Week 4: Divine Command Theories of Morality Lecture Outline: 1. Waluchow on Divine Command Theory 2. G&H on Divine Command Theory 3. The Euthyphro 4. The (Biblical) Story of Abraham NOTE: All of the readings for this week are biased against Divine Command Theory. That is, no philosopher, not even Plato, accepts that morality is a function of the commands of a God (though this does not mean that all philosophers are atheists). Hopefully by the end of today’s class, we’ll all understand why this is. Waluchow on Divine Command Theory (pgs 95 – 103) The attractive aspect of Divine Command Theory (D.C.T) is that it has the potential to establish an objective morality – if morality is a set of commands issued by a divine authority, it follows that morality is both universal and objective. There are two versions of D.C.T. Both provide the same objective motivation for being moral, i.e., ‘why should I be moral? Because God says I should.’ Where the two versions differ is the source of morality. Version 1: The Moral Ground version of D.C.T. The morally right action is that action commanded by God. That is, the fact that God has commanded some act is the reason for the act being morally right. Version 2: The Divine Index version of D.C.T. God commands us to do the morally right thing in all circumstances because it is the right thing to do. ‘Morality’ is independent of, but known by, God. Problems with the Moral Ground version: This version does permit God to be both omniscient and omnipotent, because it leaves control of morality in His hands… but this control gives rise to the following two problems: 1. There is no standard by which we can assess the choices of God as ‘morally good’ 2. Morality is wholly arbitrary. If God said that torture was morally right, it would have to be. So this leaves us with the Moral Index version (#2), where morality is independent of God, but He has complete knowledge of it. We might not always be able to grasp the reasons behind God’s command, but at least we know that He has directed us in the morally correct manner. Sustaining this version of D.C.T. requires at least that we be able to accurately identify and interpret God’s commands, and these tasks correspond to the problems with this version of D.C.T. Problems with The Moral Index Version of D.C.T.: 1. Which God, which religious text, which prophet? 2. Even if you identify God’s commands, how are they to be reliably interpreted and applied? What these problems with version 2 show is that even if this more plausible theory is adopted, we’ll still have to engage in moral reasoning to interpret God’s commands, which means we’ll need to turn to a moral theory independent of those commands. G&H – Introduction to D.C.T. (pgs. 33 – 37) There are two claims that make up every version of D.C.T. 1. God(s) command certain actions 2. These actions are morally right because they are commanded by God(s) [Note: Waluchow does not think all versions of D.C.T. are characterized by these two statements. On his account, this description only covers version #1] There are two questions G&H believe those wishing to endorse D.C.T. will have to answer. 1. Is D.C.T. defensible? 2. Even if it is defensible, are its supporters actually morally responsible agents? Reasons to think D.C.T. is not defensible: 1. Which God do these commands come from? 2. How accurate is the Bible as an historical text? 3. How do we explain the interpretive divisions within Christianity? Reason to think D.C.T. undermines the status of its followers as responsible moral agents: If morality is nothing more than a command, and the command always presents us with the right thing to do, it follows that morality consists in nothing more than blindly following commands, like a robot. But humans are not robots… we have free will, and as such, we can attempt to investigate the reasons that underwrite any command. But as soon we start to investigate the reasons behind God’s commands, we stop following D.C.T. because now we’re questioning the validity of God’s commands using moral reasoning. Most moral theories recognize that it is important to do the right thing, FOR THE RIGHT REASONS. Plato – Euthyphro (G&H, pgs. 38 – 53) This is one of Plato’s ‘Early Dialogues’ and as such, it is believed to be Plato’s interpretation of an actual conversation Socrates had during his life. Plato was Socrates’ student, and because Socrates never wrote anything down, we rely on Plato’s ‘Dialogues’ for insight into Socrates’ philosophical position. The ‘Socratic Method’: This is basically an account of the rhetorical strategy Socrates uses in every one of Plato’s ‘Dialogues’. It goes something like this: 1. You get the person with whom you are debating to state their position with as much precision and clarity as you can. 2. You ask a series of questions intended to test the hypothesis, questions that elicit ‘yes’ or ‘no’ answers. 3. By the end of the series of questions either the hypothesis must be rejected and/or modified, or the discussion has revealed some truth about the universe. ‘The Euthyphro’ opens with Socrates waiting outside the Athenian Assembly building in order to face charges brought by Meletus. Meletus’ charge is that Socrates has corrupted the Athenian youth by inventing new gods and not recognizing the old ones. Socrates discovers in talking to Euthyphro that he is at the Assembly to prosecute his own father for murder. His father had tied up a worker after the worker had murdered one of his fellows, and he let him die while waiting for advice from the religious authority. Clearly, says Euthyphro, this was a wrongful killing and his father needs to be prosecuted accordingly; at least inasmuch as religious law is concerned. Socrates asks Euthyphro to become his teacher in religious matters, so he can overcome Meletus’ indictment against him. So let’s get started: What, asks Socrates, do the Gods find holy? Euthyphro (E): Prosecuting wrongdoers is holy, failing to prosecute is unholy. Socrates (S): But this is only one example. I want to know the essence of ‘holiness’. E: What pleases the Gods is holy, what displeases them is unholy. S: Are ‘holy’ and ‘unholy’ opposites? E: yes S: But what of the fact that the Gods disagree and fight over which actions are just, and which are unjust? Does this not mean some acts will be both holy and unholy according to your definition? E: yes, but there are some acts that all the Gods agree are either holy or unholy. S: O.k. So we need to adjust our hypothesis; those actions upon which all Gods agree are either holy or unholy, and if there is disagreement, then the act is neither holy nor unholy. E: Sure. S: So now answer this – do the Gods love actions because they are holy (Waluchow’s D.C.T. version 2), or are actions holy because they are loved by the Gods? (Waluchow’s D.C.T. version 1) Clearly on this account, the Gods love an action because that action is holy, not because they love it. E: Clearly. S: Then all you have shown me is a feature of ‘holiness’, namely, that all holy things are loved by the Gods. But this still does not tell me what the essence of holiness is. Let’s try a different approach… is holiness a part of justice, or is it the other way around? E: Holiness is that part of justice that consists in ministering to the Gods. S: What does it mean to ‘minister’ to the Gods? Does anything humans do actually have an impact on the Gods. E: Yes, human actions either please or displease the Gods. S: But this is the same as saying that holy acts are those that the Gods love, which as we have already seen, is an untenable position. E: I gotta go. The Story of Abraham (G&H pgs 54 – 5) God tells Abraham to make a sacrifice of his son. Abraham prepares to do so, and God stops him at the last second, then rewards him and his descendants with many offspring. So the question is, while Abraham might have had faith in the all-knowing power of God, was he nonetheless acting morally when he lied to his son and had every intention of killing him? If your answer is ‘no’, then you cannot support D.C.T.