Notes on Pragmatics GXNU Graduate Program in Linguistics & Applied Linguistics Edited by Shaozhong Liu Vol. 1 Issue No. 2005(2) Address: College of Foreign Studies, Guangxi Normal University, Guilin, 541004, China Website: http://www.gxnu.edu.cn/cofs; Email: szliu@mailbox.gxnu.edu.cn From the Editor…………………………………………………………………………………...2 Some issues in pragmatics Chen Huai……………………………………………………………………………………………………..2 He Ning…………………………………………………………………………………………………………………….2 Jing Andian…………………………………………………………………………………………………………….…..3 Lai Tao…………………………………………………………………………………………………….….4 Liao Jinchao……………………………………………………………………………………………….….4 Liu Bin…………………………………………………………………………………………………….…..5 Liu Taomei……………………………………………………………………………………………….……6 Liu Tingting…………………………………………………………………………………………………..7 Meng Jieqin…………………………………………………………………….…………………………….8 Ou Lianfen……………………………………………………………………………………………………8 Song Yuge…………………………………………………………………………………………………….9 Sun Yan……………………………………………………………………………………………………….9 Tang Wensheng……………………………………………………………………………………………….10 Tang Xia……………………………………………………………………………………………………...11 Wang Kaiwen………………………………………………………………………………………………...11 Wang Liyuan……………………………………………………………………………………………………………..12 Wang Wenbo………………………………………………………………………………………………….12 Wei Yunhui……………………………………………………………………………………………………13 Xu Hui………………………………………………………………………………………………………..13 Xu Zhaojuan………………………………………………………………………………………………….14 Zhou Yanqiong……………………………………………………………………………………………….15 Zhou Yuping………………………………………………………………………………………………….15 From the Editor Issue 2, 2005, is based on the students’ understanding summaries of Chapter 2, of Jacob Mey’s (2003) Pragmatics: An Introduction (pp.19-36). It tries to outline the scope of pragmatics. Subtitles in Chapter 2 includes: 2.1 The pragmatic waste-basket………………………………………………………………19 2.2 Linguists without borders…………………………………………………………………21 2.3 Philosophers, ordinary people and ordinary language…………………………………….23 2.4 Of cats and ducks………………………………………………………………………….25 2.5 Linguistics and reality: Presupposition……………………………………………………27 2.6 A world of users……………………………………………………………………………29 Please enjoy. Liu, SZ, at UNCG Some issues in pragmatics Chen Huai (jesschenh@yahoo.com.cn; Sun, 24 Apr 2005 19:54:25 +0800 (CST)) To many philosophers and logicians, pragmatics is regarded as the ‘waste-basket’ of linguistics. When they try to explain language by means of ‘science’, which they consider logically, they are intended to idealize the way and the process of people talking. Pragmatics, as a result, is far from the notion of waste-basket. The truth is that it is not the abstract form of a sentence itself weights most, but the use of language and the users. It cannot be meaningful without taking into our daily life and daily language, like the fish cannot alive without water. So the concrete context seems to be the foundation of pragmatics. In order to find against those traditional thinking towards pragmatics, there are conflicts on the development of modern pragmatics, as the British pragmatician Geoffrey Leech put it “a process of colonization”, which can indicate the wave-by-wave expansion of linguistics. However, not everybody agree to the so-called nature of this conflict. The word of Lyons may give us some hints: “However abstract, or formal, modern linguistic theory might be, it has been developed to account for the way people actually use language.” (Lyons, cited from Mey, 2001:22) Still, some philosophers maintain that language has to obey the laws of logic—— “if logic is the ‘handmaid of philosophy’, then language certainly is the handmaid of logic.” Does everybody always consider the laws of logic first, before they carry through their conversation? Is it the case that the laws of logic govern the flow of our communication? (i.e., logic is prior to language). If so, I’m afraid that people may talk about nonsense, since language is dynamic, concrete while logic turn out to be more abstract. Furthermore, their overlapping seems too small. Logic does not prove to give us a satisfied answer to language use. We’d better turn back to our ordinary life and ordinary language, in a word, to the real environment of language. A sentence may seem to be confused in isolated way, and background information solves lots of problem. As we may notice that sentences become vivid in certain context. An important notion which Mey mentions in this chapter, is presupposition. It is believed as the aspects of meaning that must be pre-supposed, understood, taken for granted for an utterance to make sense. Here, Mey illustrates what presuppositions are considered in several sentences. For presupposition rests on the user context, they are pragmatic, instead of semantic. Then, the study of language users should reemphasize in the pragmatic research. (To the top) He Ning (elvahening@eyou.com; 1 Apr 2005 15:20:18 +0800) In chapter 2, Mey mainly tells us that how pragmatics developed from the “waste-basket of semantics” into an independent and important domain of the linguistic research. 2 Firstly, Mey generally explained why pragmatics was called the “waste-basket of semantics”. At the beginning, the semantics was called the “waste-basket of syntax”. In the late fifties and early sixties, linguists tried to make linguistics a science. Thus they applied many mathematical methods to the linguistic study. Linguistics was ideally considered as an algebra of language. In the mid-fifties, Chomsky developed his famous theory of generative-transformational grammar. Although he knew the domain of his research is somewhat limited, he concentrated his attention on grammar and pay no attention to the study of meaning. In this way, semantics came to be called the “waste-basket of syntax”. In the early seventies, some linguists began to try to turn the study of meaning into the foundation of the linguistic study instead of syntax. Semantics mainly concerns about the conditions under which a sentence could be true or false. In the semantic research, linguists found that many language phenomena could be explained by semantic theory, but these phenomena didn’t attract much attention at that time. All their unsolved questions were thrown into a new basket, pragmatic basket. Some natural language does make sense, but we can’t prove it to be true. These problems kept bothering the linguists, but were left to be unnoticed. Later these unsolved questions became the main items of the pragmatic study. In this sense, pragmatics became the waste basket of semantics. Secondly, Mey introduced in detail the traditional methods and theories of linguistics and the questions remained to be solved. “In the Chomskyan linguistic tradition, well-formedness plays the role of the decision-maker in questions of linguistic ‘belonging’: a language consists of a set of well-formed sentences, and it is these that ‘belong’ in the language; no others do.”(Chapter2 P25) In 1968, Lakoff published an article, entitled “Presupposition and relative well-formedness”. Lakoff , for the first time, publicly rejects in writing the formal-logic criterion of syntactic “well-formedness”. Chomsky considers this criterion as the ultimate standard to judge a linguistic production. However, what we perceive as correct in the real communication often collides with the correctness as prescribed by some grammarians. For example, according to English grammar we should us who when we are dealing with a noun which is human (and naturally animate), whereas we use which for a noun-human (possibly also non-animate) referent. (Chapter2 P25) But sometimes we don’t obey the rule in the ordinary language. For example, we usually use who to refer to our motherland or our pet. If not, it would be unacceptable. The semantics and pragmatics may be somewhat alike in terms of the subject of the research. Both of them deal with the meaning, but what the semantists only concern about is whether the sentence is true or false. Then some problems arise. Some sentences don’t have true value, but it does make sense in the natural language in a certain situation. Some sentences have the same ‘true conditions’(that’s to say they are logically equivalent), but these sentences clearly don’t have the same meaning. Some semantists noticed these problems, but they just left them unsolved. Only when we take the language user and the context into consideration, can we find the answers to these questions. Later, these unsolved questions became the main issues of the pragmatic study. What is of my special interest is the relationship between syntax, semantics and pragmatics. Semantics was once regarded as the waster-basket of syntax, while pragmatics was once called the waster-basket of semantics. From syntax to pragmatics, the domain of the linguistic research is enlarged step by step and the study becomes more and more practical. In fact, syntax is the foundation of syntax, and pragmatics is based on the research of syntax and semantics. And linguistics gradually develops into a versatile subject covering almost every aspect of knowledge concerning language. (To the top) Jing Andian (robertbai2003@163.com; Mon, 25 Apr 2005 18:47:01 +0800 (CST)) Chapter 2 is still