Stotz

advertisement
Developmental Niche Construction:
an integrative causal factor in evolution
(Commentary on Pigliucci and Kaplan’s Making Sense of Evolution)
Karola Stotz
1. Introduction
Pigliucci and Kaplan’s rather critical evaluation of contemporary evolutionary biology
starts with making a very useful and necessary distinction three levels of analysis of
evolutionary processes, the individual, population and ensemble level. While the first two
contain the actual physical, causal processes that lead to and make possible evolution (by
natural selection), the latter measures statistical distributions of outcomes. The authors
acknowledge and attempt to conceptually integrate several new developments which play
an important role to understand causal processes at the first two levels that strengthen the
active role (populations of) organisms and their development play in evolution. These
accounts are Developmental Systems Theory, which includes and takes serious the idea
of Extended Inheritance, a variety of accounts that run under the heading of Evo-Devo,
Eco-Devo and Devo-Evo, Phenotypic Plasticity including mechanism such as genetic
accommodation and assimilation, and Niche Construction.
This review extends the authors’ treatment of what kind of questions evolutionary
biology is concerned with and which kind of answers would provide their explanations.
Evolutonary biology should explain “ the origin, spread, and maintenance of phenotypic
traits, as well as the developmental pathways that reliably (re)produce them” (Pigliucci
and Kaplan 2007, 112). I want to draw attention to the developmental niche and its active
construction through (populations of) organisms and their parental generation, a process
which has been first been described by Meredith West and Andrew King in 1987, a year
earlier than the first publication about the process of niche construction by Odling-Smee
(West and King 1987; Odling-Smee 1988). While niche construction has since then
almost become a household name in evolutionary theory, not so the idea of the
developmental niche. The importance of the mechanism of ontogenetic niche
construction lies in its integrative power: it combines ideas of the active organism
altering its environment (niche construction), developmental systems theory and extended
(non- or extra-genetic) inheritance, evo-eco-devo and phenotypic plasticity. Because of
the role it plays in explanations of all of the above questions its integration into
mainstream evolutionary theory will be necessary for the continued refinement of this
evolving field.
The process of developmental niche construction contributes to explanation of: a) the
origin of a trait by introducing new epigenetic resources for variation and innovation
beyond mutation and recombination and describing how developmental processes
situated in their ecological niche can produce novel phenotypes; b) the spread of a trait by
showing in detail how organisms or their parental generation co-construct a selective
environment; and c) the maintenance of a trait through processes of transgenerational
stability of variation that extend the inheritance through the transmission of genetic
material with the reliable availability of necessary developmental resources through
multiple mechanisms of reproduction or transmission.
My central claim is that any scientific understanding of the nature of living things,
including its evolution, depends crucially on our understanding of the most basic of
biological processes that brought them about: development. For the longest time this was
not generally accepted by the founders and proponents of the Modern Synthesis for three
reasons: a) The misconstruction of development as the mere unfolding or maturation of
the organism out of its genetic ‘blueprint’ or’ program’, instead of its emergence as
qualitative novelty out of an more or less undifferentiated and unformed mass; b) The
reduction of inheritance and transgenerational stability of traits to the transmission of
genetic ‘information’; and c) The neglect of the problem of evolutionary novelty, the
socalled ‘arrival of the fittest’. Taken together, it has not taken seriously the physical,
causal processes that make possible the creation of adaptation through natural selection,
namely reliably reproducing developmental systems. In other words, evolutionary
biology has hitherto missed to answer the very possibility of evolution through the
variability, adaptability and evolvability of phenotypes.
A new evolutionary synthesis needs to include: 1) A realistic view of gene action,
activation and regulation, that is of pivotal importance to wider theory of evolution since
it stresses the fact of the underdetermination of phenotypic traits through genetic
information and hence the necessity for extended systems of inheritance to supplement
this information. 2) A new understanding of the nature of inheritance, which includes
maternal effects on gene expression, epigenetic factors such as genetic imprinting, and
behavioral, ecological, social, cultural and symbolic inheritance systems. 3) the nature of
stably reproduced, adaptive developmental systems that are sustained through the process
of ontogenetic niche construction.
2. The Modern Consensus of Evolution, Heredity and Development
The turn of the last century saw two important scientific developments that are important
in order to understand our modern understanding of development, evolution and heredity.
