Back to Realism Applied to Home Page Biological Psychology, 37 (1994) pp. 177-180. Rediscov_rev92.doc J. Searle, The Rediscovery of the Mind. (MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, 1992) pp. xv + 270, $22.50. Watson's arguments (e.g. Watson, 1913) against the inclusion of mind and consciousness in psychology held considerable sway in the minds of many experimental psychologists of the forties and fifties, and was particularly strong in the American S-R Hull-Spence brand of behaviorism. At the University of Iowa, where Spence "reigned", the standing orders to use the expression "What's on your behavior?" rather than "What's on your mind?" were only half in jest. Psychology's Cognitive Revolution which began to gather force in the mid-sixties appeared to bring mind back into psychology, but as contemporary supporters of the cognitive shift, Segal and Lachman (1972), noted, the changeover was not on the basis of contrary evidence, but more a matter of what they called a Kuhnian "paradigm shift". In other words, the shift was made on instrumentalist rather than realist grounds, that is in terms of what was convenient and "fruitful" rather than what was true. The instrumentalist approach has continued in psychology to the present. The term "cognitive" is now used to qualify most psychological areas of investigation, and has passed from being a low-status expression to a high-status one with an extension that is infinitely broad, and tends to encompass almost all things psychological. The realist distinction between a model (which is just an analogy, and, although it may be useful for generating theory, is itself not one because it does not assert a testable proposition) and theory (which does assert something to be the case, and is therefore evaluable in terms of its truth, rather than mere "fruitfulness") has been generally abandoned by most current psychological researchers. And the computer model or analogy of the mind has been widely accepted not only by those who state it explicitly (e.g. many workers in the area of Artificial Intelligence) but also by most of the concepts in cognitive psychology that employ expressions such as input/output, neglect affective and conative factors (that computers do not possess), and treat the mind (and the brain) as an information processor. The result of this approach has been that, while mentalistic language is frequently used in current cognitive psychology, the explanatory concepts are formulated in computereze, so that the mental processes themselves have been banished to a metaphorical realm of computer modeling. The title and text of Searle's book argues for a serious reinstatement of mind in psychology's explanatory concepts, and the argument is along evidential, realist lines. SSDI 0301-0511(93)00923-S 2 Book review / Biological Psychology 37 (1994) 177-180 The key concept in Searle book is consciousness, which was precisely Watson's bete noire. And "in rediscovering consciousness—the real thing, not the Cartesian ersatz nor the behaviorist doppelganger", he hopes at the outset of the book that we shall "also rediscover the mind" (p. xv). But why should experimental psychologists and psychophysiologists trouble to embark on this predominantly philosophical voyage of rediscovery? The book is clearly intended, in the first place, for professional philosophers, and both because of the readership of this journal and because of my own lack of specialist training in the field, I shall not attempt to provide an in-depth, philosophical critique of the book (for which, see, e.g. Nagel, 1992). Rather, I shall take an experimental psychophysiological research perspective that, nevertheless, for reasons argued elsewhere (e.g. Furedy, 19881, recognizes the importance of the reflective element in any empirical research, be it pure or applied, or some mixture of the two. From this perspective, one important long-term question for the scientific community is whether its current scientific understanding of the relevant phenomena (and, from an applied point of view, its ability to control those phenomena) is clearly superior to the common-sense, proverbial intelligent-man-in-the-street level. Another related question is whether there is good evidence that there is progress in understanding and control. Finally, there is the old but still relevant requirement of the Ionian pre-Socratic thinkers such as Thales (who, by the way, were not only philosophers, but also people with strong practical interests), that whatever explanations are offered they should "save the appearances", rather than consigning observed phenomena either to non-existence (as Watsonian behaviorists suggested for mind) or merely analogical existence (as is done by the current computeranalogy-based explanations). Searle's Chapter 9, entitled (in a Kantian play on words—neither the book nor Searle appears to suffers from any false modesty) "The Critique of Cognitive Reason" is especially relevant for current cognitive psychology's most salient area—Cognitive Science ((3). Some of the arguments may be relatively tough going for those not used to philosophical discussion, but there are at least two factual claims which are both readily intelligible, and strongly damaging to the CS approach whose foundations Searle characterizes as "shaky". One of these is his assertion that the brain does not do information processing (p. 222). If accepted (and I think he provides both strong and simple grounds for the assertion), this assertion alone appears to destroy most of contemporary cognitive psychological (and psychophysiological) theorising about the way in which human and animal (i.e. non-computer) cognition operates, because that theorising assumes (as an unexamined axiom) the information-processing view of mind and brain. This argument, moreover, is stated in the purely