basically about the research scope of pragmatics in the whole system of language. In this chapter, the author defines the problem of research scope of pragmatics step by step by the means of contrasting pragmatics with syntax and semantics in the respect of form, meaning and language use. Meanwhile, he discusses the relationship of language with logic and context. From the discussion, it seems he is intended to inform us pragmatics aims at studying how the language user to use and interpret it under the condition of social context. Specifically, there are 4 problems addressed in this chapter. First, he continues to discuss the status of pragmatics in the language in its early stage of development. When pragmatics shows its appearance, as a scientific branch of linguistics, in the linguistic study, it is called the waste-basket of linguistics by the linguists from other branches of linguistics from the view of its study scopes, since pragmatics takes the problems which syntax and semantics are unable to deal with by their own theories as its study focuses, just like a waste picker. From this point of view, we could predict that one day there might be something called ‘waste-basket of pragmatics’ if pragmatics could not solve all the problems left by syntax and semantics. Fairly speaking, all the branches of linguistics are just tentative approaches attempting to deal with the problems in language. Second, the author discusses the borderlines of different branches of linguistics in the language study. He argues that there in 3 not real border between the different linguistic branches. In fact, all the branches are to some extent accessible to each other. It could be easier to solve the problems in language if they work jointly. Third, he discusses the relationship between language and logic. In his opinion, the language or its use has little, if not nothing, to do with logic. He clarifies this point with the help of the example of ‘getting married’ and ‘having a child’. But it seems he confuses us by his following discussion of presupposition. In my opinion, the presupposition is built up with the help of implying and inferring, even though he adds CP to it, whereas implying and inferring belong to the category of logic. Forth, he emphasizes again the importance of context in the process of interpreting the language in actual use. From his discussion, we may conclude that context –‘the linguistic version of the human condition’ – is the most important factor while interpreting the language use. What is of especial interest to us is that pragmatics seems to be human-oriented or human-centered from his discussion of extralinguistic factors and context. If this is the case, pragmatics is comprehensive linguistic study of language. (To the top) Lai Tao (byyourside@sina.com; Sat, 23 Apr 2005 21:52:43 +0800) This chapter is basically about what on earth pragmatics is and its impact on the traditional linguistics. First, the author deals with the long-existing comment on pragmatics, i.e. pragmatics is often called “waste-basket of linguistics”. Despite its negative connotation, this way of saying acquired a certain status, especially in the early years of pragmatics. The reason? More and more unresolved questions by linguists were dropped away. Something must be done to solve them. Then, “pragmatic basket” came into being, catching the overflow of the “semantic basket”. Pragmaticians take little interest in the truth value of a sentence, but rests on the cooperation between language users. However, pragmatics has to deal with the “crawling worms” in their basket. Second, “colonization” was once used to describe the development of modern pragmatics by Geoffrey Leech, which consists of two elements: (1) conflicts back home; (2) “internal conflict”. The author points out that it was not the linguists but the philosophers whose reflections on the language had a significant and lasting impact on the development of modern linguistics, especially pragmatics. Third, “ordinary language philosophy” puts strong emphasis on the way people use their language, however, logic and language do not travel too well together, and the amount of ground they cover between them is rather small. (2.3: 23) Fourth, pragmatics also brings great impact on the “well-formedness” imposed by Chomsky. What we perceive as correct often collides with correctness as prescribed by some grammarians. Actually, “ extra linguistic factors” often enter in judgments of “well-formedness”. Then, the author moves on to explain the factors, which include context and language users. The importance of these two factors is also recognized by other people or linguists, which proves the primary status of the factors. Liao Jinchao (samliao1@163.com; Wed, 23 Mar 2005 23:31:58 +0800 (CST)) This chapter is basically about some issues in pragmatics and the author provides his opinions about these issues too. These issues include: First, the pragmatic wastebasket. In this section, the author tells the development of linguistics from Noam Chomsky’s generative-transformational grammar to semantics and then to pragmatics; Second, language and logics. In this section, we can find the author’s opinions about language and logics as well as the different perspectives of philosophers and ordinary people on language; Third, presuppositions. Sometimes, a sentence cannot be understood without pragmatic presupposition and the author thinks that presuppositions are not semantic but pragmatic. Fourth, users and contexts. Our understanding of utterances depends crucially on the worlds in which the language users live by. Mey thinks “Pragmatics specifies …context as one in which the users are of paramount interest. (Mey, Pragmatics: An Introduction 2001: p 30) What is of special interest to us is that pragmatic focus more on context and language users than other linguistic researches. Language is used by ordinary people. Language is not only an abstract system but a common human communicative tools of ordinary people. The interest in the users of language is among the main factors that have made pragmatics possible (Mey, 2001:p29). 1. The development of pragmatics Geoffrey Leech regarded the development of modern pragmatics as a process of colonization. But in Mey’s 4 opinion, the opposition between pragmatics and its counterpart linguistic researches is only the opposition between a practical and a theoretical approach to the study of language, between the theoretical and the applied linguists. In the mid-fifties, Noam Chomsky developed his generative-transformational grammar in which he made syntax into the main component of the grammar. And in his theory, sentences can be described perfectly well on the syntactic level without ever having to mean anything (Mey, Pragmatics: An Introduction 2001: p.20) As for semantics, it mainly concerns the conditions under which a sentence could be true or false. When semantic developed to a certain stage, pragmatics comes to help explain what semantics cannot explain. In a pragmatician’s eyes, the truth-value of a sentence is of little interest for people rarely utter something in order to be proven true of false. 2. Logic and language In many philosophers’ eyes “language is the handmaid of logic”(Mey, 2001:p23) and our everyday language is a variant of the pure language of logic. In Chomskian theory, language can be formally explained by mathematical rules. But Mey thinks that logic is in essence an abstraction from language and should never be made its dominant perspective. 3. Presuppositions Presupposition is not only of semantic or logical essence but a pragmatic one too. Sometimes neither a purely logical account nor an exclusively semantic account will be satisfactory in the explanation of a sentence. Mey thinks, “Since presuppositions rest entirely on the user context, they are pragmatic rather than semantic.” (Mey, 2001:p29) 4. Users and contexts The interest in the users of language is among the main factors that have made pragmatics possible. Our understanding of utterances crucially depends on the worlds in which their speakers live. As for context, pragmatics specifies context as one in which the users are of paramount interest. (To the top) LIU Bin (liubin54100101@sina.com; Tue, 26 Apr 2005 11:12:12 +0800) In this chapter, the writer talks about several issues in pragmatics. In the first section, he tells readers that though pragmatics is often called the “waste-basket of linguistics”, it is useless. In fact, we are in urgent need of pragmatics because many questions cannot be solved without pragmatics. Linguistics was ideally conceived of as”algebra” of language. However, when we try to apply formal methods to our daily life we realize that life is more than a mathematical abstraction. There are a large number of phenomena which syntax and semantics are unable to explain. For this reason, pragmatics is an indispensable part of linguistics. The second section begins with Geoffrey Leech’s comparison between the development of modern pragmatics and a process of colonization. Pragmatics came into being in the opposition between a theoretical and a practical