Black Athena and the Fabrication of the Rhetorical Tradition James Arnt Aune Texas A & M University Perhaps the most chilling moment of Martin Bernal's Black Athena occurs in Chapter IX, where he reviews the history of anti-Semitism in Northern Europe and North America, especially in colleges and universities. He cites a letter found in 1980 on the desk of Harry Caplan of Cornell, "who was for many years the only Jewish tenured professor of the subject in the Ivy League": My dear Caplan: I want to second Professor Bristol's advice and urge you to get into secondary teaching. The opportunities for college positions, never too many, are at present few and likely to be fewer. I can encourage no one to look forward to securing a college post. There is, moreover, a very real prejudice against the Jew. Personally, I do not share this, and I am sure the same is true of all our staff here. But we have seen so many well-equipped Jews fail to secure appointments that this fact has been forced upon us. . . . I feel it is wrong to encourage anyone to devote himself to the higher walks of learning to whom the path is barred by an undeniable racial prejudice. In this I am joined by all my Classical colleagues, who have authorized me to append their signatures with my own to this letter. (signed) Charles E. Bennet, C.L. Durham, George S. Bristol, E.P. Andrews [27/3/1919] Ithaca. Bernal probably doesn't know or care about the rest of the story here, but I take some comfort in the fact that not only did Caplan not "get into secondary teaching," but became an instructor in the department of Public Speaking at Cornell from 1919 to 1923, at which point he was actually able to join the Classics department. It is possible, of course, to make too much of this incident, but it seems strangely appropriate for beginning a paper on the implications of Bernal's book for rhetorical studies. Black Athena makes the bold claim that the "paradigm" that classical scholars and classics-inspired scholars have used to discuss both the importance of Greek civilization and its origins has been directly and indirectly influenced by racism and European chauvinism. The ancient Greeks themselves believed that their culture had arisen as the result of colonization, around 1500 B.C.E., by Egyptians and Phoenicians who had civilized the native inhabitants. This belief, which Bernal calls the "Ancient Model," was displaced after the 18th century by various versions of what he calls the "Aryan model," in which Greek civilization was seen as the result of an invasion from the North that had taken over the local "Aegean" or "pre-Hellenic" culture. Egyptian influence was denied, and Greek civilization was seen both as the finest moment of human achievement (itself a relatively new cultural valuation) and as the product of the mixture of the Indo-European-speaking Hellenes and their indigenous subjects. This denial of Egyptian influence on Greek civilization went hand in hand with the general devaluation of Egypt. The most surprising aspect of Bernal's history of the Ancient and Aryan Model is his documentation of the prestige of Egypt among such diverse groups as the Cambridge Platonists, writers of the Italian Renaissance, and the Freemasons. The "Aryan model," is not only wrong, on archaeological and linguistic grounds, as further volumes of Black Athena will attempt to demonstrate, but it is also wrong for a reason. The Norwegian political philosopher Jon Elster has pointed out that a distinctive feature of modern discussions of political and social theory is its obsession (derived from Marx) with identifying not only mistaken political and social beliefs, but with explaining why those mistaken beliefs have emerged. It is useful to locate Black Athena within the tradition of Marxist historiography, and to note that it represents a (oh, how I hate this word) postmodern Marxist attempt to place racial issues at the center of explanations of oppression. Bernal, whose father J.D. Bernal was one of the great "scientific Marxists" along with J.B.S. Haldane in England (and an unrepentant Stalinist as well), rather refreshingly helps us locate his project within his own life history. A one time Maoist who made his scholarly reputation in Chinese and Vietnamese history, Bernal appears to have had a mid-life crisis connected with the collapse of the Chinese revolution in the 1970's. Like many left academics, he has not abandoned the view of historical explanation he found in Marx, but has attempted to balance discussions of class with discussions of race. The story of the rise of the Aryan model reads a bit like a detective story (Murder on the Orient Express comes to mind as an alternative subtitle) in which the list of murderers includes anti-Semitic German university professors, Romantic racists, and the usual upper-class British imperialists. Capitalism does not really appear in the book, but it is an interesting exercise to read Bernal's book side-by-side with Terry Eagleton's new book, The Ideology of the Aesthetic, which traces the relationship of modern aesthetics to capitalism during the same periods covered by Bernal. Bernal usefully draws our attention to the relatively new character of racism and anti-Semitism as products of the Enlightenment and the Romantic Movement, but he may miss the extent to which the dissociation