The Minds I Chapter 17 The Riddle on the Universe and its Solution

advertisement
The Riddle on the Universe and its Solution
17
CHRISTOPHER CHERNIAK
The Riddle
of the Universe
and Its Solution
We have prepared this report to provide fuller information in connection with the
President's recent press conference on the so-called "Riddle.' We hope the report helps to
dispel the ugly mood apparent throughout the country, bordering on panic, which has
most recently found expression in irresponsible demands to close the universities. Our
report ha been prepared in haste; in addition, our work was tragically disrupted, a
described later.
We first review the less well known early history of the Riddle. The earliest
known case is that of C. Dizzard, a research fellow with the Autotomy Group at M.I.U.
Dizzard had previously worked for severs small firms specializing in the development of
artificial intelligence sof ware for commercial applications. Dizzard's current project
involved ti use of computers in theorem proving, on the model of the proof in the 1970s
of the four-color theorem. The state of Dizzard's project is know only from a year-old
progress report; however, these are often intended at most for external use. We shall not
discuss the area of Dizzard's work further. The reason for our reticence will be apparent
shortly.
Copyright © 1978 by Christopher Cherniak.
The Riddle on the Universe and its Solution
270
Dizzard last spoke one morning before an Easter weekend, while waiting for a
routine main computer system failure to be fixed. Colleagues saw Dizzard at the terminal
in his office at about midnight that day; late-night work habits are common among
computer users, and Dizzard was known to sleep in his office. On the next afternoon, a
coworker noticed Dizzard sitting at his terminal. He spoke to Dizzard, but Dizzard did
not reply, not an unusual occurrence. On the morning after the vacation, another
colleague found Dizzard sitting with his eyes open before his terminal, which was on.
Dizzard seemed awake but did not respond to questions. Later that day, the colleague
became concerned by Dizzard's unresponsiveness and tried to arouse him from what he
thought was a daydream or daze. When these attempts were unsuccessful, Dizzard was
taken to a hospital emergency room.
Dizzard showed symptoms of a total food-and-water fast of a week (aggravated
by marginal malnutrition caused by a vending-machine diet); he was in critical condition
from dehydration. The inference was that Dizzard had not moved for several days, and
that the cause of his immobility was a coma or trance. The original conjecture was that a
stroke or tumor caused Dizzard's paralysis. However, electroencephalograms indicated
only deep coma. (According to Dizzard's health records, he had been institutionalized
briefly ten years ago, not an uncommon incident in certain fields.) Dizzard died,
apparently of his fast, two days later. Autopsy was delayed by objections of next of kin,
members of a breakaway sect of the neo Jemimakins cult. Histological examination of
Dizzard's brain so far has revealed no damage whatever; these investigations continue at
the National Center for Disease Control.
The director of the Autotomy Group appointed one of Dizzard's graduate students
to manage his project while a decision was made about its future. The floor of Dizzard's
office was about one foot deep in papers and books; the student was busy for a month just
sorting the materials into some general scheme. Shortly afterward, the student reported at
a staff meeting that she had begun work on Dizzard's last project and that she had found
little of particular interest. A week later she was found sitting at the terminal in Dizzard's
office in an apparent daze.
There was confusion at first, because she was thought to be making a poor joke.
She was staring straight ahead, breathing normally. She did riot respond to questions or
being shaken, and showed no startle response to loud noises. After she was accidentally
bumped from her chair, she was hospitalized. The examining neurologist was unaware of
Dizzard's case. He reported the patient was in apparently good physical condition, except
for a previously undiagnosed pineal gland abnormality. After Autotomy Project staff
answered inquiries by the student's friends,
The Riddle on the Universe and its Solution
271
her parents informed the attending physician of Dizzard's case. The neurologist noted the
difficulty of comparing the two cases, but suggested the similarities of deep coma with no
detectable brain damage; the student's symptoms constituted no identifiable syndrome.