approach to the study of language, between the “theoretical” and the “applied” linguistics. In the third section, the writer discusses the relationship between logic and language. Many people used to consider that language is a matter of logic and a correct use of language presupposes the use of logic. Contrary to this, Austin’s opinion is that people communicate by means of language, not necessarily defined as the ensemble of correct sentences or logically valid propositions. So logic is in essence an abstraction from language and should never be made into its dominant perspective. The fourth section talks about some ideas of George Lakoff’ which are opposite to Chomskyan linguistic traditions. In Chomsky’s opinion, a language consists of a set of well-formed sentences, and it is these that “belong” in the language. However, what we perceive as correct often collides with correctness as prescribed by some grammarians. In the fifth section, the author briefly talks about “presupposition”. Many linguists used to believe that meaning is something that should be dealt with outside of linguistics. The very term “extralinguistic” carried with it the connotation of “unscientific”, and suggested that the linguist relying on outside information somehow was cheating on method. However, the very idea of “extralinguistic” is suspect. The meaning of a sentence often depends on the context where the sentence appears. Presupposition plays an important role in language users’ understanding of sentences’ meaning. When language users perceive a sentence they not only form an idea of the sentence itself but also suppose that something else accompany it. Sometimes a Presupposition may be true but it also happens that it might be contrary to the truth. In the sixth section, the author discusses the importance of context and language users in linguistic research. Now we have realized that language is not an abstract system and the renewed interest in the users of language has made pragmatics popular. But we still need to ask such a question: how can we explain this interest, and where did 5 it come from? Since users and their language are at the core of all things pragmatic, the “world of users”is the very condition for doing any pragmatics. The meaning of utterances often depends on the worlds where their speakers live. If a listener of a sentence knows little about the society where the speaker lives, he may misunderstand the meaning of it. Listeners of different culture might understand the same sentence differently. (To the top) Liu Taomei (ltaomei@126.com; Sun, 24 Apr 2005 11:14:02 +0800 (CST)) This chapter is basically about what is pragmatics and what role it plays in the research of linguistics. There are 5 things addressed in the reading: The origin of the notion ‘waste-basket’ which linguistics often call pragmatics; the development of modern pragmatics; the relationship between logic and language; some problems in syntax and some extralinguistic factors ,such as presupposition and the users of a language. First, Mey elaborates the origin of the notion ‘waste-basket’ which linguistics often call pragmatics. According to Mey, ‘waste-basket’ does not mean uselessness, but implies that it can explain the problems that other fields of linguistics cannot explain. Secondly, Mey illustrates the development of modern pragmatics. Geoffery Leech once compared the development of modern pragmatics to a process of colonization. One of the conflicts which drive the linguists to explore is the opposition between a theoretical and a practical approach to the study of language. Another more ‘internal’ conflict is the opposition of the idea that all of linguistic science (inclusive phonology and semantics) fit into the syntactic framework. Lakeoff proposed an alternative framework, ‘generative semantics’ in the late sixties. And the publication of J.R. Searle’s work Speech Acts encourages Chomsky’s rebellious students to make the first inroads into the pragmatic territory. Thirdly, Mey discusses the relationship between logic and language. For many philosophers and ordinary people, logic is prior to language. In contrast to this view, the linguists put strong emphasis on the way people use their language. The most famous representative is John.L. Austin, the ‘father of speech act theory’. The title of his book How to do things with words contains an implicit question, the answer to which is that people communicate by means of language, not necessarily defined as the ensemble of correct sentences or logically valid propositions. Many of the early discussions on the foundation of pragmatics have been on the possibility and desirability of letting pragmatic conditions govern the correct use of logical propositions. Unfortunately, logic and language do not travel too well together. Mey proves it by two examples and makes a conclusion that ‘ logic is in essence an abstraction from language and should never be made into its dominant perspective, this holds in matters of both syntax and semantics.’(Jacob L.Mey, 2001:24) Fourthly, Mey talks about some problems in syntax that arise from the use of the logic-inspired rewrite rules that were devised by Chomsky and his school. In the Chomskyan linguistic tradition, a language consists of set of well formed sentences, and it is these that ‘belong’ in the language, no others do. However, what perceive as correct often collides with correctness as prescribed by some grammarians. In 1968, George Lakeoff published an article, entitled ‘Presupposition and relative well-formedness’. In the article, Lakeoff for the first time, publicly and in writing, rejects the formal-logic criterion of syntactic ‘well-formedness’, imposed by Chomsky as the ultimate standard by which to judge a linguistic production. Lakeoff remarks ‘extralinguistic factors very often enter in judgments of ‘well-formedness’. It is precisely those ‘extralinguistic factors’ that open the door for apparently ungrammatical behavior. Fifthly, some extralinguistic factors ,such as presupposition and the users of a language , are discussed individually in the last part of this chapter. Many linguists used to believe that meaning is something that should be dealt with outside of linguistics. According to some linguists, the “survival’ property of a presupposition is built into the very semantics of a particular lexical item, a word. For others, presuppositions are inextricably tied to a particular lexical item. However, most cases are not such clear-cut instances of semantic or logic presupposition. Most of the time, neither a purely logic account, based solely on the truth or falsity of sentences in isolation, nor an exclusively semantic account, based on the value of individual lexical items, will be satisfactory; we must appeal to a pragmatic explanation, based on the particular context of a particular mutterer. Since presupposition rest entirely on the user context, they are pragmatic, rather than semantic. Moreover, since all interaction is impossible without the presence of ‘interactants”, the ultimate ‘real-world’ presupposition is the pragmatic ‘actant’, the language user. As to the question why linguists become interest in the users of language. There are several reasons for that. Since users and their language are at the core of all things. Pragmatic, the ‘world of users’ is the very condition for doing any pragmatics: a truly existential condition. All these phenomena(along with many others, sometimes called ‘extralinguistic’ can be brought together under the umbrella of context, basically the linguistic version of the 6 ‘human condition’. (To the top) Liu Tingting (hetao1126@sina.com; Wed, 30 Mar 2005 11:41:30 +0800) This chapter is basically about some issues associated with pragmatics, including some concerns on philosophy as well as on linguistics. In this way, the author intents to give us a further explanation for pragmatics and the scientific quality in the study of pragmatics. There are six things in the reading: the pragmatics waste-basket; linguists without borders; philosophers, ordinary people and ordinary language; of cats and ducks; linguistics and reality: presupposition; a world of users. First, the pragmatic waste-basket. Pragmatics is often called the “waste basket ”of linguistics, for it tend to solve some linguistic problems that other blanches of linguistics cannot deal with. In the early stages of in study on linguistic, linguistics was ideally conceived of as an “algebra” of language. However, we people try to apply the mathematical methods to daily life, they realize that life is more than a mathematical abstraction and the language used by ordinary people in daily life is quite flexible, which is not always obey some strict rule. For example, from a syntactic point of view, some sentences are perfectly correct, however, are strictly meaningless. Since syntax has nothing to do with meaning, such problems are left to the semantics, which deals with meaning. In this way, semantics came to be called the “waste basket ”of syntax. As long as semantics remained an abstract science whose man concern was the conditions under which sentence