisms. These mechanisms include individual discrimination, structural discrimination, and self-perpetuating discrimination that results from a stigmatized person’s beliefs and behaviors. Each of these three generic mechanisms has various methods that can successfully cause a stigmatized person to experience the negative consequences of stigmatization. Therefore, due to the multiplicity of mechanisms that - 35 - cause stigma, when a stigmatized group counteracts a “specific mechanism that leads to the undesirable outcome they seek to escape” (Link & Phelan, p 380), by either confronting or avoiding the specific mechanism, “the benefit is only temporary because the mechanism that has been blocked or avoided can be easily replaced by another” (ibid). For example, if one were to avoid individual discrimination, by say not finding out if s/he were a carrier for a serious genetic disorder, then the stigma surrounding that certain disease would still prosper, for such mechanisms as structural discrimination and self-perpetuating discrimination can still be in place, effectively maintaining the firm roots for that stigma. Link and Phelan note another and related reason to the persistence of stigma – namely the fact that there are a multitude of associated negative outcomes. Due to this detail, “members of stigmatized groups are disadvantaged in a broad range of life domains” (ibid), such as employment, social relationships, housing and psychological and physical well-being (specifically when health insurance coverage is denied as a result of having or having a predisposition of a stigmatized genetic disorder, for example). Much like in confronting or avoiding the mechanisms that bring about stigma, if one confronts or avoids a stigma-related outcome, other associated negative consequences can crop up in place of the originally blocked or avoided outcome. A clear example of this is John Henryism, whereby physiological signs of distress develop as a means to coping with prolonged exposure to psychological stresses. Thus due to its persistent nature, the solution to the dilemma of stigma is not merely a matter of changing one’s attitude towards the knowledge, as implied by Chadwick’s distinction between morally neutral “knowledge” and the socially conditioned attitudes that are developed towards “knowledge.” In order to seriously deter stigma and its negative consequences, Link and Phelan suggest focusing on two principles. The first of these two principles is that any approach to change stigma must be both multifaceted and multilevel. “It needs to be multifaceted to address the many mechanisms that can lead to disadvantaged outcomes, and it needs to be multilevel to address issues of both individual and structural discrimination” (Link & Phelan, p 381). The second principle for any - 36 - approach that attempts to change stigma is that it must address the fundamental causes of stigma. This entails either changing long held “attitudes and beliefs of powerful groups that lead to labeling, stereotyping, setting apart, devaluing, and discriminating” (ibid) or changing “circumstances so as to limit the power of such groups to make their cognitions the dominant ones” (ibid). As Link and Phelan argue, an approach that combines these two principles is the only way to effectively combat stigma and its effects. Obviously this proposal for effective deterrence of stigmatization cannot happen overnight. Social change takes time and during that transitional time the fact remains that fear of stigmatization can genuinely lead one to not want to know information about him/herself, especially when that information remains capable of stigmatizing the individual. Therefore, I propose that a concept of relational autonomy and its supporting ethic of care approach might be beneficial in addressing both the right not to know debate and the very real and influential social phenomenon of stigmatization. - 37 - Relational Autonomy and Its Application to the Debate - 38 - As previously mentioned in chapter two (see section 2.1), the reader might recall that relational approaches to autonomy emphasize the “vexed relationship between autonomy and socialization” (Mackenzie, p 4). Because persons are socially embedded, agents’ identities and personal choices are formed within the context of social relationships, shaped by a complex of intersecting social determinants such as race, class, gender and ethnicity. Under the relational approach to autonomy relations of dependency are seen as crucial for the development of persons, agents’ sense of themselves and their capacities, meaning that dependency is essentially required for the development and exercise of autonomy. Therefore the implication is that if one does not initially have relations of dependency, then one cannot be fully autonomous. Additionally, maintaining relations of dependency are necessary in order to maintain the capacity for autonomy. By continuing with this logic, it is then not so difficult to imagine that persons often base their choices on the probability that they can continue to maintain relations of dependency. Now particularly in the case of genetic testing, where genes are inherently relational, it seems essential to dissect the issue of autonomous decision making in terms of the social web that they tend to be made. At first glance, it would seem that relational