cognitive realm. In fact, of course, any adequate psychological explanation has to refer to affective and conative factors as well, and Book review / Biological Psychology 37 (1994) 177-180 3 these non-cognitive factors operate not only in the "real" world, but also in the laboratory. So, for example, just because cognitive psychophysiological researchers using human college-student subjects assume maximal and equal motivational levels for all their subjects (e.g. that all subjects throughout the experiment find the experimental task as riveting and fascinating as does the experimenter) does not mean that these non-cognitive factors are, in fact, held constant. The other basic CS assumption that Searle attacks is the view that psychological cognitive processes are computational. He begins his attack on this claim by remarking that "philosophically speaking, this does not smell right to me and I have learned at least at the beginning of an investigation, to follow my sense of smell" (p. 199). He then provides, in some 20 pages, a number of thoroughgoing arguments to support his philosophical intuitions. One of the main arguments is that equivalence of outcome does not imply equivalence in process. So, to provide an introspectively based example that he does not mention, even though modern computers have come to equal and even perhaps surpass human grand-masters in chess performance, the ways in which the computer and human play are quite different. In brief, the computer simply computes (although the modern computer does so with vast power and precision). In contrast, the mentation involved in the human player comprises cognitive processes that include computation (i.e. calculation of the consequences of certain sequences of moves>, perception, and intuition, as well as non-cognitive factors. These non-cognitive factors include affective ones (e.g. feelings about chess positions as a function of their differing degrees of beauty; fear of blunders [one is reminded of Tartakover's fearsome maxim—the blunders are there, just waiting to be made]; feelings personal inadequacy when faced with a stronger opponent), as well as conative ones (e.g. varying amounts of effort expanded on the game as function of one's physical conditioning, and the importance of the game's outcome). I have already noted that Searle does not suffer from false modesty. In this regard his stated attitude towards referencing the work of others is striking. He confesses that "I think unconsciously I have come to believe that philosophical quality varies inversely with the number of bibliographical references" on the grounds that "books I read in my philosophical childhood... contain few or no references to other authors" (p. xiv). Clearly he does not recognize citations of others as valid coins of the realm, but I think there is at least one contemporary work on which he should have commented, namely The Meaning of Behavior by Australian philosophical psychologist J.R. Maze (1982). Perhaps Searle ignored this book because the title referred to behavior rather than mind, but in fact Maze's book constitutes a thoroughgoing mentalist attack on the same sort of modern cognitive psychology that comprises Searle's main target. However, whereas Searle's 4 Book review / Biological Psychology 37 (1994) 177-180 mentalism is teleological or purposivist, since it regards intentionality as an adequate explanatory concept and part of what it means to cognize (Tolman's position was similarly propositional as well as purposive), Maze's mentalism is mechanistic or deterministic, according to which, in any adequate explanatory account "the first step is to get rid of 'intentions”' (Maze, 1982, p. 27). In fact, it is specifically Searle's earlier writings concerning intentionality (e.g. Searle, 1979) that Maze criticizes in some detail (Maze, 1982, pp. 25-27), using, in the main, Anderson's (1962) earlier critique of the doctrine of constitutive or intrinsic relations. Still, in general, Searle's book constitutes a very effective and clear argument for the rediscovery of the mind, although my preference would have been for a more critical examination of the teleological component (i.e. intentionality) of Searle's position, and more attention paid to affective and conative factors. But for cognitive psychophysiologists the important, though somewhat negative, contribution remains—the demonstration that computer-modeling (i.e. conventional Cognitive Science) can lead to no progress in our understanding even of cognitive psychological functions, let alone non-cognitive ones. This message is one on which many current psychophysiological researchers should reflect, even if that reflection needs perforce take place only in the privacy of that ever-shrinking part of their lives that is not engaged in the acquisition of funding through grant writing, politicking, and the publishing of experimental reports which may advance the approach of a particular "school" in psychophysiology, but which does nothing for genuine progress in the understanding and control of psychological cognitive processes. References Anderson, J. (1962). Studies in empirical philosophy. Sydney: Angus & Robertson. Furedy, J.J. (1988). On the relevance of philosophy for psychological research: Some autobiographical speculations concerning the influence of Andersonian realism. Australian Journal of Psychology, 40, 71-77. Maze, J.R. (1982). The meaning of behavior. London: Allen & Unwin. Nagel, T. (1993). The mind wins! Review of J. Searle, The Rediscovery of the Mind. The New York Review, March 4, 37-41. Segal, E.M., & Lachman, R. (1972). Complex behavior or higher mental process: Is there a paradigm shift? American Psychologist, 27, 46-55. Watson, J.B. (1913). Psychology as the behaviorist views it. Psychological Review, 20, 158-177. John J. Furedy University of Toronto