could be true or false, it was unable to explain certain phenomena that transcended those conditions. For instance, how to explain that certain pars of a sentence remain true, regardless of whether the entire sentence is true or false? Such considerations led pragmaticians to the conviction that there wee more things happening between people than were dreamt of by the philosophers. As time went by, the linguists dropped more and more of their unresolved questions into the new, pragmatic basket. The pragmatic waste-basket is more like a can of worms: the problem that in the basket contains tend to spill over into all the domains of linguistic thinking. Second, linguists without borders. In this part, the author mentions some conflicts lie in the field of liguistic study. The British pragmatician Geoffrey Leech has compared the development of modern pragmatics to a process of colonization, by which some brave settlers tried to expand their horizons by venturing into hitherto uncharted territory. In this colonization, there are many conflicts. Such as, the conflict between a theoretical and practical approach to the study of language, between the “theoretical” and the “applied ” linguists. And another more internal conflict originated in the “syntacicism”of the Chomskyan school of linguists, whereby all of linguistic science was supposed to fit into the syntactic framework. Third, philosophers, ordinary people and ordinary language. This part is basically about the relationship of language and logic. Traditionally, philosophers busying themselves with problems of language have concentrated on the relationships between logically defined expressions, and sentences in natural language. As to ordinary people discussing problems of language, language is a matter of logic. For many philosophers and lay people alike, logic is thus prior to language. In contrast to this view, ordinary language philosophy puts strong emphasis on the way people use their language. In the book How To Do Thing With Words, John L. Austin mentions that people communicate by means of language, not necessarily defined as the ensemble of correct sentences or logically valid propositions. And many of the early discussions on the foundation of pragmatics have been on the possibility and desirability of letting pragmatics conditions govern the correct use of logical proposition. But logic and language do not travel too well together, and the amount of ground cover between them is rather small. The language is a matter of logic to mean; a correct use of language presupposes the use of logic. Forth, of cats and ducks. In this part, the author discusses the ambiguity that the syntax system meets with in the language use of daily life. In the Chomskyan linguistic tradition, well-formedness plays the role of the decision-maker in questions of linguistic “belonging”: a language consist of a set of well-formed sentences, and it is these that “belong” in the language; no others do. However, Chomskyan system has come most often under attack from the quarters of “OWLs”, and makes least sense if we for a moment consider what it is that people really say, and how they judge well-formedness in relation to their own language’s correctness. In our daily life, there are general cases, in which extralinguistic factors very often enter in judgments of well-formedness as Lakolf remarks (G. Lakoff, 1971b: 330) It is precisely those extralinguistuc factors that open the door for apparently ungrammatical behavior. Fifth, linguistics and reality: presupposition. This part is basically concerned on the problem of “real ”meaning of the sentence in daily life. To a pragmatician, the very idea of “exralinguistic” meaning, s if belonging to another, forbidden “real” world, is suspect. In conversion, utterances often contain some underlying elements, which remain constant. Such an element is often called a presupposition. And according to some linguists the “survival” property of a presupposition is built into the very semantics of a particular lexical item, a 7 word. For others, presuppositions are inextricably tied to a particular lexical item. However, most cases are not clear- cut instances of semantic or logical presupposition. Most of time in order to get the real meaning of the sentences, we must appeal to a pragmatic explanation, based on the particular context of a particular utter. Thus, we can make a conclusion that, since presupposition like the ones discussed rested entirely on the user context, they are pragmatic, rather than semantic. Sixth, a world of user. This part is concerned on that the understanding to some conversion greatly depends on the different environments which the user of language, the speaker’s linguistic, social, cultural and general life context. In another word, an utterance does not make any sense until we place it in its human context. What is of especial interest to us in this chapter is that in the study of pragmatic, different ideas are raised by linguists and the arguments on such ideas, promote the development pragmatic reach. In this way, many unclear issues on pragmatics become explicit. After my reading of this chapter, I get a further understanding about pragmatic, especially some important item in the pragmatic field. (To the top) Meng Jieqin (mjqwb5172@21cn.com; Sun, 24 Apr 2005 19:59:57 +0800 (CST)) Chapter two is basically about some issues in pragmatics. There are 6 things addressed in the reading: First: it is about the pragmatic waste—basket. The notion of waste—basket goes back to Yehoshua Bar-Hillel (1951—75). Syntax doesn’t focus on meaning. The meaning is left to semanticists. So semantics is called the waste—basket of syntax. The main concern of semantics was the conditions under which a sentence could be true or false. But there are more and more unsolved questions (conditions), which are dropped into pragmatic basket. The pragmatic waste—basket tend to spill the problem into all the domains of linguistic thinking. Second: it is about the conflicts between a theoretical and practical approach to the study of language. John Lyons thinks there is no real conflict in linguistics, except in the mind of people. Chomskyan School of linguistics thinks the origin of conflict in the syntacticism. Lakoff and Searle believe that. In fact, it was not the linguists who were the first to discover and explore pragmatics, but the philosophers. Third: it is about the relationship between language and logic. Philosophers think that logic is prior to language; but for the pragmatist, language and logic don’t correspond well to each other. Four: it is about syntactic well—formedness. Chomskyan School believes that well—formedness plays the role of the decision—maker in questions of linguistic ‘belonging’. While anti--Chomsky School thinks so too. Extralinguistic factors often enter in judgments of well—formedness, which is proved from a general case of cats, ducks and penguins. Five: it is about presupposition. It is conclude that presuppositions rest on the user context; they are pragmatic rather than semantic. Six: it is about context. No matter traditional linguist or pragmatist they believe that our understanding of utterance depends on human context. And for pragmatics, all language phenomena are under umbrella of context. Ou Lianfen (willie9830@sina.com; Fri, 6 May 2005 10:28:17 +0800) The chapter discusses some issues in pragmatics such as pragmatics waste-basket, presupposition and language users. Firstly, Mey elaborates the origin of the notion of the “waste-basket”. Pragmatics is often called the “waste-basket” of linguistics. The notion goes back the Israeli logician-philosopher and linguist Yehoshua Bar-Hillel, who also called semantics the waste-basket of syntax.. Chomsky came up with a suggestion for trash-disposal :he explain the fact that certain sentences didn’t make sense , even though they were perfectly good constructions, by saying that when combining words into sentences, you had to take certain precaution. Secondly, Mey discusses the relationship between linguistics and reality. He introduces the property of the presupposition by explaining some cases. The British pragmatician Geoffey Leech has compared the development of modern pragmatics to a press of colonization. The eminent British linguist Sir John Lyons argues that there was no real conflict between the abstract and practical. Language is a matter of logic, which is prior to language. In contrast to this view, the school usually referred to as ordinary language philosophy puts strong emphasis on the way people use their language. 