The paper was attempting, very recklessly and compressedly, to tell a single story (because I think it is a single story) which might, I now see, have been better presented in three parts. In the light of the questions, I plan to separate them out roughly as follows: The first part of the story is about sovereignty. This part of the story tells how sovereignty replaced jurisdictional thinking as the default mode of theorising about politics. This had the effect of replacing multiple sites of decision in different political bodies with a single site of decision in a single body which monopolises political authority. I wanted to show, firstly, that thinking about churches was central to this story and, secondly, that it cannot be separated from a parallel story about the legitimacy of the decisions taken, which is driven by the growing sentiment of individual selfdetermination that was spreading through Europe at the time, especially in religious and commercial activities. These two stories converge in Hobbes, where the identification of the state as the single site of authoritative decision is paralleled by an explanation of the state as a framework of obligations individually undertaken: all rational individuals will to live under the same laws. Subsequent western political thought (as I take it) follows in these footsteps one way or another. I used Richard Baxter to try to show the strains that the attempt to combine the two stories generates, in two directions: against the state as the single source of authoritative decision in the one direction and against individual selfdetermination in the other (sects vs. the national church). This dynamic, I suggested, was taken by Carl Schmitt to typify modern political thinking and practice: individual selfassertion in the realm of values threatened to escalate into a massively destructive freefor-all, and in the realm of politics it threatened to destroy the authority of the state from the inside. Schmitt thought that Weber, Kelsen, and indeed most of his contemporaries, were infected by the logic which produced it. At the same time I was trying to tell another story, about how Weber had diagnosed a problem in modern German political thinking and practice, a problem about the relationship between norms and facts. On the one hand there were norms which presented themselves authoritatively. On the other hand there was the phenomenon of mass obedience. The problem was to account for the convergence between the two stories distinguished above in this case: how, if at all, could the state be understood as a site of voluntarily incurred obligation rather than simply as a scene of domination? [Hobbes vs Baxter?] The solution was to change the way in which consensus, or agreement, was located intellectually, from a presupposition of legitimacy to an outcome of various legitimate processes which, taken together, validated the obedience which otherwise had no obvious intellectual location (in practice, of course, it could be given or withheld) and made it plausible to continue to claim that in some sense the people governed themselves. I used Kelsen and Schmitt to illustrate how this claim, and its grounds, could be interpreted in radically different ways. I deliberately left the differences between the two unresolved, in order to show, as I hoped, the importance of the wider imaginative frameworks which reconcile our normative claims and the facts of the matter. This point about the constitutive role of fictions in political understanding was the moral of the second story, and, suitably expanded, this is what the substance of the read paper will be turned towards. The third part of the story, in some ways the most important and the least well articulated, was what I struggled to communicate in response to questions, especially Kinch's question. What I wanted to say was that the idea of popular sovereignty combines within its own terms the contradictory tendencies that mark out modern European political thinking. So, when I said that, for us, if politics is simply domination, it isn't politics, I meant that we conceive of modern politics in terms that are held in tension between the poles of fatalism and voluntarism (I went back to the birth of modern European politics in the paper to try to show this), and that the vitality of western political thinking is a product of the unresolved competition between the tendencies towards one or the other pole. It is possible to imagine the victory of one side in this struggle, but the results would not be conceivable in the terms in which we currently think. I guess I had in mind, or rather have in mind, something like Michael Oakeshott's vision of an ongoing battle of styles (the politics of faith and the politics of scepticism) which are always present in some proportion and which find their reflection in differences of emphasis, direction of attention and so on (so Hume is different from Hobbes in some ways, as Paul suggested, but he is also like Hobbes in other ways, so sometimes the distribution f goods is emphasised over the inhibition of mass slaughter), and that political thinking is always about finding a way of keeping the two tendencies together without overbalancing in either direction.