autonomy would suggest that a right not to know simply cannot exist. This is due to relational autonomy’s emphasis on responsibilities to others, arising essentially from its focus on social relations of inter-dependency. Therefore, it would seem logical for example, for a mother to undergo genetic testing in order to determine if she is a carrier of the breast cancer gene, because she owes it to her family to find out such information. In fact, as Nina Hallowell reports in her article “Doing the right thing: genetic risk and responsibility,” many women who attend genetics clinics do so from a perception of “having a responsibility to their kin (past, present and future generations) to establish the magnitude of their risk and the risks to other family members, and to act upon this information by engaging in some form of risk management” (Hallowell, p 597). In this way, these women present themselves as “interdependent” selves, as opposed to individuated or autonomous agents. It is precisely this feeling of genetic responsibility to - 39 - others that causes these women to forego their right not to know their genetic risks. (However, it could be argued, especially from a classical, liberal standpoint on autonomy, that the possible associations of guilt generated by one’s feeling of genetic responsibility might actually be threatening one’s autonomy.) Most of us, on the other hand, live in a liberal society, whereby we live our lives for ourselves and not for others. Regardless, this does not mean that we do not take our responsibilities to others into account when making personal decisions, especially when said personal decisions can have an impact on those that one feels responsible towards. Essentially when we lead our lives and make personal decisions a tension continually exists for us all between indifferent individualism and a concern for others. In making decisions one does not necessarily always have to choose to follow his/her free and independent will. The person may willfully and reasonably choose to subordinate his/her own interests to the perceived collective interest of others (i.e. relatives). On the other hand, one does not have to do this. Nor does it necessarily qualify as selfish if one chooses to not know. For if finding out certain information meant that an individual’s world and identity would probably crumble and thereby lead one to a wretched state where life looses meaning for him/her, then it would seem at worst masochistic and at best irresponsible for one to willingly choose to break one’s sanity for the sake of his/her obligations to others. This is precisely where a care of ethics approach comes into play. Contrary to the implications brought on by the term “care,” a care of ethics approach does not dictate that individuals should be selfless and totally unconcerned with one’s own well-being. Instead, care ethics highlight how individuals’ empathy and empathic concern for others “occurs against a background of natural and persisting concern for one’s own wellbeing” (Slote, p 116). In fact, this self-concern sets limits as to how much empathy or concern an individual can have for others. Empathy that goes unchecked would render an individual practically incapacitated for s/he would never be able to get anything done because s/he would not be able to properly care for his/her own needs. As trite as it may sound, one must care for oneself before s/he can genuinely care for others. Therefore, it - 40 - would be completely rational and in accordance with both relational autonomy and a care ethics perspective for an individual to choose to not know results of a genetic test that has a serious potential to demolish one’s self-image, self-esteem, and sanity all in one fell swoop. In this way, maintaining one’s (possibly misguided) self-image by choosing to not know does not necessarily trump but can actually contribute to principles of solidarity and responsibility, because such a decision can be made in order to care for oneself thereby enabling him/her to help care for others. 5.1 SHALLOW VERSUS DEEP CONCEPTIONS OF RELATIONAL AUTONOMY I now wish to turn to the issue of how relational autonomy can adequately address the dilemma of stigmatization. Just as there are numerous ways to dissect the familiar and well-established concept of individual autonomy (as discussed in the first chapter), there also are many different ways to approach the concept of relational autonomy. Mackenzie and Stoljar, for example, propose a distinction between constitutive conceptions of relational autonomy and causal conceptions. The former focuses on social constitutions of the agent or the social nature of the capacity of autonomy itself, while the latter focuses on ways in which socialization and social relationships impede or enhance autonomy. In reviewing the literature on relational autonomy, I was particularly struck by Diana Meyers’ answer to the feminist conundrum of women in oppressed societies autonomously choosing “warped desires.” Her proposed solution is that “not all desires should be afforded equal credence or weight” (Mackenzie & Stoljar, p 18). According to Meyers, the uncritical acceptance of social norms or expectations does not yield real autonomous desires. Only “through the exercise of skills of self-discovery, selfdefinition, and self-direction” (ibid) can one develop