After further consultation, the neurologist proposed the illness ,,light be caused by
a slow acting sleeping-sickness-like pathogen, caught from Dizzard's belongings-perhaps
hitherto unknown, like Legionnaire's Disease. Two weeks later, Dizzard's and his
student's offices were quarantined. After two months with no further cases and cultures
yielding only false alarms, quarantine was lifted.
When it was discovered janitors had thrown out some of Dizzard's records, a
research fellow and two more of Dizzard's students decided to review his project files. On
their third day, the students noticed that the research fellow had fallen into an
unresponsive trancelike state and did not respond even to pinching. After the students
failed to awaken the research fellow, they called an ambulance. The new patient showed
the same symptoms as the previous case. Five days later, the city public health board
imposed a quarantine on all building areas involved in Dizzard's project.
The following morning, all members of the Autotomy Group refused to enter the
research building. Later that day, occupants of the rest of the Autotomv Group's floor,
and then all 500 other workers in the building, discovered the Autotomy Project's
problems and left the building. The next day, the local newspaper published a story with
the headline "Computer Plague." In an interview, a leading dermatologist proposed that a
virus or bacterium like computer lice had evolved that metabolized newly developed
materials associated with computers, probably silicon. Others conjectured that the
Autotomy Project's large computers might be emitting some peculiar radiation. The
director of the Autotomy Group was quoted: The illnesses were a public health matter,
not a concern of cognitive scientists.
The town mayor then charged that a secret Army project involving recombinant
DNA was in progress at the building and had caused the outbreak. Truthful denials of the
mayor's claim were met with understandable mistrust. The city council demanded
immediate quarantine of the entire ten-story building and surrounding area. The
university administration felt this would be an impediment to progress, but the local
Congressional delegation's pressure accomplished this a week later. Since building
maintenance and security personnel would no longer even approach the area, special
police were needed to stop petty vandalism by Juveniles. A Disease Control Center team
began toxicological assays, protected by biohazard suits whenever they entered the
quarantine zone.
The Riddle on the Universe and its Solution
272
In the course of a month they found nothing, and none of them fell ill. At the time
some suggested that, because no organic disease had been discovered in the three victims,
and the two survivors showed some physiological signs associated with deep meditation
states, the cases might be an outbreak of mass hysteria.
Meanwhile, the Autotomy Group moved into a "temporary" World War II-era
wooden building. While loss of more than ten million dollars in computers was grave, the
group recognized that the information, not the physical artifacts that embodied it, was
indispensable. They devised a plan: biohazard-suited workers fed "hot" tapes to readers in
the quarantine zone; the information was transmitted by telephone link from the zone to
the new Autotomy Project site and recorded again. While transcription of the tapes
allowed the project to survive, only the most important materials could be so
reconstructed. Dizzard's project was not in the priority class; however, we suspect an
accident occurred.
A team of programmers was playing back new tapes, checking them on monitors,
and provisionally indexing and filing their contents. A new programmer encountered
unfamiliar material and asked a passing project supervisor whether it should be
discarded. The programmer later reported the supervisor typed in commands to display
the file on the monitor; as the programmer and the supervisor watched the lines advance
across the screen, the supervisor remarked that the material did not look important.
Prudence prevents our quoting his comments further. He then stopped speaking in
midsentence. The programmer looked up; he found the supervisor staring ahead. The
supervisor did not respond to questions. When the programmer pushed back his chair to
run, it bumped the supervisor and he fell to the floor. He was hospitalized with the same
symptoms as the earlier cases.
The epidemiology team, and many others, now proposed that the cause of illness
in the four cases might not be a physical agent such as a virus or toxin, but rather an
abstract piece of information-which could be stored on tape, transmitted over a telephone
line, displayed on a screen, and so forth. This supposed information now became known
as "the Riddle," and the illness as "the Riddle coma." All evidence was consistent with
the once-bizarre hypothesis that any human who encountered this information lapsed into
an apparently irreversible coma. Some also recognized that the question of exactly what
this information is was extremely delicate.
