Voltaire’s Criticisms Berkeley had two principal arguments to prove that we do not directly perceive the extension of bodies: perceptual relativity arguments (esp. with regard to variations in magnitude) anti-abstraction arguments Both sorts of arguments fail and therefore he does not prove his case. Against Perceptual Relativity Arguments There are two kinds of magnitude: apparent magnitude real magnitude Apparent magnitude is measured by the number of minimally visible or tangible points a thing takes up (or the angular portion of the visual field it takes up. Real magnitude is measured by moving a standard unit end over end along a line. While apparent magnitude varies with distance, real magnitude (which is also perceived) does not. Whether you are close to an object or far away, the reading on the tape measure is the same. Reid’s Later Expansions on Voltaire’s Point There are no perceptual relativity arguments concerning tangible position or figure. (The arguments concern differences between vision and touch, or differences between different views of the same object.) The perceptual relativity arguments are based on a misunderstanding of what it is that vision tells us about. Vision tells us just about the compass direction and elevation (“right-ascension” and “declension”) that each of the parts of an object has relative to the position of the eye. Touch tells us about the position that each of the parts of an object has relative to one another. So vision and touch are not telling us different things about the same object, but about different features of the same object: visible position and figure (the figure formed by the combination of the visible positions of all the parts) tangible position and figure Visible position and figure should vary with changes in position and distance, since they are relative to the position of the perceiver. Against the Anti-Abstraction Argument “… extension is not a feeling.” So when we perceive extension we are not having feelings = sensations, and so not perceiving a “sensible thing” we are instead perceiving a real object. Reid’s Expansion on this Argument Our sensations of smell, taste, sound, heat & cold, and even pressure and pleasure/pain are not extended. Our sensation terminology is ambiguous, sometimes referring to the cause of a feeling, sometimes to the feeling. In no case (even that of colour) do we think of the feeling (the state of mind we are in and that exists only in us and only when perceived) as being extended or as having position, figure, or magnitude. We only think this of the cause of the sensation. So, Berkeley’s claims notwithstanding, primary qualities not only can be abstracted from secondary qualities, they are never in fact perceived together. Problems with the Voltaire/Reid case for distinguishing sensation (of secondary qualities) from perception (of primary qualities) pains and other tactile sensations have location relative to one another Reid is just wrong about colour Boullier’s “Transcendental” Argument for the Existence of Body “… the whole commerce of the life of men depends on this agreement in the perceptions that all have of one and the same world as their object and center. Without that, men would not be able to understand each other, or unite together, or communicate with one another in the course of their actions. If we consider society in relation to … its natural state, that [reciprocal] bond [between the people who compose it] is formed by [their] common ideas of a shared world that they take themselves to inhabit.” We are able to understand one another and communicate with one another in the course of our actions. Insofar as we do this, we have to understand how the objects we are dealing with look from the perspective of others. When we do that we suppose a common space in which we are all located at different positions with regard to the object and calculate how the object must look to others by projection in that common space. So the supposition of the existence of an external world is a necessary condition of the possibility of mutual understanding and communication. (Even if there is no such world, we are necessarily compelled to suppose it and to act as if it existed.) This makes it very likely that God would have in fact created such a world — rather than create an illusion that we really are incapable of escaping. Kant’s ill-informed understanding of Berkeley Kant: Berkeley’s claim that matter is impossible rests on appeal to the paradoxical consequences of the infinite divisibility of space. (In fact, it rests on no such claim. The appeal to infinite divisibility is Kant’s own [Leibnizian] argument for denying that things in themselves exist in space.) Kant’s “Refutation of Idealism” (another “transcendental argument”) “I am conscious of my own existence as determined in time. All determination of time presupposes something permanent in perception. This permanent cannot, however, be something in me, since it is only through this permanent that my existence in time can itself be determined. Thus perception of this permanent is possible only through a thing outside me …” “… space alone is permanent, while time, and therefore everything that is in inner sense, is in constant flux.” My experience of myself and my own internal states presupposes an experience of things in space. Because: I experience myself as “determined in time” (as having different experiences or ideas over time) But all determination of temporal relations presupposes reference to something permanent in perception. Because: To think that one idea follows another (as opposes to coexisting with it or preceding it) is to think that there is some enduring thing of which the one idea is a later state and the other an earlier state. This permanent thing could not be myself or my mind. Because: I have no experience of any such thing. All I find in myself by introspection is a collection of ideas occurring in constant flux. In fact, nothing that exists only in time is permanent; the only thing that is really permanent and enduring over all of time is space. Because: Space and all its parts are eternal and unaltering (one part of space does not move with respect to the others and none is ever annihilated or created). Each of the parts of time exists only for an instant. So what is only in time (except for space and what is spatial) is impermanent. Consequently, it is only through being considered to be states of something that is located or moving in space that what exists only in time can be considered to be successive rather than simultaneous, or successive in one order rather than the reverse order.