actual autonomous desires. Influenced by such reasoning, I would like to propose another distinction with regards to relational autonomy, especially with respect to the right not to know debate – a shallow versus deep conception of relational autonomy. Within the shallow conception (“shallow” as in accepting something at face value), any and all societal and/or cultural influences are considered valid influences on one’s autonomy. The shallow construction of relational autonomy highlights human beings’ inherent need to feel as part of a social unit or group (see Kurzban & Leary, p 187). In this way, even stigmatization is relevant - 41 - and acceptable to shape one’s personal choices. In contrast to Andorno’s assertion that the right not to know cannot be absolute, the shallow construction would argue that it is absolute, based on any individual’s perceived fear of stigmatization. However, as Mackenzie and Stoljar cite, John Christman believes that critical reflection yields autonomy only when processes of reflection have not been influenced by “illegitimate external influences.” As he explains, critical reflection is necessary in order to determine whether influences are illegitimate. If an agent revises his/her identifications, due to becoming aware of external influences through the process of critical reflection, then such influences indeed are illegitimate. Therefore, if we follow Christman’s criteria, if one were to fully dissect the reasons why s/he did not want to know certain information and the result essentially came down to acknowledging that one feared becoming stigmatized, then the real question remains if said acknowledgment and realization leads him/her to change his/her desire to know said information. However, as understood from above, stigmatization is a fairly thorny matter in that it can be internalized and thus self-perpetuating. So how can one separate him/herself from thinking those thoughts which perpetuate particular stigmas and determine if stigma is a legitimate influence on his/her decision-making process? In order to solve this problem, let’s try a thought experiment. For the purposes of this experiment, let’s say that there is the possibility of finding out if someone is a carrier of a late onset genetic condition which is highly stigmatized due to a number of factors: 1) there is no cure for it, 2) there is no treatment for it, 3) very few people in the world are affected by it, and 4) it causes one’s skin to turn blue. It would be perfectly rational for an individual to choose not to know if s/he is the carrier of such a condition because it could shatter his/her self-perception and lead to other negative consequences including lower quality of life and depression. Now say we were to slowly work on destigmatizing the condition, first of all by developing an effective albeit costly makeup product that allows them to hide the blue condition of their skin. The same individual still might rationally choose not to know such information if they believe that they would not be able to access such makeup due to financial constraints. Now let’s say that all the - 42 - initial conditions remain the same, but that the cost of the makeup has dropped and is now tenable for that individual, meaning that there still is no cure and very few people in the world are affected by this condition. I emphasize the aspect that few people in the world remain afflicted by this condition because it could certainly influence a person’s perception of how life would be for him/her (i.e. fairly isolating). Certainly it seems within the limits of reason that the person choose to not want to live such a life, that it is not in accordance with his/her view of the “good life” and how s/he particularly wants to live it. Now let’s say that a sizeable population is afflicted by the condition which has an affordable makeup cover-up treatment, but still no cure. Is it still valid for the person to reject knowing if they are a carrier of this disease? At this point, the disease is much less stigmatized than at first portrayed in our thought-experiment. In correlation, it seems to be less rational for one to choose to not know if they are a carrier for such a condition. What this thought-experiment seems to prove is that just as stigma is a matter of degree, the rationality applicable to rejecting to know information about a condition is contingent upon the degree of stigma it could confer upon an individual were one to be diagnosed with it. The thought-experiment also proves how the relational approach to autonomy is better equipped to deal with such issues (of stigma) as compared to individual approaches because relational approaches fully grasp the importance of maintaining social relations and how such considerations can easily factor into individuals’ choices (with regard to knowing information). In this way, relational autonomy seems to be a best of both worlds device that incorporates the values of both individual autonomy and a care ethics perspective. Now, relational approaches to autonomy are particularly concerned with analyzing the role that social norms and institutions, cultural practices and social relationships play in shaping beliefs, desires and attitudes of agents. Additionally, relational autonomy examines the development of competencies and capacities necessary for autonomy, such as