8 In the Chomskyan linguistic tradition, well-formedness plays the role of the decision-maker in questions of linguistic belonging: a language consists of a set of well-formed sentences, and it is these that belong in the language. Of persons who engage in interaction, the ultimate real-world presupposition is the pragmatic actant, the language user. Since users and their language are at the core of all things pragmatic, the word of users is the very condition for doing any pragmatics. Thirdly, Mey points out the importance of putting the users in the context to make pragmatics possible. Since users and their language are at the core of all things pragmatics, the world of users is the very condition for doing any pragmatics: a truly existential condition. Our understanding of utterances depends on the worlds in which their speakers live, both in general with regard to the conditions of their lives. These worlds of users can only be discovered by looking at the way language is used in those worlds. (To the top) Song Yuge (songyg2005@163.com; Tue, 26 Apr 2005 21:57:20 +0800 (CST)) Pragmatics, once regarded as the “waste-basket” of semantics, makes its way in linguistics and now is a new branch of linguistics. However, pragmatics contains too much, sometimes even invades the fields of other science. So Mey listed some issues that are noticeable in our study in this chapter. Firstly, Mey pointed out that some pragmaticians often colonize in the field of syntax or semantics, and at the same time, there are conflicts inside pragmatics, that is, the opposition between a theoretical and a practical approach to the study of language. But, the field of pragmatics is also occupied partly by various tribe of philosophers. Then Mey went on with the topic that what the philosophers did in pragmatics field. Some philosophers think that language is a matter of logic, and our daily language is a bastardized and illegitimate variant of the pure language of logic. Of course, this idea is criticized by Mey. He pointed out that pragmatics should emphasize the way people use their ordinary language, and he thought highly of John L. Austin, the “father of speech act theory”, who had an enormous influence on the development of pragmatics. Thirdly, Mey said frankly what we perceive as correct often collides with correctness as prescribed by some grammaticians, about which he gave us some examples. Also he pointed out the way to solve the above problem, that is, “those extralinguistic factors open the door for apparently ungrammatical behavior. He meant explicitly that pragmatics can explain the conflict between what people really say and the rules of the grammaticians. Next, Mey talked about presupposition and defined it(an underlying element which remains constant----). Some linguists said presupposition is semantic, but Mey argued that in most cases, presupposition is more than just a matter of implying and inferring abstract conditions on speaking, it is an active choice made in the face-to-face confrontation. At last, Mey drew a conclusion: -----since presupposition discussed here rest entirely on the users context, they are pragmatic, other than semantic. Finally, though pragmatics is fully accepted as a new part of linguistics, Mey still asked a question: where did pragmatics come from? And then he himself answered the question. Users and their language are at the core of all things pragmatic, the “world of users” is the very condition for doing pragmatics. “world of users” cannot be predicted from the language viewed as a logical system, but can only be discovered by looking at the way language is used in these worlds. Mey emphasized the importance of the context in pragmatics. In this chapter, Mey continued to explain what is pragmatics and told us the border of pragmatics study according to some difficulties we met with in studying linguistics. Sun Yan (yanyansun@126.com; Thu, 28 Apr 2005 13:21:17 +0800 (CST)) Chapter 2, Pragmatics: An Introduction, Mey, Jacob L. pp. 19-35, begins with the pragmatic waste-basket, following by such issues as philosophers in the field of pragmatics, their devotion to pragmatics, the relation between well-formedness and the extra-linguistic factors, presupposition and users’ role in pragmatics. First, the question of why pragmatics is a wastebasket is considered. This notions goes back to the 1970s, when semantics was called the ‘waste-basket of syntax’. It was so because when Noam Chomsky developed his theory of generative-transformational grammar in the mid-fifties, syntax was made a main component of grammar and was completely divorced from the meaning of the language. So when people saw a sentence that was meaningless, but which was also syntactically correct, they left it to semantics. Yet, as linguists stepped further into the domain of semantics, they found a lot that couldn’t be explained by semantics. The unresolved was discarded into another waste-basket, which later become the main concern of pragmatics. Pragmaticians are not interested in the truth value of a sentence, taken in its abstract form. Instead they rest their study on the 9 cooperation between language users. Soon pragmatic problems seem to spread into all the domains of linguistic thinking. If one thinks pragmatics is studied by linguists only, he will be taking things for granted. The second issue addressed in this chapter is that linguists are without borders. When early pragmaticians ventured into what later became known as pragmatic territory, they found an indigenous breed of philosophers of language quietly cultivating the territory for some time. These philosophers’ reflections on language had a significant and lasting impact on the development of modern linguistics, especially, pragmatics. The next issue will be what these philosophers have been doing. They concentrated their study on the relationship between logically defined expressions and sentences in natural language. They and many ordinary people considered logic prior to language. Another school, representing by Austin, put strong emphasis on the way people use their language. One of the heated discussions has been on the possibility and desirability of letting pragmatic conditions govern the correct use of logical propositions, when disguised as ‘ordinary language’ utterances. Unfortunately, when expressing language in the form of logical propositions, people find they don’t mean the same. Mey concludes the relation between ordinary language and logic with the citation from Strawson: “ordinary language has no exact logic”. ( Note that there is logic in language, but not necessarily in ordinary language.) The fourth issue under discussion is the relation between well-formedness and the extra-linguistic factors. Constructio ad sensum (construction according to the sense) is taken as an example to reject the formal-logic criterion of syntactic ‘well-formedness’, imposed by Chomsky, as the ultimate standard by which to judge a linguistic production. The example of referring to ‘duck’ as ‘it’ and ‘penguin’ as ‘he’ is a case in point to introduce Lakoff’s remarks that extra-linguistic factors often open the door for apparently ungrammatical behavior. The fifth section examines the notion of presupposition, which is defined as something that a speaker or writer assumes that the receiver of the message already knows. Mey further argues that semantically different utterances may have the same presupposition. Therefore, presupposition may rest on the user context. The last thing is the role that the world of users plays in pragmatics. Users’ activities constitutes what linguists called ‘ human condition’ and to pragmatists, context. What interests us most is the notion of logical proposition as is mentioned in 2.3. If, according to to the rule of logic, the formula p&q is logically equivalent to the formula q&p. How come p&q is better than q&p? (As the sentence Getting married and having a child is better than having a child and getting married indicates.) To understand the logic in this sentence, we probably should turn to logic in linguistics for further interpretation. Tang Wensheng (wwsstang@sina.com; Thu, 12 May 2005 23:31:24 +0800) This chapter is basically about some issues in pragmatics. There are 4 things addressed in the reading: First, the development of pragmatics: Pragmatics is often called the ‘waste-basket’ of linguistics. How did this come about? The notion of waste-basket goes back to the Israeli logician-philosopher and linguist Yehoshua Bar-Hillel, who called semantics the ‘waste-basket of syntax’ in 1971, when Chomsky made syntax into the main component of the grammar, completely divorced from the semantics, the meaning of the language. As long as semantics remained an abstract science whose main concern was the conditions under which a sentence could be true or false, it was unable to explain certain phenomena that transcended those conditions. This led pragmaticians to the conviction that there were more things happening between people than were dreamt of by the philosophers. The semantics basket being filled to the brim, another waste-basket had to be created to catch the overflow. As time went by, the linguists dropped more and more of their unreserved questions into this new, pragmatic basket. Pragmatics now has come to the center stage of linguistics. For pragmaticians the truth value of a sentence, taken in its abstract form, is of little interest. Pragmatics rests on the cooperation between language users. Leech has compared the development of modern pragmatics to a process of colonization. Of course, there were conflicts on the home front. One is the opposition between a theoretical and a practical approach to the study of language. Another conflict is in the syntacticism and generative semantics. Second, logic and language: Traditionally, philosophers busying themselves with problems of language have concentrated on the relationships between logically defined expressions and sentences in natural languages. What is the relationship of language and logic? Many of the early discussions on the foundation of pragmatics have been on the possibility and desirability of 10 letting pragmatic conditions govern the correct use of logical propositions. Unfortunately, logic and language do not travel too well together. For many philosophers and lay people alike, logic is prior to language. In contrast to this view, ordinary language philosophy put strong emphasis on the way people use their language. For example, 1) Getting married and having a child is better than having a child and getting married. 