of sensibility wrought by industrial capitalism created psychological conditions in which a search for a lost cultural wholeness in ancient Greece was inevitable. More generally, even if one rejects both Bernal's use of racism as an explanatory principle or the more classical Marxist use of capitalism as an explanatory principle, Bernal helps us see more clearly the social forces that underlie the revaluation of civilizations, periods, and texts. Discussions of the nature of the "canon" in literary studies and the by now wearisome debates over the undergraduate core curriculum indicate that we are once again at one of those significant points in the history of Western culture that Bernal so unforgettably documents in the case of the "fabrication of ancient Greece." The rise of the Aryan model and search for lost cultural unity are of particular significance for students of rhetoric, for whom scholarship is inevitably an exercise in nostalgia. The purpose of this paper is to discuss Bernal's book in the context of certain key problems in contemporary rhetorical studies, especially the vexing issue of how to write the history of the Western rhetorical tradition and how to talk about the legitimacy of the classical rhetorical tradition in an increasingly multicultural university climate. I intend to range rather widely across Bernal's work in the hope of stimulating conversation and research into its implications. I will begin by locating some key issues in contemporary rhetorical studies, then discuss the scholarly reception of Bernal's work, and conclude by suggesting how his work might solve the issues with which I began. In Search of Ariadne's Thread, Revisited In 1978 Michael Leff published an essay that traced certain emerging patterns in rhetorical scholarship after the breakup of neo-Aristotelianism and the rise of social-scientific views of communication. He found a unifying theme in the notion of rhetoric as a way of knowing. Things have changed considerably in twelve years. Although rhetorical scholarship is arguably in a more secure position, both within the Speech Communication Association and in the academy generally, than twelve years ago, any attempt to discern patterns, much less consensus, among rhetorical scholars seems impossible. The mania for specialization that long ago led to the split between speech and theater and later between rhetorical studies and communication studies has occurred within rhetorical studies as well. Speculative rhetorical theory, seemingly a growth industry in the heady days of the early 1980's, has ceased to be of interest to most students of rhetoric, even though the opportunity to make connections with similar developments in literary studies was missed. Instead, public address studies is the subject of almost all the important book-length work in our field, some of it from university presses that ten years ago would not have touched a manuscript from a "speech" person. Although some theoretical self-consciousness is present in the recent turn to close readings of public address, that self-consciousness is probably at its lowest point in the history of rhetorical criticism, a sign perhaps of increased disciplinary maturity. Where theoretical terms are used, the best critics seem to do so in the spirit of Levi-Strauss's bricoleur, borrowing a term from Cicero here, and Foucault there. The history of rhetorical theory has emerged as a distinctive subfield, with the founding of the journal Rhetorica, although that journal quite rightly operates under more rigorous and largely atheoretical standards appropriate to its audience. A more interdisciplinary group of scholars who began as students of argumentation and debate have developed a full-fledged movement in the rhetoric of science and the rhetoric of inquiry. Other developing interest groups include women's studies and performance studies. All this diversity of interest is exciting, although it makes for confusion when people in smaller colleges and universities search for a sense of self-definition or have to justify their existence in terms of core curricula. My own college is currently going through a curriculum review in which it is difficult to explain where "speech" courses fit within normal patterns of distribution requirements. We are in a Fine Arts division and our courses currently fulfill that requirement, but "real" Fine Arts people (in art, music, and dance) understandably resent the fact that, say, small group communication falls under the heading of the Fine Arts. Virtually everyone at my institution understands that rhetoric is a central part of the liberal arts tradition and that public speaking is a "useful skill," but it is virtually impossible for anyone, least of all me, to figure out where our department should fit within the divisional structure of the college. Another way in which the increased scholarly prestige of rhetorical/communication studies may have unintended consequences is that not only is it very difficult for small colleges, even those like mine with fairly stringent research expectations, to attract top candidates for positions, but it is very unlikely that those top candidates could be trusted to teach a beginning public speaking course with even a minimal level of competence. We are now approaching the situation of English as a discipline, in