Most importantly, its saw the rediscovery of Mendel and the emergence of classical
transmission genetics which ultimately led to its split from embryology and its integration
with Darwin’s theory of evolution by natural selection into Neo-Darwinism and then the
Modern Synthesis under the exclusion of embryology. All the while the rise of
developmental mechanics with its new methodology of manipulating animals in
controlled laboratory settings brought the discipline of embryology, now called
developmental biology, from the sea shore to the indoors. This constrained the choice of
organism, which “must be selected for the inability of their development to be influenced
by specific environmental cues”. In other words, “the influence of … environmental
sources of phenotypic diversity were progressively eliminated under the physiological
context of embryology” (Gilbert 2003, 88f). While this physiological tradition favored
the whole organism at the expense of the environment, transmission and population
genetics and the later emerging molecular genetics focused on genes at the expense of the
organism. Both research traditions discounted and dispensed with both the organism and
the environment understood as both the co-constructed niche of the organism and the
internal cellular environment of the gene and their expression.
The ‘century of the gene’ (Keller 2000) has brought about a new and more sophisticated
preformationism that replaced the older ‘homunculus’ as the preformed organism by the
‘information’ for making an organism encoded in the genome. This new conception is
less a preformationism rather than a kind of ‘animistic’ predeterminism, where genes
‘program’ and therefore predetermine, less than perform, outcomes. True to the spirit of
today’s interactionism the mainstream ‘modern consensus’ can be “standardly construed
as the epigenesis of something preformed in the DNA” (Robert 2004, 34). It rest, quite
problematically, on an unscientific conception of gene and gene action. In its place I want
to promote ‘molecular epigenesis’, a bold thesis about the contingency and epigenetic
regulation of gene expression. It proposes three classes of phenomena, sequence
‘activation’, ‘selection’ and ‘creation’, replacing the misleading metaphor of ‘gene
action’. They more accurately describe what happens during the expression of genes
through transcriptional, pre-, co-, and post-transcriptional processes of DNA coding
sequences.
Molecular Epigenesis contains three sub-theses: 1) Thesis of distributed causal
specificity: Other molecular resources share the causal role of ‘genes’: the ‘causal
specificity’ for the linear sequence of any gene product is distributed between the coding
sequence, cis-acting sequences, trans-acting factors, environmental signals, and the
contingent history of the cell (the cellular code). 2) Thesis of genetic underdeterminism:
These multiple and overlapping processing and targeting mechanisms amplify the
repertoire of RNA and protein products specified through the eukaryotic genome,
expanding the possibilities specified by the literal code of DNA. 3) Thesis of regulated
recruitment, combinatorial control, and systemic organization: These mechanisms of
gene expression change the focus of postgenomic research from single molecules and
their molecular, biochemical and intrinsic function to their cellular, constituent,
component or contextual function due to their recruitment and organization in complex
cellular networks. In other words, all agents involved in the regulation of gene
expression, including DNA, must interact with other agents to achieve full specificity,
which is imposed by regulated recruitment and combinatorial control. I conclude from
these three main theses that organisms necessarily inherit stable developmental resources
that ensure the reliable differential expression of modular genetic resources.
3. Epigenetic regulation of gene expression
Genetic activity is involved in all biological processes, but so are non-genetic factors.
Explanations listing only interacting genes are vacuous statements. Postgenomic biology
has brought with it a new conception from the active gene to the reactive genome that is
activated and regulated by cellular processes that include signals from the internal and
external environment (Stotz forthcoming). This is not the place to report the details now
available on the mind-numbing complexities of the expression of genes during
development, instead a few detail should suffice. The last decade of genome-sequencing
has revealed the paradox that the complexity of organism is not related to its number of
genes. Instead, it seems to be related to the complexity of the expression of this limited
number of coding sequences. In other words, what is of particular importance during
development is not the existence of some genes but their differential time- and tissuedependent expression. In the last two decades development has become equated with
differential gene expression, but what is often forgotten in this definition is the complex
network of other molecules (such as proteins and metabolites), cellular structures, 3dimentional cellular assemblages and other higher-level structures that control or are
otherwise involved not only in this differential expression of genes but in a wide range of
other developmental processes decoupled from the direct influence of DNA sequences.
In eukaryotes DNA is part of a densely packed chromatin structure, which allows it to fit
neatly into the nucleus, but which is also a major mechanism to control gene expression.