This became clear when the programmer involved in the fourth case was
interviewed. The programmer's survival suggested the Riddle must be understood to
induce coma. He reported he had read at least some lines on the monitor at the time the
supervisor was stricken. However, he
The Riddle on the Universe and its Solution
273
knew nothing about Dizzard's project, and he was able to recall little about the display. A
proposal that the programmer be hypnotized to improve his recall was shelved. The
programmer agreed it would be best if he did not try to remember any more of what he
had read, although of course it would be difficult to try not to remember something.
Indeed, the programmer eventually was advised to abandon his career and learn as little
more computer science as possible. Thus the ethical issue emerged of whether even
legally responsible volunteers should be permitted to see the Riddle.
The outbreak of a Riddle coma epidemic in connection with a computer-assisted
theorem-proving project could be explained; if someone discovered the Riddle in his
head, he should lapse into coma before he could communicate it to anyone. The question
arose of whether the Riddle had in fact been discovered earlier by hand and then
immediately lost. A literature search would have been of limited value, so a biographical
survey was undertaken of logicians, philosophers, and mathematicians working since the
rise of modern logic. It has been hampered by precautions to protect the researchers from
exposure to the Riddle. At present, at least ten suspect cases have been discovered, the
earliest almost 100 years ago.
Psycholinguists began a project to determine whether Riddle coma susceptibility
was species-specific to humans. "Wittgenstein," a chimpanzee trained in sign language
who had solved first-year college logic puzzles, was the most appropriate subject to see
the Autotomy Project tapes. The Wittgenstein Project investigators refused to cooperate,
on ethical grounds, and kidnapped and hid the chimpanzee; the FBI eventually found
him. He was shown Autotomy tapes twenty-four hours a day, with no effect whatever.
There have been similar results for dogs and pigeons. Nor has any computer ever been
damaged by the Riddle.
In all studies, it has been necessary to show the complete Autotomy tapes. No safe
strategy has been found for determining even which portion of the tapes contains the
Riddle. During the Wittgenstein-Autotomy Project, a worker in an unrelated program
seems to have been stricken with Riddle coma when some Autotomy tapes were printed
out accidentally at a public user area of the computer facility; a month's printouts had to
be retrieved and destroyed.
Attention focused on the question of what the Riddle coma is. Since it resembled
no known disease, it was unclear whether it was really a coma or indeed something to be
avoided. Investigators simply assumed it was a virtual lobotomy, a kind of gridlock of the
information in the synapses, completely shutting down higher brain functions.
Nonetheless, it was unlikely the coma could be the correlate of a state of meditative
enlight-
The Riddle on the Universe and its Solution
274
enment, because it seemed too deep to be consistent with consciousness. In addition, no
known case of Riddle coma has ever shown improvement. Neurosurgery, drugs, and
electrical stimulation have had, if any, only negative effects; these attempts have been
stopped. The provisional verdict is that the coma is irreversible, although a project has
been funded to seek a word to undo the "spell" of the Riddle, by exposing victims to
computer-generated symbol strings.
The central question, "What is the Riddle?" obviously has to be approached very
cautiously. The Riddle is sometimes described as "the GOdel sentence for the human
Turing machine," which causes the mind to jam; traditional doctrines of the unsayable
and unthinkable are cited. Similar ideas are familiar in folklore-for instance, the religious
theme of the power of the "Word" to mend the shattered spirit. But the Riddle could be of
great benefit to the cognitive sciences. It might yield fundamental information about the
structure of the human mind; it may be a Rosetta Stone for decoding the "language of
thought," universal among all humans, whatever language they speak. If the
computational theory of mind is at all correct, there is some program, some huge word,
that can be written into a machine, transforming the machine into a thinking thing; why
shouldn't there be a terrible word, the Riddle, that would negate the first one? But all
depended on the feasibility of a field of "Riddle-ology" that would not self-destruct.