which the radical separation of training in writing and in teaching literature has existed for several years. Now these are very practical questions, and they seem to fall very far afield from Bernal's book, but in a way they do fit in with this discussion. Before the Fall (by which I mean 1965, when Edwin Black's Rhetorical Criticism: A Study in Method was published, and the first major burst of the social-scientific assault began), it was relatively easy to defend "Speech" within the two premises that defined American college education. Those two premises can be summarized under the names Aristotle and John Dewey. Rhetoricians could have it both ways. That is, the democratic (some would say levelling) impulses of Dewey's education for citizenship authorized debate programs, courses in group discussion, and courses in persuasion. The liberal arts (some would say elitist) tradition justified courses in rhetorical criticism and public address. The notion that there was perhaps some tension between these two traditions of education seldom occurred to speech people before the Fall, but the tension came out most clearly when interpersonal communication, later organizational communication, began to edge out the earlier, dare I call it, Ancient Model. It is utterly unclear, given both the increased fragmentation of rhetorical studies and its increased detachment from its Deweyan roots, what the organizing principle, paradigm if you will, for rhetorical studies is. Despite the occasional nod to Chinese or Indian or Arabic rhetoric, we have not really systematically questioned either the continuing use of the classical rhetorical tradition means as a legitimating device or how well it continues to function as a vocabulary for teaching critical or performance skills. There is an odd humility to the title of Thomas M. Conley's book, Rhetoric in the European Tradition, but that book, like almost all recent discussions of the broad sweep of "the Tradition" (which as I get older sounds more and more like F.R. Leavis' "Great Tradition" and sounds equally mythical) does not address the question of the Tradition's origins or continued legitimacy. It remains to be seen how the field of communication will be reconfigured after the curricular wars have died down. My own instinct is that we are collectively in search of what Henry Louis Gates, Jr., calls a search for a "myth of origins," and that myth of origins can no longer usefully be described in Greco-Roman terms. It is not clear, however, that "multiculturalism" in its current forms has a clearly articulated myth of origins, either, save a radicalized view of New Deal interest group politics. A more anthropological view of rhetoric and communication, based on the complex relationship between orality and literacy, and examining the social forces underlying shifts in rhetorical theory and practice, seems to me to provide a way of linking together the fragmentary impulses that we know as rhetorical studies, performance studies, cultural studies, and communication studies. Such an anthropological view also seems more congenial to the Deweyan, democratic strain in American rhetorical studies that provided the foundation for the best of our pedagogy, if not, finally, our research. It is in light of these reflections on the fragmentation of contemporary rhetorical scholarship, the search for an appropriate "paradigm" for rhetorical studies, and the largely ignored issue of rhetorical pedagogy that I now wish to turn to the scholarly reception of Bernal's work. In 1978 Michael Leff published an essay that traced certain emerging patterns in rhetorical scholarship after the breakup of neo-Aristotelianism and the rise of social-scientific views of communication. He found a unifying theme in the notion of rhetoric as a way of knowing. Things have changed considerably in twelve years. Although rhetorical scholarship is arguably in a more secure position, both within the Speech Communication Association and in the academy generally, than twelve years ago, any attempt to discern patterns, much less consensus, among rhetorical scholars seems impossible. The mania for specialization that long ago led to the split between speech and theater and later between rhetorical studies and communication studies has occurred within rhetorical studies as well. Speculative rhetorical theory, seemingly a growth industry in the heady days of the early 1980's, has ceased to be of interest to most students of rhetoric, even though the opportunity to make connections with similar developments in literary studies was missed. Instead, public address studies is the subject of almost all the important book-length work in our field, some of it from university presses that ten years ago would not have touched a manuscript from a "speech" person. Although some theoretical self-consciousness is present in the recent turn to close readings of public address, that self-consciousness is probably at its lowest point in the history of rhetorical criticism, a sign perhaps of increased disciplinary maturity. Where theoretical terms are used, the best critics seem to do so in the spirit of Levi-Strauss's bricoleur, borrowing a term from Cicero here, and Foucault there. The history of rhetorical theory has emerged as a distinctive subfield, with the founding of the journal Rhetorica, although