The DNA’s weak chemical bond to the histone complex to which it is tightly wrapped to
form nucleosomes (like beads on a string) needs to be broken down in order to free the
DNA molecule to undergo new bonds with transcription factors. Hence the default
position of DNA in eukaryotes is no expression unless expression is activated. Several
large complexes of transcription factors and several other accessory proteins such as
chromatin remodeling factors are needed in order to proceed with the transcription of a
stretch of DNA. Most of these factors are themselves gene products. What is often not
mentioned, however, is the need for environmental inducers for all transcriptional
processes. It generally holds for all eukaryotes that “in the absence of their respective
inducing signal, transcriptional regulators tend not to be found in the nucleus with (in the
case of activators) their activating regions free to work. Rather, activating regions are
masked … or… the regulators are maintained outside of the nucleus, until the inducing
signal is detected” (Ptashne and Gann 2002, 67). Many genes require for their differential
activation the integration of a proper combination of several environmental signals, and
this combination of signals, together with the presence of a particular combinations of
activational factors, controls which exact sequence will be transcribed how much, and it
will also effect cotranscriptional processes such as alternative splicing and RNA editing.
Genes can therefore be expressed in many distinctive ways by different set of signals and
activators. Not only because of these complicating factors of gene expression do we
regard it as important not to downplay development as nothing but gene action and
activation. Genes have an important role in development, but their role can be properly
understood only within the larger system that holds controlling influence over them.
Transgenerational stability need not rely on the faithful transmission of DNA. Genes
depend on the context for their differential expression. Natural selection selects for
adaptive traits or phenotypes, which are always derived from non-linear interactions
among a range of diverse developmental resources. Their organization frequently exhibits
phenotypic plasticity, a capacity that allows the organism to react adaptively to different
environmental conditions (Pigliucci 2001; West-Eberhard 2003). The stable inheritance
of this adaptive phenotype results from the reliable transmission of all the necessary
developmental factors across generations. In other words, phenotypic plasticity relies on
a stable ‘developmental niche’ which is faithfully reconstructed by the species, the parent
and the organism itself. The subject of selection is the whole developmental system.
4. Extragenetic inheritance and developmental niche construction
This construction of the developmental niche relies heavily on the extragenetic
inheritance of developmental resources. This heterogeneous process includes maternal
and paternal (parental) effects, which cannot be reduced to the influence of parental genes
or RNAs on their offspring, but include all processes of care for the offspring. These are
comprised of differential provisioning of resources, preference induction (oviposition,
imprinting on food, habitat, and mates), and social learning, to name just a few (Jablonka
and Lamb 2005; Mousseau and Fox 2003). Niche construction can be understood as one
form of 'extended inheritance'. Inheritance systems have evolved to make the
transmission of crucial information from parents to offspring more reliable. A reliably
reproduced developmental system is the result of the reliable provision of a wide range of
developmental resources necessary to reconstruct the organism’s life cycle, of which
DNA is just one. Additional and equally necessary resources are DNA imprinting
systems, cellular structures, ambient temperature, nutrients, gut organisms, and offspring
care. Organisms have developed a range of strategies to construct the ontogenetic niche
for their offspring to guide the developmental process.
West and King were one of the firsts to “Ask not what’s inside the genes you inherited,
but what your genes are inside of” (West and King 1987, 552). Looking at the enormous
complexity of gene expression of eukaryotes that reveals a very flexible and reactive
genome open to many intra-and extra-organismal environmental influences, it was simply
a matter of time before some systems found ways to manage aspects of their own
developmental environment. It is not so much the particular gene you inherit that counts
but when, where and how a particular sequence is transcribed or translated by the higher
order network of gene regulation that controls the time- and tissue dependent expression
of genes. These mechanisms do not only control when genes are switched on and off, but
also which parts of the DNA sequence will be transcribed, which will be spliced and in
which combination, which will be edited at certain nucleotides, and which will be
translated and at what rate. Some have referred to the particular mixture of gene products
(protein transcription factors and RNAs) and the particular cellular signaling factors they
react to as the cellular code. The cytoplasmic chemical gradients plus the messenger
RNA and transcription factors that are inherited with the mother’s egg give this process a
head start, but the mother’s control over the fetus’ environment does not stop there. Even
after birth rearing practices, such as the licking of pups by rat mothers, continue to
influence gene expression levels. The protein packaging of DNA can be modified in
certain ways to influences which genes are transcribed. This imprinting system, often
called the histone or chromatin code, gives the paternal and maternal genome control
over the offspring’s gene expression.