self-reflection, self-direction and self-knowledge. Oppressive socialization and oppressive social relationships can impede autonomous agency, particularly when they restrict agents’ freedom by limiting the range of significant options that are available to them. Once internalized, oppressive socialization practices can block agents’ capacities - 43 - for detecting whether the norms are right. This point leads me to what I would like to propose as the deep conception of relational autonomy (“deep” as in delving through layers of matter in order to get to the heart of it all), whereby not all societal or cultural influences are valid. Like the aforementioned authenticity models of individual autonomy (refer to section 1.1), the deep conception of relational autonomy necessitates critical reflection in order to discern between legitimate and illegitimate social influences on one’s autonomy. Under the deep conception of relational autonomy, stigma can be comprehended as invalid in influencing one’s identity and personal preferences because it seems to be self-imposed or perpetuated (i.e. perceived subjectively rather than objectively actualized). While there are various determinants of stigma that can be measured, it is not necessarily an objective fact but rather considered to be a matter of subjective degree, particularly on a micro, or individual, level. In this way, the deep conception of relational autonomy harshly judges influencing factors to be valid strictly based upon lines of objective reality. Additionally in using the deep conception, stigmatization can be judged to be a subverting influence on one’s autonomy because stigma can be seen as originating from society at large, rather than a particular individual who is close to a stigmatized person. And as I have mentioned before, relational autonomy does not prescribe to the notion of blindly accepting any and all relationships as crucial to one’s autonomous decision-making. Only those relations that are close to and constructive of one’s identity are critically relevant to one’s autonomy. Although, because a society’s general notions of stigma can be internalized on an individual level, then those persons that are close to the stigmatized individual could potentially personally harbor said stigmatizing thoughts and feelings. This therefore leads me to speculate that perhaps it is best not to conceive the deep and shallow conceptions of relational autonomy as either/or concepts, meaning that one should only adopt either a deep or shallow conception of relational autonomy when dealing with the issue of a right not to know. Instead, it might be better to view deep and shallow as endpoints on a continuum. After all, not all genetic disorders or predispositions are equally stigmatized. For example, with the medical progress in terms of chemotherapies, cancer is not necessarily a death sentence anymore, especially varying - 44 - with regard to the type of cancer. So if genetic testing were to determine a predisposition to developing a certain type of cancer, it might not be as stigmatizing as compared to a diagnosis of Huntington’s disease. Of course, the stigma associated with cancer has lessened not only due to medical progress in terms of treatment, but also because it has become normalized, largely due to the fact that the number of people affected by the disease has grown exponentially over the past few decades, as opposed to those affected by say a “rarer” disease such as Huntington’s. Therefore, perhaps the best way to approach the right not to know using a relational approach would be to consider the specific case and what degree of stigma is involved. Although this approach is particularly relevant when the fear of stigmatization is the most influential factor in an individual’s choice to not know certain information, it is also applicable in cases where the fear of stigmatization is merely one of several contributing factors to that person’s decision. And so in summary, the fear of stigmatization can be a valid influencing factor for an individual deciding to not know information resulting from a genetic test. The degree to which a condition is stigmatized is relevant in determining the validity of its influence in such a decision. Owing to human beings’ innate need to “belong” to social groups, the higher the degree for which a condition is stigmatized, the more likely one will validly fear having or developing said condition, due to the negative social ramifications (i.e. ostracism) that are likely to occur for an individual that has the condition. Conversely, conditions which are stigmatized to a relatively low degree should not foster such fears. If such fears arise in an individual with respect to a condition that is not highly stigmatized, then they would be irrationally based because there would be a low probability that negative social outcomes would ensue for an individual solely as a result of having said condition. In using a relational approach to autonomy, somewhere between a shallow and deep conception, depending upon the specific genetic condition that is being tested, one can determine if fears of stigmatization are substantiated enough to warrant a rational choice in not knowing whether one has or has the propensity of developing said condition. Highly stigmatized genetic conditions should be paired with a relational