that journal quite rightly operates under more rigorous and largely atheoretical standards appropriate to its audience. A more interdisciplinary group of scholars who began as students of argumentation and debate have developed a full-fledged movement in the rhetoric of science and the rhetoric of inquiry. Other developing interest groups include women's studies and performance studies. All this diversity of interest is exciting, although it makes for confusion when people in smaller colleges and universities search for a sense of self-definition or have to justify their existence in terms of core curricula. My own college is currently going through a curriculum review in which it is difficult to explain where "speech" courses fit within normal patterns of distribution requirements. We are in a Fine Arts division and our courses currently fulfill that requirement, but "real" Fine Arts people (in art, music, and dance) understandably resent the fact that, say, small group communication falls under the heading of the Fine Arts. Virtually everyone at my institution understands that rhetoric is a central part of the liberal arts tradition and that public speaking is a "useful skill," but it is virtually impossible for anyone, least of all me, to figure out where our department should fit within the divisional structure of the college. Another way in which the increased scholarly prestige of rhetorical/communication studies may have unintended consequences is that not only is it very difficult for small colleges, even those like mine with fairly stringent research expectations, to attract top candidates for positions, but it is very unlikely that those top candidates could be trusted to teach a beginning public speaking course with even a minimal level of competence. We are now approaching the situation of English as a discipline, in which the radical separation of training in writing and in teaching literature has existed for several years. Now these are very practical questions, and they seem to fall very far afield from Bernal's book, but in a way they do fit in with this discussion. Before the Fall (by which I mean 1965, when Edwin Black's Rhetorical Criticism: A Study in Method was published, and the first major burst of the social-scientific assault began), it was relatively easy to defend "Speech" within the two premises that defined American college education. Those two premises can be summarized under the names Aristotle and John Dewey. Rhetoricians could have it both ways. That is, the democratic (some would say levelling) impulses of Dewey's education for citizenship authorized debate programs, courses in group discussion, and courses in persuasion. The liberal arts (some would say elitist) tradition justified courses in rhetorical criticism and public address. The notion that there was perhaps some tension between these two traditions of education seldom occurred to speech people before the Fall, but the tension came out most clearly when interpersonal communication, later organizational communication, began to edge out the earlier, dare I call it, Ancient Model. It is utterly unclear, given both the increased fragmentation of rhetorical studies and its increased detachment from its Deweyan roots, what the organizing principle, paradigm if you will, for rhetorical studies is. Despite the occasional nod to Chinese or Indian or Arabic rhetoric, we have not really systematically questioned either the continuing use of the classical rhetorical tradition means as a legitimating device or how well it continues to function as a vocabulary for teaching critical or performance skills. There is an odd humility to the title of Thomas M. Conley's book, Rhetoric in the European Tradition, but that book, like almost all recent discussions of the broad sweep of "the Tradition" (which as I get older sounds more and more like F.R. Leavis' "Great Tradition" and sounds equally mythical) does not address the question of the Tradition's origins or continued legitimacy. It remains to be seen how the field of communication will be reconfigured after the curricular wars have died down. My own instinct is that we are collectively in search of what Henry Louis Gates, Jr., calls a search for a "myth of origins," and that myth of origins can no longer usefully be described in Greco-Roman terms. It is not clear, however, that "multiculturalism" in its current forms has a clearly articulated myth of origins, either, save a radicalized view of New Deal interest group politics. A more anthropological view of rhetoric and communication, based on the complex relationship between orality and literacy, and examining the social forces underlying shifts in rhetorical theory and practice, seems to me to provide a way of linking together the fragmentary impulses that we know as rhetorical studies, performance studies, cultural studies, and communication studies. Such an anthropological view also seems more congenial to the Deweyan, democratic strain in American rhetorical studies that provided the foundation for the best of our pedagogy, if not, finally, our research. It is in light of these reflections on the fragmentation of contemporary rhetorical scholarship, the search for an appropriate "paradigm" for rhetorical studies, and the largely ignored issue of rhetorical pedagogy that I now wish to turn to the