2) Having a child and getting married is better than getting married and having a child. Although these two sentences have the same truth condition or is logically equivalent, the two sentences clearly do not have the same meaning, in everyday life as in everyday language use. Third, linguistics and reality: Many linguists used to believe that meaning is something that should be dealt with outside of linguistics. Since linguistic meaning only could be studied through speakers’ utterances in situations, we shouldn’t be worried about ‘real’ independent meaning (Bloomfield,1950). To a pragmatician, the very idea of ‘extralinguistic’ meaning, as if belonging to another, forbidden ‘real’ world, is suspect. According to some linguists, the ‘survival’ property of a presupposition is built into the very semantics of a particular lexical item, a word. However, most cases are not such clear-cut instances of semantics or logical preposition. We must appeal to pragmatic explanation, based on the particular context of a particular utterer. That is to say, presuppositions rest entirely on the user context. Finally, a world of user: The interest in the users of language is among the main factors that have made pragmatics possible. Users and their language are at the core of all things pragmatic. Notice that the intended use in a particular instance often depends more on the specific context and tone of voice than it does on the grammatical form or vocabulary of what is said. The context is the total social setting in which the speech event takes place. The simple declarative sentence, "I'm hungry," for example, could be used to report on a physiological condition, or to express a feeling, or implicitly to request that someone feed me. In fact, uses of two or more varieties may be mixed together in a single utterance; "Stop that," for example, usually involves both expressive and directive functions jointly. In many cases, however, it is possible to identify a single use of language that is probably intended to be the primary function of a particular linguistic unit. British philosopher Austin developed a similar, though much more detailed and sophisticated, nomenclature for the variety of actions we commonly perform in employing ordinary language. While the specifics may vary, some portion of the point remains the same: since we do in fact employ language for many distinct purposes, we can minimize confusion by keeping in mind what we're up to on any particular occasion. What is of special interest to us is that pragmatics rests on the operation between language users. The full meaning of an utterance may not even be accessible to the users at the time of speaking or hearing, as long as they do not know what motivates the other’s use of language. (To the top) Tang Xia (lenatx01981@yahoo.com.cn; Mon, 25 Apr 2005 19:56:59 +0800 (CST)) At the beginning of the chapter two, Mey compared pragmatics to the waste-basket of linguistics, by which embodied its all-inclusivity. It concerns all the domains of linguistic thinking and imposes its unruly order on our explanation. In language research, there are linguists without borders. It’s possible that the conflict between the “theoretical” and “applied” linguistics. Another is the internal conflict. Before linguists, there is an indigenous breed of philosophers of language who were the first to discover and explore the territory of pragmatics. The philosophical “truth conditions” sometimes are in trouble in language use. With the same “truth conditions ”, the two sentences may clearly do not have the same meaning. And, grammar also cannot explain all the problems in language use. There are always many extralinguistic factors, such as the context. In some conditions, according to their presuppositions, the sentence is contradicted to each other, but in fact, it can exist logically. Then pragmatics can make it sense by giving it a proper context. And because of the different world of users, things always have different meaning. Mey defined further what is pragmatics and its importance in language research, by talking about the existence of the linguists without border, the “truth condition ”and grammar being in trouble in language use and the world of users in this chapter. (To the top) Wang Kaiwen (loadstar97kw@sina.com; Mon, 25 Apr 2005 13:30:54 +0800) 11 This chapter is further talking about what is pragmatics and what kinds of linguistic phenomena to which it can apply. As we know, research on linguistics can date back to as long as two thousands years ago, and researchers have established many basic branches of linguistics in which syntax and semantics are mainly involved. But as time goes and proceeding of linguistic research, there are more and more problems came into being which cannot be resolved just in linguistic domain, pragmatics, then, formulated. There are three things addressed in the chapter two: First, how is pragmatics come into being and what is its ability to explain linguistic phenomena. There are a great many of sentences cannot completely explained by syntaxists or by semanticist. For example, supposed, person A said to person B in classroom:“ Would like to go to the cinema tonight?” and B replied: “I have to do my homework..” What meaning his answer attend to express? Go or not to go? We cannot make a decision about this only turn to syntactic or semantic methods, because the meaning of the answer is based on context. And from pragmatic aspect, we can imply that B wouldn’t like or cannot to go, for homework and play cannot go together at same time, and the answer is an indirect speech act (from pragmatic view) to not offend the speaker and to save the speaker’s face. Second, presupposition is a crucial part in pragmatics and has great explanatory function when deal with utterances. This is an advantage of pragmatics compared with syntax and semantics. For example, there is a cannot-be-answered question in ordinary occasions: “ Have you stopped to beat your wife?” Why? Because whether your answer is yes or no you would undoubtedly stepped into a trap and in embarrassment, that is to say, you confess you had taken violence to your wife. Presupposition of the question is that you have beaten your wife. If it did not exist, the question is not exists too. But it is really an embarrassed question in quarrels. Third, context is a focus of pragmatics. What is context? Context concludes not only words or utterances which occurs before/ after the sentence, but the total social setting in which the speech event takes place, especially the interlocutors’ mental, social and physical situations. For a example, someone asked Edison after his innumerous failures to construct a dry cell battery, “if you discouraged by the fact that he have no results?” “No results? I now know of 936 things that don’t work.” Apparently, in questioner’ opinion, Edison is a loser for he have had no results, but, Edison don’t think so, he regard failures as another kind of success or bridge to success. Differences between them, here, is their different attitudes towards success in scientific research. this physical world also involved body of context and plays significant role in explanations of utterances. What is most interesting to me in this chapter is the notion of presupposition, for it shows that linguistic cannot isolated from reality and there are many ex-existed conditions which guarantee a utterance’ values in reality. While paradoxes utilize it in some cases, the paradoxes are worthless in real lives. But presupposition are still help us reason, imply and decide meanings which speakers really want to say, thus, communication can go smoothly. Wang Liyuan (catherine200661@sina.com; Fri, 01 Apr 2005 11:52:57 +0800) This chapter is basically about some issues in pragmatics, and further explains what is pragmatics and what kind of academic characteristics pragmatics have. There are 5 things addressed in this reading. First, the author explains why pragmatics is called “waste-basket”. Because semantics remains to concern which a sentence could be true or false, it was unable to explain certain phenomena that transcended those conditions. Second, Leech has compared the development of modern pragmatics to a process