autonomy approach that skews towards a shallow construction with regard to - 45 - the issue of not knowing, thereby validating an individual’s autonomous choice to not know. Alternatively, if the specific genetic condition is not highly stigmatized, or stigmatized to a relatively low degree, then the relational autonomy approach should be skewed towards a deep construction, thereby invalidating an individual’s choice to not know based on an irrational fear of stigmatization. All of this – stigmatization and relational autonomy in both its shallow and deep conceptions – adds another dimension to the right not to know debate; a dimension that has not been previously addressed with traditional notions of autonomy. - 46 - Conclusion - 47 - The relational approach to autonomy can both affirm and negate a right not to know, at least with respect to genetic testing. While the classic individual approach to autonomy sees moral questions in terms of rights, the relational approach, with its focus on interdependence, comprehends moral questions in terms of responsibilities. Therefore, one could frame the debate of a right not to know as either a duty to know due to humans’ interdependence or a responsibility to not harm, depending on which stance of the argument with which one sides. For those that view the matter in terms of a duty to know, the individual essentially subjugates his/her desires to those of others for whom s/he feels responsible towards. However, for those living in a liberal society, no one is required to do such a thing. Regardless, relational autonomy clearly underscores the reasoning behind such “sacrificial” decision-making, for one’s obligations felt towards his/her relatives could validly influence his/her autonomous preferences. On the other hand, relational autonomy also supports claims for a responsibility (on the part of physicians) to not harm their patients in telling them information that they themselves would render as devastating for themselves. As Strasser argues, no one other than the patient can best determine if such information is capable of devastating him/her. As I’ve tried to construct my argument, a relational approach to autonomy focuses on human relations and the influence those relations have on an individual’s decisionmaking process. Considering human beings’ fundamental need to “belong” and be part of a community, stigmatization can rightfully cause one to fear the consequences of knowing particular information about oneself, particularly if said information has the potential to negatively influence one’s social relations. However, not all stigmatization should be considered a valid factor in influencing one’s decision to not know information. It is essentially the degree of stigma for which a particular condition or disease could confer upon an afflicted individual that correlates to the probability of harm and validity of the influence. I therefore agree with Andorno’s position that the right not to know cannot be absolute, especially in terms of basing such decisions on a fear of stigmatization. While I cannot suggest a definite threshold for stigma which would determine a certainty of harm and validity of influence, one should consider a specific condition in respect of a spectrum of stigma. If a condition tends to be on the higher side - 48 - of the spectrum, then the fear of stigmatization can be considered a valid and thereby rational influencing factor upon an individual choosing to not know certain genetic information. In contrast, if the condition is on the lower side of the stigma spectrum, then relational autonomy cannot support an individual’s claim to not want to know genetic information for fear of the stigmatization that knowing would inflict upon him/her. Conditions that are not so stigmatizing are therefore not likely to cause harm to the individual in terms of socialization (i.e. one would not likely be shunned by the community, especially by those relations that are of supreme importance to the individual). Furthermore, I combined a relational autonomy approach to the right not to know debate with elements of an ethics of care perspective. In doing this, one understands one’s choice to not know about a stigmatizing condition as fairly rational and anything but selfish. In fact, it would be highly responsible for a caring individual to not want to know about a genetic condition, particularly when knowing such information could shatter that individual’s world and identity to the point that it would change them entirely and perhaps for the worse. In order to remain an individual capable of entering into and maintaining caring and interdependent relations with others, then s/he must care for him/herself. An essential component of that requires one to maintain his/her sanity, selfesteem and identity. If not knowing a genetic status is part of that, then so be it. For the purposes of brevity for this thesis, I focused on the right not to know debate with regard to finding out information from a physician. Obviously there are further complications with a right not to know involved in an individual finding out genetic information and then deciding whether or not to share that information with relatives. Do relatives have a right not to know such information, especially if it comes up in casual, informal discussions? The purview of this thesis does not