scholarly reception of Bernal's work. Responses to Black Athena Molly Meyrowitz Levine, in the introduction to a special issue of Arethusa devoted to the book, summarizes Bernal's argument very well: "We, it is claimed, owing to residual racism, anti-Semitism, sheer scholarly inertia, and/or exaggerated respect for authority, have suppressed or ignored the weight of what Professor Bernal considers to be overwhelming evidence for substantial Semitic and Egyptian roles in the development of Greek language and civilization." This thesis contains two different claims. The first is that we have good reasons to believe that there was substantial Semitic and Egyptian influence on the development of Greek language and civilization. Contained in this first claim is a much more controversial one, bound up with the title of the work. To argue for substantial Semitic and Egyptian influence is not the same as labeling that influence as "black." The African-American classicist Frank M. Snowden, Jr., has disputed this claim, and Bernal himself admits that it would be more useful to title the work "African Athena." The response of right-wing periodicals has tended to focus on the African side of Bernal's argument, a response that confirms his view of the racist assumptions of contemporary proponents of "classical education," even if his larger argument might need to be modified. Although this paper is intended to focus more on the second claim, that racism, anti-Semitism, and imperialism directly and indirectly affected Altertumswissenschaft in the West, it would be useful to see how Bernal's first claim has fared thus far in scholarly discussion. We need, I think, to dismiss the response of right-wing periodicals to the book. National Review, for instance, mentioned the book in an editorial note, and somehow concluded that Bernal was "a black professor of government at Cornell." The New Criterion, which now devotes each issue to a hatchet job on a prominent left-wing academic, simply dismissed the possibility of Egyptian influence on ancient Greece, and characterized Bernal's work as analogous to Lysenko's genetics. There have, however, been far more serious criticisms of Bernal's work. These include, first, the argument that Bernal's etymological analyses are unscientific. That is, he provides no set of rules that could explain the presence of Semitic roots in Greek. Gary Rendsburg, a specialist in Semitic languages at Cornell, explains that it is possible to generate specific rules that would account for Bernal's findings, specifically that Greek words without an Indo-European root would be a logical place to start, and concludes that there are very few of Bernal's etymologies that aren't borne out. Second, there may be other explanations for the popularity of the "ancient model" in Greece. Jasper Griffin argues that Greeks used the Egyptians as "a stick with which Greeks beat other Greeks." Herodotus, for instance, "who gaily grants so much to the Egyptians, preferred to do that rather than give any credit to his Greek forerunner Hecataeus." Other writers, such as Tamara M. Green, are equally skeptical about the possibility of assessing the validity of ancient Greek views of cultural origins, because we operate according to canons of scientific historiography that are simply meaningless in an ancient context. Nonetheless, considerable support for Bernal's thesis has emerged among classical archaeologists, and it will be interesting to see how the debate continues as the years progress. Sarah P. Morris, while sympathetic to Bernal's thesis, points out an important fact that is obscured by Bernal's book: the reason why the Aryan model was easily disseminated after the 18th century is that the Aryan model itself had classical roots. Although my concern in this paper is with the racist underpinnings of later classical scholarship, I do want to note a few research questions that emerged in my reading of the debate over the question of African/Semitic influences on Greek civilization. I vividly remember some discussions I had with people after the first issue of Rhetorica appeared some years ago, and how remarkable (not to mention eccentric) it was that someone was actually studying Egyptian rhetoric. One question that is almost never discussed in standard histories of rhetoric--and I am thinking of Kennedy's and Conley's here in particular--is the question of the origin of rhetoric as a self-conscious practice. Kennedy simply dismisses the question of rhetoric's origins in a footnote in The Art of Persuasion in Ancient Greece. His comparison of Greek "rhetorical consciousness" with that of other cultures simply assumes both the uniqueness of the Greek view and, somewhat paradoxically, its universal applicability. His justification of a classical-rhetorical analysis of the Christian biblical writings is a case in point. What one sees operating in Kennedy, and in virtually every standard account of Greek rhetoric such as Corbett or The Rhetoric of Western Thought is a remarkably sanitized version of ancient Greek culture. Fredric Jameson characterizes the alternative view of ancient Greece that has emerged from twentieth-century classical scholarship inspired by anthropology in this way, as "a culture of masks and death, ritual ecstasies, slavery, scapegoating, phallocratic homosexuality, an