of colonization. The author thought the territory of pragmatics is made by philosophers. In author’s opinion, there are no borders in linguistics. Third, philosophers think: “Logic is prior to language”. The author takes some linguistic phenomena for example, such as truth value of sentences. Then the author thought ordinary language has its ordinary logic. Pragmatics puts language into a certain context and makes the language related with its users. Four, it talks about the presupposition. There must be presuppositions in a conversation, or the conversation will not go on. Semantic presuppositions relate the presuppositions with sentences, but pragmatic presuppositions relate the interlocutors with presuppositions. Presupposition is a part of context. Five, it talks about the world of users. It further explains the process the pragmatics development. (To the top) Wang Wenbo (bobomaoheboboyu@tom.com; Tue, 26 Apr 2005 07:16:23 +0800 (CST)) 12 This chapter discusses several issues in pragmatics. First, just as semantics is the ‘waste-basket of syntax’, pragmatics is the waste-basket of semantics. For a long time semantics remained a science whose main concern was the conditions under which a sentence could be true or false, it was unable to explain certain phenomena that transcended(or sometimes even voided) those conditions. Many ambiguous sentences led pragmaticians to the conviction. Second, pragmatics can solve the problems of left by logics. Many of the early discussions on the foundation of pragmatics have been on the possibility of letting pragmatic conditions govern the correct use of logical propositions. We can identify our everyday language conjunction ‘and’ with the logical conjunction ‘&’, and they are not the same meaning. Third, in grammar, some linguistic phenomena exist extralinguistic factors. The grammarians usually can’t use grammar rules to correct them. So usually the meaning only could be studied through speakers’ utterances in situations, which usually contain an underlying element the ‘proposition’. We shouldn’t be worried about ‘real’, independent meaning. Besides, presupposing is more than just a matter of implying and inferring abstract conditions on speaking. Fourth, pragmatics is the users of language. If specifies this context as one in which the users are of paramount interest, inasmuch as they represent the driving force behind the linguistic enterprise, both in its theoretical (grammar-oriented) and its practical(usage-bound) aspect. (To the top) Wei Yunhui (whitman@163.com; Fri, 29 Apr 2005 12:00:26 +0800 (CST)) This chapter just goes on with the fields involved in pragmatics, in the beginning, Mey names pragmatics a “waste-basket” of semantics, just the same as what the Israeli logician-philosopher and linguist Yehoshua Bar-Hillel(1915-75) called semantics of syntax. It is true that, as the world changes, so does the language, more and more unresolved language questions by semantics are dropped into this new, pragmatics basket, which, Mey points out, is not only a receptacle for discardables, but more like a can of worms. Actually the next sections of this chapter show the fact that pragmatics is on its way: Firstly, the British pragmatician Geoffrey Leech has compared the development of modern pragmatics to a process of colonization, along with which go some conflicts. They may exist between outside or inside of pragmatics, and just because of these conflicts, pragmatics goes forwards rapidly. Here what is of especial interest to us is that it was not the linguists who were the first to discover and explore the terra incognita of pragmatics, but the philosophers. Then in the next section Mey goes on with the topic on the role the philosophers play in the development of pragmatics. Some philosophers concentrate on the logic of language and think that a correct use of language presupposes the use of logic, and our everyday language is a bastardized and illegitimate variant of the pure language of logic. In contrast to this view, the school of ‘ordinary language philosophy’ like John L. Austin, puts strong emphasis on the way people use their language, and Mey more agrees to this view. In the following section, Mey points out that some contradictions still occur between what we perceive as correct and correctness as prescribed by some grammarians. He uses some concrete examples to demonstrate this and indicates that extralinguistic factors very often enter in judgement of well-formedness and it is precisely these ‘extralinguistic factors ’ that open the door for apparently ungrammatical behavior. And then comes the discussion of presupposition, which, some linguists think, depends on semantics or logic. While Mey indicates that this must appeal to a pragmatic explanation, based on the particular context of a particular utterer. He concludes that , since presuppositions rest entirely on the user context, they are pragmatic, rather than semantic. And finally since it is the fact that pragmatics now is a fully accepted part of linguistics, Mey lead us to the question: how can we explain pragmatics? where did it come from? It is users and their language that are at the core of all things pragmatic, and the ‘world of users’ is the very condition for doing any pragmatics. Also Mey points out ‘context’, an important fact in pragmatics. (To the top) Xu Hui (echowaiting@sina.com; Mon, 25 Apr 2005 22:38:42 +0800) Chapter Two goes into more detail about the pragmatic look and discusses some more issues in pragmatics. There are three things addressed in this reading report. First, the author talks about the change of the role of pragmatics. Pragmatics is often called the “waste-basket” of 13 linguistics where linguists drop unsolved and heterogeneous problems. Nevertheless, many scholars have already cultivated the territory of pragmatics, especially the philosophers, whose reflections on language had a lasting impact on the development of pragmatics. Second, the author refers to the logical analysis on language. In contrast to the view that logic is prior to language, the school of “ordinary language philosophy” puts strong emphasis on the way people use their language, because truth conditions of sentences cannot explain all the problems in language. John L. Austin is a famous scholar of this school. The third part is of special interest to us. Before George Lakoff publicly rejects the formal-logic criterion of syntactic “well-formedness” imposed by Chomsky, well-formedness decides linguistic “belonging”. However, for pragmatics extralinguistic factors often judge well-formedness. Presupposition is a case of such factors. According to the author, presuppositions in real interactions rest entirely on the user context, they are pragmatic rather than semantic. Therefore, language users and their language are the focus of pragmatic study. An utterance can make sense only when we put it in its human context. And in this users context, we should also pay attention to such notions as “register”, “the modal aspects of the utterance’’ and so on. (To the top) Logic or illogic? Xu Zhaojuan (ajuan2003@163.com; Tue, 26 Apr 2005 10:41:17 +0800 (CST)) This reading / chapter is basically about some issues in pragmatics. The author talked about many things in this chapter, including the pragmatic waste-basket, linguistis without borders, philosophers, ordinary people and ordinary language, of cats and ducks, linguistics and reality: presupposition, a world of users and so on.. What is of especial interest to us is that pragmatics is often called the ‘the waste-basket’ of linguistics. The notion of waster-basket goes back to the Israeli logician-philosopher and linguist Yehoshua Bar-Hillel, who called semantics the ‘waste-basket of syntax’. To see what he meant by this, we have to consider the ambitions of linguistics as a science in the late fifties and early sixties, with its emphasis on formal reasoning and abstract symbolism. Linguistics was ideally conceived of as‘algebra’ of language; the expression was first used by Hjelmslev in 1943, but has been borrowed by many. The phenomena of real life cannot be exhaustively accounted for by the idealizations that are typical of mathematical methods and which, strictly speaking, do not exist. For example, in mathematics even such a simple thing as a line is not a line in reality, but only a well-defined concept, to which the line I draw on the ground or on paper is but a poor approximation. In the mid-fifties, when Noam Chomsky developed his famous theory of ‘generative transformational grammar’, he was aware that much of what he said the grammar could do was valid only for a limited subset of the language, with all the fringes cut off. In his earliest attempts, Chomsky made syntax into the main component of the grammar, completely divorced from the semantics, the meaning of the language, and postulated that sentences could be described perfectly well on the syntactic level without ever having to ‘mean’ anything- just like algebraic formulas, which, taken by themselves, don’t mean anything until we assign values to the variables, but still can be quite easily tested for