At this point, an even more disturbing fact about the Riddle began to emerge. A
topologist in Paris lapsed into a coma similar in some respects to Dizzard's. No computer
was involved in this case. The mathematician's papers were impounded by the French,
but we believe that, although this mathematician was not familiar with Dizzard's work,
she had become interested in similar areas of artificial intelligence. About then four
members of the Institute for Machine Computation in Moscow stopped appearing at
international conferences and, it seems, personally answering correspondence; FBI
officials claimed the Soviet Union had, through routine espionage, obtained the
Autotomy tapes. The Defense Department began exploring the concept of "Riddle
warfare."
Two more cases followed, a theoretical linguist and a philosopher, both in
California but apparently working independently. Neither was working in Dizzard's area,
but both were familiar with formal methods developed by Dizzard and published in a
well-known text ten years ago. A still more ominous case appeared, of a biochemist
working on information-theoretic models of DNA-RNA interactions. (The possibility of a
false alarm remained, as after entering coma the biochemist clucked continuously, like a
chicken.)
The Riddle coma could no longer safely be assumed an occupational
The Riddle on the Universe and its Solution
275
hazard of Dizzard's specialty alone; it seemed to lurk in many forms. The Riddle and its
effect seemed not just language-independent. The Riddle, or cognates of it, might be
topic-independent and virtually ubiquitous. Boundaries for an intellectual quarantine
could not be fixed confidently.
But now we are finding, in addition, that the Riddle seems an idea whose time has
come-like the many self-referential paradoxes (of the pattern "This sentence is false")
discovered in the early part of this century. Perhaps this is reflected in the current attitude
that "computer science is the new liberal art." Once the intellectual background has
evolved, widespread discovery of the Riddle appears inevitable. This first became clear
last winter when most of the undergraduates in a large new introductory course on
automata theory lapsed into coma during a lecture. (Some who did not nevertheless
succumbed a few hours later; typically, their last word was "aha.") When similar
incidents followed elsewhere, public outcry led to the president's press conference and
this report.
While the present logophobic atmosphere and cries of "Close the universities" are
unreasonable, the Riddle coma pandemic cannot be viewed as just another example of
runaway technology. The recent "Sonic Oven" case in Minneapolis, for instance, in
which a building with a facade of parabolic shape concentrated the noise of nearby jets
during takeoff, actually killed only the few people who happened to walk through the
parabola's focus at the wrong time. But even if the Riddle coma were a desirable state for
an individual (which, we have seen, it does not seem to be), the current pandemic has
become an unprecedented public health crisis; significant populations are unable to care
for themselves. We can only expect the portion of our research community-an essential
element of society-that is so incapacitated to grow, as the idea of the Riddle spreads.
The principal objective of our report was at least to decrease further coma
outbreaks. Public demand for a role in setting research policy has emphasized the
dilemma we confront: how can we warn against the Riddle, or even discuss it, without
spreading its infection? The more specific the warning, the greater the danger. The reader
might accidentally reach the stage at which he sees "If p then q" and p, and so cannot stop
himself from concluding q, where q is the Riddle. Identifying the hazardous areas would
be like the children's joke "I'll give you a dollar if you're not thinking of pink rats ten
seconds from now."
A question of ethics as well as of policy remains; is the devastating risk of the
Riddle outweighed by the benefits of continued research in an ill-defined but crucial set
of fields? In particular, the authors of this report have been unable to resolve the issue of
whether the possible benefit of
The Riddle on the Universe and its Solution
276
any report itself can outweigh its danger to the reader. Indeed, d preparation of our final
draft one of us tragically succumbed.
Reflections
This curious story is predicated upon a rather outlandish yet Intri idea: a mindarresting proposition, one that throws any mind into a of paradoxical trance, perhaps even
the ultimate Zen state of satori. reminiscent of a Monty Python skit about a joke so funny
that anyone hears it will literally die laughing. This joke becomes the ultimate se weapon
of the British military, and no one is permitted to know m than one word of it. (People
who learn two words laugh so hard t require hospitalization!)
This kind of thing has historical precedents, of course, both in and in literature.
There have been mass manias for puzzles, there have been dancing fits, and so on. Arthur
C. Clarke wrote a short story a a tune so catchy that it seizes control of the mind of
anyone who h it. In mythology, sirens and other bewitching females can complete
fascinate males and thus overpower them. But what is the nature of s mythical mindgripping powers?