utterly non- or anti-classical culture to which something of the electrifying otherness and fascination, say, of the Aztec world, has been restored." Yet this alternative view of ancient Greece has yet to be integrated significantly into the study of classical rhetoric. There are some interesting speculative attempts to account for the origins of rhetoric--Vincent Farenga's wacky Derridean/Girardian article is one and Jacqueline de Romilly's is another--but none seem to raise the question of Egyptian influences. I have always suspected that there is a direct connection between the wisdom tradition of the Egyptian courts and its further elaboration in the "Wisdom" literature of the Hebrew Bible (Proverbs, for instance) with classical rhetoric than is usually discussed. Yet the peculiar isolation of students of classical languages from the study of Hebrew and other Semitic languages makes it difficult to explore those links. I wonder, too, if Egyptian ceremonial magic might not underlie some of the traditions de Romilly explores. John O. Ward has recently drawn our attention to the complex relationship between rhetoric and magic from classical times through the Renaissance. He analyzes the social forces underlying the conception of rhetoric as control and rhetoric as magic, a conceptual split that may parallel Paul de Man's useful but undeveloped characterization of rhetoric as suspended between trope and persuasion. A closer attention to the relative prestige of Egyptian, Greek, and Roman texts in any given period in the history of rhetoric might help us explore more completely the complex dialectic identified by Ward. A good example of how ignoring Egypt may lead to misleading conclusions is the recent study of classical republicanism in American history represented by the works of Wood, Bailyn, and Pocock. Despite their persuasiveness, these works really do not engage the significance of freemasonry for the republican tradition of the American framers. Another recent example of how a Hellenocentric view can distort intellectual history comes from recent scholarship in Judaica. Gershom Scholem, whose pathbreaking work on Jewish mysticism and the Kabbalah has been admired for years, and who has indirectly had influence on contemporary literary and rhetorical theory through the work of Harold Bloom, argued that Kabbalah was imported into Judaism from Greek and other Gnostic sources, and that Kabbalah as we know it does not really date much before the early Middle Ages. Moshe Idel, however, has demonstrated rather painstakingly that we have good reasons to believe that Kabbalah is of ancient origin, and that it may be more accurate to say that the mystical strain of ancient Judaism influenced what was to become Gnosticism rather than the other way round. Idel does not say so, but is it possible that Scholem, so ingrained with the spirit of German scholarship, tended to slight the possibility of religious innovation in Judaism? To summarize, not only does Bernal help draw our attention to the way in which rhetorical scholars have ignored the question of the origins and legitimacy of Greek rhetorical consciousness, but he helps us see that ignoring this question goes hand in hand with devaluing the mystical, magical, and irrational side of the rhetorical tradition, a side that the rationalistic view of rhetoric could so easily consign to the dark and savage realm of the "Oriental." I want to turn next to Bernal's second claim, that not only do we have good archaeological and philological reasons to believe that the Ancient Model is valid, but that those good reasons were systematically ignored or repressed by the racist, anti-Semitic, and imperalist assumptions of German and British scholarship from the the 18th century onward. The most persuasive arguments against Bernal's second claim come from Frank M. Turner, whose work on the Victorians and ancient Greece is an important source for Bernal's work. Turner's doubts center on the following arguments: First, despite the veneer of scientific objectivity in Bernal's work, he is just as tendentious as the earlier scholars he criticizes. Turner puts it this way, "Professor Bernal's work stands in the longer tradition of engaged, polemical classical scholarship within which consideration of the ancient world is subordinate to or at least on an equal level with a modern political or religious concern. George Grote might not agree with Professor Bernal, but he would understand the nature of the product." Second, Bernal's readings of classical scholarship rely too heavily on secondary sources. We do not know enough about 18th century classical scholarship to know if the Ancient Model really held sway until then. Bernal does not do enough primary-source based, particularistic readings of, say, Niebuhr, really to justify his broad claims. Instead we get ism-based explanation, whereby things called romanticism and imperialism are used to explain historical processes, without enough attention to the individual sources themselves. If we turn to the individual sources, we find relatively little attention paid to what, for Bernal, is the central issues: the origins of ancient Greek culture. Only five pages of Grote, for instance, deal with the issue. Third, it is possible to devise other explanations for the ascendency of Greece during this