address such specific instances. Additionally, I did not adequately address the burden of acquiring knowledge in terms of one’s responsibility to then share that information with others. For example, if one were - 49 - to find out that s/he were a carrier for Tay-Sachs, would s/he then be required to inform his/her partner about said predisposition, particularly if both partners were planning on having children together. If an individual were reasonably afraid of his/her partner’s rejection based upon a genetic predisposition, then it seems that the relational autonomy principle and a care of ethics perspective is not sufficient enough to determine a decision one way or the other, for the quality of life of the possibly afflicted offspring also comes into play. 6.1 FURTHER APPLICATIONS As for other sorts of testing – not solely genetic testing – relational autonomy cannot necessarily support a right not to know, particularly when a high probability of mortality or serious morbidity is at stake. Such examples can entail HIV/AIDS or tuberculosis, or even newly discovered air and blood-borne diseases that as of yet do not have a cure or adequate treatment. I agree with Zimmerli’s contention that public health can definitely trump individual rights. The public’s right to life, and a relatively healthy one at that, surpasses an individual’s right to reject knowing information that has the potential to stigmatize said individual. While stigmatization is obviously difficult to eradicate, due to its persistent nature, efforts should be made to seriously eradicate it lest masses go untested and untreated due to individuals’ fear of the negative consequences of stigma associated with such diseases. On the other hand, there are contagious diseases that do not have cures but have successful therapies associated with them, that nonetheless carry with them a relatively high degree of stigma. What easily comes to mind as examples of this are the sexually transmitted diseases of HPV and herpes. Research has yet to prove definitive links between such diseases and negative effects on reproduction or even predispositions for acquiring later onset diseases (such as cervical cancer). Currently a number of studies suggest that there are certain correlations. At this point in time, it might be wise to stay cautious and not allow an individual’s fears of stigmatization to trump aims of public health. - 50 - Thus, relational autonomy can not always support a right not to know information about having a certain disease. It largely depends upon the kind of disease and the numbers that are potentially affected by said disease. The fewer the number of people that could become affected by a disease, such as with genetic diseases that are limited to the individual and his/her progeny, then the greater the validity of one’s claim to a right not to know, based upon relational autonomy. However the same does not hold true for far more infectious diseases, especially those that cause high morbidity and/or mortality. - 51 - REFERENCES Andorno, R. “The right not to know: an autonomy based approach.” Journal of Medical Ethics. Vol. 30, pp 435-440. (2004) Chadwick, R. “The philosophy of the right to know and the right not to know.” The Right to Know and the Right not to Know. Avebury. (1997) Chadwick, R., Levitt, M. and Shickle D. “Introduction.” The Right to Know and the Right not to Know. Avebury. (1997) Fulda, K. and Lykens, K. “Ethical issues in predictive genetic testing: a public health perspective.” Journal of Medical Ethics. Vol. 32, pp 143-147. (2006) Hallowell, N. “Doing the right thing: genetic risk and responsibility.” Sociology of Health and Illness. Vol. 21, No. 5, pp 597-621. (1999) Kurzban, R. and Leary, M. “Evolutionary Origins of Stigmatization: The Functions of Social Exclusion.” Psychological Bulletin. Vol. 127, No. 2, pp 187-208. (2001) Link, B. and Phelan, J. “Conceptualizing Stigma.” Annual Review of Sociology. Vol. 27, pp 363-385. (2001) Mackenzie, C. and Stoljar, N. “Introduction: Autonomy Refigured.” Relational Autonomy: Feminist Perspectives on Autonomy, Agency, and the Social Self. Oxford University Press. (2000) O’Donovan, K. and Gilbar, R. “The loved ones: families, intimates and patient autonomy.” Legal Studies. Vol. 23, 332-358. (2003) - 52 - O’Neil, O. Autonomy and Trust in Bioethics. Cambridge University Press. (2002) Ost, D. “The ‘Right’ Not to Know.” Medicine and Philosophy. Vol. 9, pp 301-312. (1984) Schermer, M. The Different Faces of Autonomy – A Study on Patient Autonomy in Ethical Theory and Hospital Practice. Universiteit van Amsterdam. (2001) Shickle, D. “Do ‘all men desire to know’? A right of society to choose not to know about the genetics of personality traits.” The Right to Know and the Right not to Know. Avebury. (1997) Slote, M. The Ethics of Care and Empathy. Routledge. (2007) Strasser, M. “Mill and the Right to Remain Uninformed.” Medicine and Philosophy. Vol. 11, pp 265-278. (1986) Timmons, M. Moral Theory – An Introduction. Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, Inc. (2002) Verkerk, M. “The care perspective and autonomy.” Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy. Vol. 4, pp 289-294. (2001) World Medical Association. WMA Statement on Genetics and Medicine. http://www.wma.net/en/30publications/10policies/g11/index.html 2009) - 53 - (adopted 2005, amended