Cherniak's description of the Riddle as "the Gödel sentence for human Turing
machine" may seem cryptic. It is partly explicated late his likening it to the selfreferential paradox "This sentence is false here, a tight closed loop is formed when you
attempt to decide when it is indeed true or false, since truth implies falsity, and vice
versa. nature of this loop is an important part of its fascination. A look at a variations on
this theme will help to reveal a shared central mechanism underlying their paradoxical,
perhaps mind-trapping, effect.
One variant is: "This sentence contains threee errors." On read it, one's first
reaction is, "No, no-it contains two errors. Whoever wrote the sentence can't count." At
this point, some readers simply walk a scratching their heads and wondering why anyone
would .rite such pointless, false remark. Other readers make a connection between
sentence's apparent falsity and its message. They think to 'themselves "Oh, it made a third
error, after all-namely, in counting its own errors A second or two later, these readers do
a double-take, when they real that if you look at it that way, it seems to have correctly
counted its errors.
The Riddle on the Universe and its Solution
277
and is thus not false, hence contains only two errors, and ... "But ... Wait a minute. Hey!
Hmm ..." The mind flips back and forth a few times and say the bizarre sensation of a
sentence undermining itself by means of an interlevel contradiction-yet before long it
tires of the confusion and jumps out of the loop into contemplation, possibly on the
purpose or interest of the idea, possibly on the cause or resolution of the paradox,
possibly simply to another topic entirely.
A trickier variant is "This sentence contains one error." Of course it is in error,
since it contains no errors. That is, it contains no spelling errors ("first-order errors").
Needless to say, there are such things as "second-order errors"-errors in the counting of
first-order errors. So the sentence has no first-order errors and one second-order error.
Had it talked about how many first-order errors it had, or how many secondorder errors it
had, that would be one thing-but it makes no such fine distinctions. The levels are mixed
indiscriminately. In trying to act as its own objective observer, the sentence gets
hopelessly muddled in a tangle of logical spaghetti.
C. H. Whitely invented a curious and more mentalistic version of the fundamental
paradox, explicitly bringing in the system thinking about itself. His sentence was a barb
directed at J. R. Lucas, a philosopher one of whose aims in life is to show that Gödel’s
work is actually the most ineradicable uprooting of mechanism ever discovered-a
philosophy, incidentally, that Gödel himself may have believed. Whitely's sentence is
this:
Lucas cannot consistently assert this sentence.
Is it true? Could Lucas assert it? If he did, that very act would undermine his
consistency (nobody can say "I can't say this" and remain consistent). So Lucas cannot
consistently assert it-which is its claim, and so the sentence is true. Even Lucas can see it
is true, but he can't assert it. It must be frustrating for poor Lucas! None of us share his
problem, of course!
Worse yet, consider:
Lucas cannot consistently believe this sentence.
For the same reasons, it is true-but now Lucas cannot even believe it, let alone
assert it, without becoming a self-contradictory belief system. To be sure, no one would
seriously maintain (we hope!) that people are even remotely close to being internally
consistent systems, but if this kind of sentence is formalized in mathematical garb (which
can be done), so that Lucas is replaced by a well-defined "believing system" L, then
The Riddle on the Universe and its Solution
278
there arises serious trouble for the system, if it wishes to remain consistent. The
formalized Whitely sentence for L is an example of a statement that the system itself
could never believe! Any other bell system is immune to this particular sentence; but on
the other hand is a formalized Whitely sentence for that system as well. Every "bell
system" has its own tailor-made Whitely sentence-its Achilles' h
These paradoxes all are consequences of a formalization of an o vation as old as
humanity: an object bears a very special and u relationship to itself, which limits its
ability to act upon itself in the it can act on all other objects. A pencil cannot write on
itself; a fly sw cannot swat a fly sitting on its handle (this observation made bye German
philosopher-scientist Georg Lichtenberg); a snake canno itself; and so on. People cannot
see their own faces except via ext aids that present images-and an image is never quite
the same a original thing. We can come close to seeing and understanding ours
objectively, but each of us is trapped inside a powerful system w unique point of viewand that power is also a guarantor of limited And this vulnerability-this self-hook-may
also be the source o ineradicable sense of "I."