period, explanations that have little to do with racism, anti-Semitism, or imperialism. These explanations are twofold: A. the contemporary concern with the fate of democratic regimes, and B. the attempt to cope with the decline of biblical salvation history as a master narrative for the West. Turner points out that the chief concern of the British classicists, and British intellectuals generally, in the 19th century was with democratic politics--whether democracy in itself was the best regime and whether democratic regimes could control empires. "The political character of ancient Egypt more than anything else excluded it from serious consideration in terms of its relation to Greece. . . .It was not a polemically useful subject." In fact (and here we are closer to a topic of interest to rhetoricians), even "more impressive than the demise of Egypt from European discourse about antiquity was the demise of concern about republican Rome." Turner also writes that the new prestige of the Greeks had much to do with the rise of Darwinism and the decline of the Christian religion. The classicists sought to find "an alternative history for the development of humankind to that recorded in Hebrew scripture," as a way of escaping from the moral confines of Christian theological anthropology. Neither of these arguments is to deny the influence of racism and imperialism on 19th century British scholarship, but Bernal may err in attributing them centrality. Bernal, in fact, according to Turner, may be missing the point by assuming a higher level of professionalism in 19th century classical scholarship than actually existed. Scientific consensus among 20th century archaeologists and classicists is a different animal from the loose gentlemanly consensus of earlier "scholars." Turner's criticisms are not really adequately responded to by Bernal in the APA paper published in Arethusa, but I think there are some provocative implications raised by the exchange that I wish to pursue here. First, how do we account for shifting fashions in classical and philosophical and rhetorical scholarship? I know, for instance, that when I was in graduate school Aristotle was required reading in classical rhetoric, but Cicero tended to be read in selections only, and was never taken seriously as a theorist. Things have changed considerably in recent years. Michael Leff has pointed out that even the recent Aristotelian revival, by Beiner and others, is a heavily Ciceronianized Aristotle. Thomas Conley persuasively points out in his recent history of rhetorical theory that twentieth century rhetorical theory may be seen as a recovery of the Ciceronian more than the Aristotelian tradition. We know that at some point "neo-Aristotelianism" took hold in American speech scholarship, but it is still somewhat confusing when or how that took place. The supposed founding document of neo-Aristotelianism, Wichelns' classic essay on the literary criticism of oratory, only mentions Aristotle once, and is generally more Ciceronian in spirit than Aristotelian. Thonssen and Baird's 1948 Speech Criticism is explicitly Aristotelian. It is probably no accident, that as the more "liberal artsy" members of the speech profession sought legitimation for their work there was a tendency to locate authority in Aristotle rather than in Cicero. There may have been other dynamics at work as well. Bernal's rejoinder to Turner points out a pattern in the political underpinnings of scholarly admiration for particular societies: "The Enlightened scholars of the 18th century admired big stable empires like Rome, Egypt, and China (these three went together), just as the Romantics loved small and dynamic--unstable--societies like Greece and Switzerland. The history of rhetoric would provide an interesting test case for proving or disproving Bernal's claim about the increasing influence of racism and anti-Semitism on 19th-century classical scholarship. If Turner is correct that we need more individual case studies of the period, then people like Whately or Grote might illustrate subtle shifts in the image of Greece during this period. Mary Rosner's recent discussion of the reception of Cicero's work in the nineteenth century suggests that matters may be considerably more complicated than either Bernal or Turner realizes. Neither Turner's book nor the vastly more entertaining but "anecdotal" Richard Jenkyns' The Victorians and Ancient Greece discuss the fortunes of rhetoric and oratory during this period. It would be an interesting exercise to trace the history of British attitudes toward classical rhetoric and its relationship to contemporary political oratory in the 19th century. For our purposes, it is enough to note that Bernal provides an explanation for the Aristotelian cast of Whately's Elements of Rhetoric; although Whately's views were far more traditional than others, what has remained unexplained until this point is why Aristotle's rhetoric became more influential in the 19th-century than it ever had previously. A discussion of the shifting definitions of logic as well as rhetoric in the nineteenth century would also be a useful research task inspired by Bernal's thesis. A final point concerns the relationship between the decline of rhetoric and the romantic view of ancient Greece in the 18th and 19th century. Where I may part company with the