We can call the design-like control of the next generation’s developmental environment
extended inheritance or just ontogenetic niche construction. Parental activity can
facilitate, guide and entrench social learning, which in the case of humans and higher
animals falls under the rubric of the cultural transmission of information. What all of
these above cases of inheritance through environment construction have in common is
making the transmission of crucial information more reliable. And while some of the
above mechanisms have at first sight not much in common with the construction of
epistemic structure by an extended mind, in the latter cases of behavioral, ecological and
cultural inheritance the biological shades smoothly into the cognitive.
There have been repeated attempts to reduce all of these mechanisms to the action of
inherited or parent-of-origin genes, so that ultimately the real causes are all genetic. This
special pleading fails in the light of the discovery that development relies less on the
existence of genes in an organism than on the regulated expression of these genes, which
ultimately depends on a host of environmental factors. Wherever there are genes there are
extragenetic factors necessary for their regulated expression.
5. A new synthesis of epigenesis, evolution and extended heredity
What a new account of development really has to accomplish is not just to go beyond
these vexed dichotomies such as innate and learned, but to provide a framework that
integrates a complex set of heterogeneous factors into a system of developmental
resources all of which are reliably reproduced in succeeding generations of a
developmental system but none of which really belong alone to either ‘gene’, ‘organism’
or ‘environment’ (the famous “Triple Helix” of Richard Lewontin 2000). Its
contextualization of genes should obviate “even naïve temptations toward
gene/environment dichotomies and … will open up a very rich area of empirical
investigations to examination and conceptualization in developmental-system term”
(Moss 2001, 85). The important systems features of such a view are the rejection of
dichotomous description of behavior in favor of a full analysis in terms of continuing
interaction between, and the joint determination by, heterogeneous developmental
resources. Other important features are extending the idea of inheritance to include other
factors than DNA, including factors formerly thought of as ‘environmental’ or
‘experiential’ if they are reliably reproduced or ‘passed on’ for succeeding generations;
and last but not least the reconceptualization of evolution as (Oyama, Griffiths, and Gray
2001, 4).
DST descibes evolution as construction in which evolutionary change results from the
constructive interaction between all developmental resources, and between populations
and their environments: the various elements of developmental systems coevolve. As we
have seen organisms are not independent of or just passively dependent on their
environments, they and their parental generation actively construct their developmental
niches which is an integral part of the whole developmental system.
References:
Gilbert, Scott F. 2003. The reactive genome. In Origination of Organismal Form: Beyond
the Gene in Developmental and Evolutionary Biology, edited by G. B. Müller and
S. A. Newman. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
Jablonka, Eva, and Marion J. Lamb. 2005. Evolution in Four Dimenesions: Genetic,
Epigenetic, Behavioral, and Symbolic Variation in the History of Life. Cambridge,
MA: The MIT Press.
Keller, Evelyn Fox. 2000. The Century of the Gene. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Lewontin, Richard C. 2000. The Triple Helix: Gene, Organism, and Environment.
Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Moss, Lenny. 2001. Deconstructing the gene and reconstructing molecular develomental
systems. In Cycles of Contingency: Developmental Systems and Evolution, edited
by S. Oyama, P. E. Griffiths and R. D. Gray. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Mousseau, Timothy A., and Charles W. Fox, eds. 2003. Maternal Effects as Adaptations.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Odling-Smee, F. John. 1988. Niche-constructing phenotypes. In The Role of Behavior in
Evolution, edited by H. C. Plotkin. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Oyama, Susan, Paul E. Griffiths, and Russell D. Gray. 2001. Introduction: What is
developmental systems theory? In Cycles of Contingency: Developmental Systems
and Evolution, edited by S. Oyama, P. E. Griffiths and R. D. Gray. Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press.
Pigliucci, Massimo. 2001. Phenotypic Plasticity: Beyond Nature and Nurture, Syntheses
in Ecology and Evolution. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press.
Pigliucci, Massimo, and Jonathan Kaplan. 2007. Making Sense of Evolution: The
Conceptual Foundations of Evolutionary Biology. Chicago and London:
University of Chicago Press.
Ptashne, Mark, and Alexander Gann. 2002. Genes and Signals. Cold Spring Harbor, NY:
Cold Spring Harbor Laboratory Press.
Robert, Jason S. 2004. Embryology, Epigenesis and Evolution: Taking Development
Seriously. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Stotz, Karola. forthcoming. 2001 and all that: a tale of a third science. Biology &
Philosophy.
West, Meredith J., and Andrew P. King. 1987. Settling Nature and Nurture into an
Ontogenetic Niche. Developmental Psychobiology 20 (5):549-562.
West-Eberhard, Mary Jane. 2003. Developmental Plasticity and Evolution. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Download