correctness. From this point, many sentence is perfectly correct, however, it is strictly ‘meaning-less’. Since syntax has nothing to do with meaning, and should be left to the people dealing with meaning, the semanticists. The semantics basket being filled to the brim, another waste-basket had to be created to catch to overflow. As time went by, the linguists dropped more and more of their unresolved questions into this view, pragmatics basket, which became a not-too-tidy collection of rather heterogeneous problems, many of which kept bothering the linguists, in particular those defending a pragmatic approach. The linguistic philosophers, also want to know the sentence in order is true or false. People rarely utter something in order to be proven true or false. We want to know why people say something; weather what they say is true or false is only interesting in special surroundings, such as the philosophical debate or the courtroom. Unfortunately, logic and language do not travel too well together, and the amount of ground they cover between them is rather small. Let’s look at this well-known case: (1) Getting married and having a child is better than having a child and getting married. Supposing we can identify our everyday language conjunction and with the logical conjunction ‘&’, we would be looking at a logical proposition of the form p (‘getting married’) & q (‘having a child’), expressed in everyday language by means of a sentence like the above. Such an utterance should then, by the laws of logic, be equivalent to the proposition q (‘having a child’) & p (getting married). Hence, the above utterance would be logically equivalent to the one below: (2) Having a child and getting married is better than getting married and having a child. 14 So, there is no difference in semantics content between p and q, or between ‘getting married and having a child’ and ‘having a child and getting married’. We have to provide a pragmatic account, along the following lines. The ‘and then’ reading of both ands in the first sentence can be shown to be systematically ‘read in’ to conjoined reports of events by a pragmatic principle governing the reporting of events by pragmatics principle governing the reporting of events. The sentence can only be assigned the right truth conditions, or alternatively be given the correct semantic representation, if the pragmatic significance of and in this sentential context (namely the ‘and then’ interpretation) is taken in account before doing the semantics. This amounts to a concise argument that semantics is not autonomous with respect to pragmatics, and that pragmatics provided part of the necessary input to a semantic theory. But if pragmatics is, on occasions, logically prior to semantics, a general linguistic theory simply must incorporate pragmatics as a component or level in the overall integrated theory. (3) If you give me a bite of your ice-cream, you can have a bite of mine (4) He turned on the switch and the motor started We read this in a way that is as ‘strong’ as the world allows. Given p and q, try interpreting it as: (i) ‘p and then q’; if successful try (ii) ‘p and therefore q’; if successful try also (iii) ‘p, and p is the cause q’ So the philosopher’s idea as the language should be obey the reality the order. ‘And’ not means the ‘&’, so language is not the logic, extra linguistic factors very often enter in judgments of well-formedness’. (To the top) Zhou Yanqiong (higherjojo@tom.com; Fri, 6 May 2005 12:44:02 +0800 (CST)) In this chapter Mey first introduced how the notion-- the pragmatic “waste-basket” came into being. Mey introduced the history of the notion “waste-basket”. The Israeli logician- philosopher and linguist Yehoshua Bar-Hillel first called semantics the ‘waste-basket of syntax’, as people thought more about what went into the semantic waste-basket and why, linguistic dropped more and more of the unresolved questions into another basket—pragmatic basket.yet Mey thought pragmatics was far from a receptacle, what pragmatics contains concerns all the domains of linguistic thinking.Then Mey demonstrated what is pragmatics from the following several aspects. (1)Mey talked about the development of modern pragmatics from the point of colonization.just like colonization there must be conflict between something, because the conflict linguists came to know the pragmatic territory which was not first discovered and explored by linguists but by the philosophers. (2) Both philosophers and ordinary people think logic is prior to language, Mey gave two examples which are contradict with what philosophers and ordinary people thought. And the examples of “cat” and “duck” which are contradict with the grammer while from the point of extralinguistic factors both of them can be thought corret. (3)For some linguists ,presuppositions are inextricably tied to a particular lexical item, as to the presuppositons Mey gave an examples to illustrate in most cases we must appeal to a pragmatic explanation. (4) At last, Mey explained when we want to understand a language we must take consideration of the world of its users. Zhou Yuping (bingxueping123@163.com; Fri, 25 Mar 2005 12:14:44 +0800 (CST)) This chapter is basically on some issues in pragmatics. The first one is that pragmatics is often called the “waste-basket” of linguistics a few decades ago. The famous linguist,Noam Chomsky divided a neat and clear line between syntax and semantics, and let some problems grammar can’t dissolve ascribe to semantics, when he developed his famous theory of “generative—transformational grammar”. Several decades later, linguistic trash affected the attention of the philosophy. Its trash disposal brought about the new born of pragmatics. Later during the process of venturing into hitherto uncharted territory of linguistics, the British pragmatician Geoffrey Leech proposed the hypothesis of colonization. But not everyone agreed with him, especially in the realm of the “theoretical” and the “applied”. The eminent British linguist Sir.John. Lyons strongly argued that there was no ‘real’ conflict between the ‘abstract’ and the ‘practical’. But in fact, why did a number of people apparently think there was? To gain a satisfactory reply, Chomsky’s rebellious students, such Robert and Lakoff, turned their sights into the sphere what later became 15 known as pragmatic territory. But to their grat surprise, these Lord Marchers of the Language Realm found the invaded region already populated, and even partly cultivated, by various tribes of philosophers. The second is philosophers and pragmatics. Traditionally, philosophers busying themselves with problems of language have concentrated on the relationships between logically defined expressions and sentences in natural languages. They hardly had the same idea as ordinary people that language is a matter of logic, and it was inveterate and hard-to-change that logic is prior to language. Until John L. Austin published the “father of speech act theory” and “How to do things with words”(1962), people gradually put strong interest on the way people use their language. The writer cited three examples to test the relationship between logic and the use of language. Logic is in essence an abstraction from language and should never be made into its dominant perspective, this holds in matters of both syntax and semantics. The third emphasis is on some problems in syntax that arise from the use of the logic-inspired rewrite rules that were devised by Chomsky and his school. In 1968, George Lakoff published an article entitled ‘Presupposition and relative well—formedness’. In this article, for the first time, Lakoff rejects the formal—logic criterion of syntactic ‘well—formedness’. Through certain examples, the writer proposed ‘extralinguistic factors’ during communication. Many linguists used to believed that the very term ‘extralinguistic’ carried with it the connotation of ‘unscientific’, since linguistic meaning could be studied through speakers’ utterances in situations not just utterances themselves. The same sentence can analysis completely different meanings if their situation is different, e.g. the presupposition is different the meaning of sentences is different. The last of the chapter concentrated on the users of language. Compared to the earlier focus on language as an abstract system, users of language are the main factors that have made pragmatics possible. These ‘worlds of users’ cannot be predicted from the language just as a logical system or other theories of linguistics. Bilmes has perspicuously remarked: “the meaning of an utterance is determined in large part by how it responds and how it is responded to, by its place in an interactional sequence”. The most interesting one for me is the second topic, logic and linguistic. Logic is prior to language , or language decided logic, it is still a contradictory topic in academic circles. The topic is of great value to human, it can implement into other extensive fields and help to explain many problems befuddled people so far. Theory combined with practice can be invaluable, otherwise it has no sense. (To the top) 16