Malcolm Fowler's hammer nailing itself is a new version of the ouroboros. (From Vicious Cird*.f Infinity:
An Anthology of Paradoxes by Patrick Hughes and George Brecht.)
The Riddle on the Universe and its Solution
279
The "Short Circuit" serves to illustrate the short circuit of logical paradox. The negative invites
the positive, and the inert circle is complete. (From Vicious Circles and Infinity.)
But let us go back to Cherniak's story. As we have seen, the selfreferential linguistic
paradoxes are deliciously tantalizing, but hardly dangerous for a human mind. Cherniak's
Riddle, by contrast, must be far more sinister. Like a Venus's-flytrap, it lures you, then
snaps down, trapping you in a whirlpool of thought, sucking you ever deeper down into a
vortex, a "black hole of the mind," from which there is no escape back to reality. Yet who
on the outside knows what charmed alternate reality the trapped mind has entered?
The suggestion that the mind-breaking Riddle thought would be based on selfreference provides a good excuse to discuss the role of looplike self-reference or
interlevel feedback in creating a self-a soulout of inanimate matter. The most vivid
example of such a loop is that of a television on whose screen is being projected a picture
of the television itself. This causes a whole cascade of ever-smaller screens to appear one
within another. This is easy to set up if you have a television camera.
The results [see figure] are quite fascinating and often astonishing. The simplest
shows the nested-boxes effect, in which one has the illusion of looking down a corridor.
To achieve a heightened effect, if you rotate the camera clockwise around the axis of its
lens, the first inner screen will
The Riddle on the Universe and its Solution
280
A variety of effects that can be achieved using a self-engulfing television system. (Photographs b Douglas
R. Hofstadter.)
The Riddle on the Universe and its Solution
281
appear to rotate counterclockwise. But then the screen one level farther down will be
doubly rotated-and so on. The resulting pattern is a pretty spiral, and by using various
amounts of tilt and zoom, one can create a wide variety of effects. There are also
complicating effects due to such things as the graininess of the screen, the distortion
caused by unequal horizontal and vertical scales, the time-delay of the circuit, and so on.
All these parameters of the self-referential mechanism imbue each pattern with
unexpected richness. One of the striking facts about this kind of "self-image" pattern on a
TV screen is that it can become so complex that its origin in videofeedback is entirely
hidden. The contents of the screen may simply appear to be an elegant, complicated
design-as isapparent in some shown in the figure.
Suppose we had set up two identical systems of this sort with identical
parameters, so that their screens showed exactly the same design. Suppose we now made
a tiny change in one-say by moving the camera a very small amount. This tiny
perturbation will get picked up and will ripple down the many layers of screen after
screen, and the overall effect on the visible "self-image" may be quite drastic. Yet the
style of the interlevel feedback of the two systems is still in essence the same. Aside from
this one small change we made deliberately, all the parameters are still the same. And by
reversing the small perturbation, we can easily return to the original state, so in a
fundamental sense we are still "close" to where we started. Would it then be more correct
to say that we have two radically different systems, or two nearly identical systems?
Let us use this as a metaphor for thinking about human souls. Could it be valid to
suppose that the "magic" of human consciousness somehow arises from the closing of a
loop whereby the brain's high level-its symbol level-and its low level-its
neurophysiological level-are somehow tied together in an exquisite closed loop of
causality? Is the "private I" just the eye of a self-referential typhoon?
Let it be clear that we are making not the slightest suggestion here that a
television system (camera plus receiver) becomes conscious at the instant that its camera
points at its screen! A television system does not satisfy the criteria that were set up
earlier for representational systems. The meaning of its image-what we human observers
perceive and describe in words-is lost to the television system itself. The system does not
divide up the thousands of dots on the screen into "conceptual pieces" that it recognizes
as standing for people, dogs, tables, and so forth. Nor do the dots have autonomy from
the world they represent. The dots are simply passive reflections of light patterns in front
of the camera, and if the lights go out, so do the dots.