others on this panel is in my insistence that the best part of the Greco-Roman rhetorical tradition was largely overturned precisely by the forces Bernal identifies. Although certainly no Tory, Bernal does draw our attention to the degree to which racism and anti-Semitism are essentially products of the Enlightenment. The rejection of the Jewish and Christian notion of monogenesis of the races in favor of the more "scientific" polygenesis illustrates how supposedly enlightened positions can be reactionary politically. Similarly, the rejection of rhetoric went hand in hand with the Romantic racist emphasis on ethnicity. The most significant passage here in Bernal comes during his discussion of the Romantic concern, beginning at the University of Gottingen, with the history of peoples and races and institutions: "A race was believed to change its form as it passed through different ages, but always to retain an immutable individual essence. Real communication was no longer perceived as taking place through reason, which could reach any rational man. It was now seen as flowing through feeling, which could touch only those tied to each other by kinship or 'blood' and sharing a common heritage." It is this racial focus that was ultimately bound up with the displacement of rhetoric by something called "literature," especially the importance of a national literature in the England and the United States. Terry Eagleton has demonstrated, persuasively I think, the deep interconnection among the rise of literary studies, capitalism, and the decline of rhetoric. There was always a clear-sighted focus on the reality of power and politics in the rhetorical tradition, however reactionary its social uses, and this was something, especially given the decline of revealed religion, that endangered the legitimacy of the capitalist state. Similarly, there was a universalizing tendency in the argumentative side of the rhetorical tradition that was hardly compatible with Romantic racism. I do believe it is possible to defend both rhetoric and logic as formal systems of thought independent of particular cultural traditions, and I am a little concerned about recent attempts, notably by post-structuralist feminists, to undermine them. This last comment leads me to the larger question of the canon and curricular reform with which I began the paper. I am not comfortable with the attempts of some left academics to brand either Bloom or Hirsch as at best ethnocentric or at worst racist--their own personal histories on the issue of race are impeccable (we tend to forget that both are social democrats politically). If one wants to see really racist accounts of the canon and curricular issues one need only pick up a copy of the magazine Chronicles, where Paul Gottfried and others have attacked even Bloom for not being sufficiently conservative. But where I do believe that Bloom and Hirsch are caught up in the Romantic and Enlightenment currents of racism is in their steadfast rejection of any attempt to think of education in formal rather than content based terms. Cultural Literacy is caught up in one massive contradiction that, to my knowledge, no commentator has noted. When, after an indictment of any notion of formal or skills-based learning, Hirsch tries to provide an example of a work that illustrates his principles of cultural literacy at work, the example he chooses is, of all things, Blair's lectures on rhetoric and belles lettres. Bloom, equally a foe of anything resembling formalism, at least recognizes the existence of significant tensions within Western culture, notably the famed Straussian tension between Athens and Jerusalem, but there remains the dogged emphasis on Socrates as the heroic figure in Western culture, an emphasis that, despite Bloom's Straussian rejection of historicism, can finally be explained only in historicist terms. I recently had the opportunity to look at a syllabus from the now notorious Western Culture class at Stanford University, which my nephew took a few years back. There we find the obligatory reading of Aristotle and Plato, but there is nary a mention of Cicero nor any study of classical oratory. I fear that, racist-inspired or not, "classical education" remains as much a myth now as it was in the nineteenth century. I have tried to suggest some directions of conversation and research inspired by Bernal's book. If we can ever transcend the current lack of civility in discussions of curricular matters, Bernal helps us ask questions about the myth of origins underlying our study of rhetoric, about directions in which that study might proceed when it has been divested of European cultural arrogance, and about proper modes of explanation in writing the history of European rhetorical theory. I would add, by way of a conclusion, that Bernal makes his arguments in a way that should satisfy even the most committed partisan of the rational side of the Western rhetorical tradition. After all, he is merely trying to help us makes good on Western culture's claim to promote rationality and justice. Originally presented at the Speech Communication Association annual convention, Chicago, Illinois, November 1990. © 1996 James Arnt Aune. All rights reserved. [Fragments Note: Aune taught at St. Olaf College when this essay was written ] http://mcgees.net/fragments/essays/guests/black.htm