The kind of closed loop we are referring to is one where a true
The Riddle on the Universe and its Solution
282
representational system perceives its own state in terms of its repe of concepts. For
instance, we perceive our own brain state not in t of which neurons are connected to
which others, or which ones are fi but in concepts that we articulate in words. Our view
of our brain is as a pile of neurons but as a storehouse of beliefs and feelings and id We
provide a readout of our brain at that level, by saying such thin "I am a little nervous and
confused by her unwillingness to go to the party. Once articulated, this kind of selfobservation then reenters the system as something to think about-but of course the reentry
proc via the usual perceptual processes-namely, millions of neurons fi The loop that is
closed here is far more complex and level-muddling the television loop, beautiful and
intricate though that may seem.
As a digression it is important to mention that much recent progress in artificial
intelligence work has centered around the attempt to give a program a set of notions
about its own inner structures, and ways, reacting when it detects certain kinds of change
occurring inside its At present, such self-understanding and self-monitoring abilities of
grams are quite rudimentary, but this idea has emerged as one of the prerequisites to the
attainment of the deep flexibility that is synonymous with genuine intelligence.
Currently two major bottlenecks exist in the design of an arts mind: One is the
modeling of perception, the other the modeling of learning. Perception we have already
talked about as the funneling of a m low-level responses into a jointly agreed-upon
overall interpretation the conceptual level. Thus it is a level-crossing problem. Learning
is a level-crossing problem. Put bluntly, one has to ask, "How do symbols program my
neurons?" How do those finger motions that you execute over and over again in learning
to type get converted slowly systematic changes in synaptic structures? How does a oncecon activity become totally sublimated into complete unconscious oblivion The thought
level, by force of repetition, has somehow "reached do ward" and reprogrammed some of
the hardware underlying it. The same goes for learning a piece of music or a foreign
language.
In fact, at every instant of our lives we are permanently changing synaptic
structures: We are "filing" our current situation in our mem under certain "labels" so that
we can retrieve it at appropriate timers the future (and our unconscious mind has to be
very clever doing since it is very hard to anticipate the kinds of future situations in w we
would benefit from recalling the present moment).
The self is, in this view, a continually self-documenting "worldline (the fourdimensional path traced by an object as it moves through time and space). Not only is a
human being a physical object that inter
The Riddle on the Universe and its Solution
283
Nally preserves a history of its worldline, but moreover, that stored worldline in
turn serves to determine the object's future worldline. This largeline harmony among
past, present, and future allows you to perceive scale your self, despite its ever-changing
and multifaceted nature, as a unity with some internal logic to it. If the self is likened to a
river meandering through spacetime, then it is important to point out that not just the
features of the landscape but also the desires of the river act as forces determining the
bends in the river.
Not only does our conscious mind's activity create permanent side effects at the
neural level; the inverse holds too: Our conscious thoughts seem to come bubbling up
from subterranean caverns of our mind, images flood into our mind's eye without our
having any idea where they came from! Yet when we publish them, we expect that wenot our subconscious structures-will get credit for our thoughts. This dichotomy of the
creative self into a conscious part and an unconscious part is one of the most disturbing
aspects of trying to understand the mind. If-as was just asserted-our best ideas come
burbling up as if from mysterious underground springs, then who really are we? Where
does the creative spirit really reside? Is it by an act of will that we create, or are we just
automata made out of biological hardware, from birth until death fooling ourselves
through idle chatter into thinking that we have "free will"? If we are fooling ourselves
about all these matters, then whom -or what-are we fooling?
There is a loop lurking here, one that bears a lot of investigation. Cherniak's story
is light and entertaining, but it nonetheless hits the nail on the head by pointing to
Gödel’s work not as an argument against mechanism, but as an illustration of the primal
loop that seems somehow deeply implicated in the plot of consciousness.
D.R.H.
Download