Problems of Bilgrami’s veroteleologism Federico Penelas – Universidad de Buenos Aires I will call “veroteleologism” to the thesis according to which truth should be considered as the final goal of inquiry. In what follows I will make some critical remarks to the defense of this idea, as it appears in several papers by Akeel Bilgrami1. Let’s consider first the following antiveroteleologism argument. AV1 Premise 1- If a goal is not recognizable when reached, the inquirer cannot have the intention of reaching it as a goal. Premise 2- In the context of inquiry, we are able to recognize when we reach justification of a belief, but not when that belief is truth. Conclusion 1- Truth is not a goal of inquiry; only justification can play that role. Bilgrami considers this a valid argument, but he objects the second premise. Bilgrami’s point is that, from a pragmatist philosophical frame, epistemology should take the first person’s perspective, and in doing it, it should be noticed that truth is both the norm and the goal of inquiry. Bilgrami does nothing more but draw this conclusion from Peirce’s model of belief-doubt. From this perspective it is assumed to be a group of beliefs which constitutes our world-view and which we use as a standard in the determination of the truth value of the rest of our beliefs. Beliefs constituting such a group don’t need justification, for they are believed without any doubt whatsoever. Thus, the idea of providing justification to beliefs about which we don’t have the slightest doubt and which constitute our world-view lacks sense from the epistemological point of view. The idea of justification starts working, then, just when our world-view is shaken and it must therefore be changed. Thus, for Bilgrami, truth applies to doubt free beliefs, whereas justification applies to hypotheses, which enter the game in the process of change of our system of doubt-free beliefs. This being so, the goal of inquiry is not justification but truth, for what the inquirer wants to know is which one of those beliefs about which he is in doubt can be added to his world-view, i.e. which one is true. This is how the second premise of AV1 is objected, by pointing out that in the context of inquiry (from the only relevant perspective, that is, that of the first person’s), we are indeed able to recognize which of our beliefs are true, since these are the ones that constitute our world-view, and the ones that don’t need to be justified since we don’t doubt them at all. Here Bilgrami refers to Wittgenstein’s “hinge propositions”, and here I myself would like to refer to the Spanish philosopher Ortega y Gasset, who back in 1934 distinguished beliefs from ideas in an Cfr. “Realism and Relativism”, “Pursuit an Analogy”, “Is Truth a Goal of Inquiry?: Rorty and Davidson on Truth” 1 analogous way to Bilgrami’s distinction between beliefs and hypotheses 2. “We have ideas, but we are in beliefs”, was Ortega’s slogan. Let’s pay attention, however, to this new formulation of the former argument, which displays certain reasons that can be put forward in favor of the thesis of truth’s non recognizability. AV2 Premise A- A non-recognizable goal –that is, a goal that can’t be recognizable when reached- can’t be thought of as a goal. Premise B- If all of our beliefs can be revised, then we will never know when a belief is true. Premise C- All of our beliefs are revisable. Conclusion- Truth is not a goal of inquiry. Bilgrami’s reaction to this argument is that of accepting its validity and taking premises A and C as true, while rejecting premise B. Such a rejection, as Bilgrami concedes, is the most difficult point in his standpoint. The difficulty rests in the fact that the acceptance of premise C along with his thesis on doubt-free beliefs as true can compromise him with a relativism that he is not disposed to accept. Certainly, pointing out that a belief constituting our world-view is true but revisable presupposes that, when giving it up and taking its negation as non doubtable, we should say that both p and not-p are true regarding the different perspectives outlined before and after the revision; this leads us to assume a direct commitment to a notion of truth relative to belief systems. Note here that such relativism allows us to reject premise B and thus disqualify the entire argument. For this reason Bilgrami is obliged to do two things when confronting the argument: the first one is proving us that his thesis on truth along with premise C won’t lead to relativism; the second one is to outline an alternative way of objecting premise B. I want to stress that these are two different tasks. My impression is that Bilgrami, in taking care of the firs one, thinks to be taking care of the second one as well. If this is so, I think he owes us an argument of why resolving one of these problems implies resolving the other one too. The debt is high, for the rejection of relativism implies loosing a way to attack premise B. On the other hand, were my impression mistaken, then Bilgrami should face up the second task by showing how truth is recognizable, even knowing that, given a certain belief, one doesn’t know for certain that it will never be abandoned (what else does it mean that every belief is revisable but this?), and that indoubtability is the trademark of the truth of beliefs. Let’s see the way in which Bilgrami undertakes the first task, this is, how he argues in favor of the idea that his pragmatism doesn’t imply relativism. Bilgrami points out that “what has to be shown to stave off relativism, is that in those cases when two inquirers contradict one another on some matter (or when a verdict at a later inquiry-stage contradicts the verdict of an earlier inquirystage), it is every bit as bad and intolerable as when the same inquirer contradicts himself at a one and the same stage of his inquiry. Every bit as bad, in the sense that in those cases too we want to 2 See “Ideas y creencias”, in J. Ortega y Gasset, Ideas y creencias, Madrid, Espasa Calpe, 1940, pp. 17-61. say that only one of the contradictory beliefs is true”3. A way of sustaining this last idea is by abandoning bilgramian pragmatism (columbian pragmatism according to Bilgrami), which doesn’t segregate epistemologically belief from truth. Such an abandonment allows completing the game by pointing out that one of the two beliefs is the true one, even when the inquirer doesn’t know which one it is. Now, according to Bilgrami, a pragmatist doesn’t contradict himself if he notes that “it is intolerable that the same inquirer at the same stage of inquiry contradicts himself”. The problem would lay in the possible insistence in that the case of the inquirer which contradicts himself in the same stage of inquiry (let’s call this case I) is not identical to that of two inquirers with contradictory beliefs, or to that of one inquirer with contradictory beliefs in different stages of his inquiry (let’s call these other situations case II). This denial of identification would leave our pragmatist just with a relativistic way of accounting for the cases of divergence among inquirers (or different stages of inquiry): to point out that there is no real contradiction among them at the end, for the truth of each of the beliefs is relative to the different backgrounds or doctrines. Thus, for Bilgrami, the entire weigh of his argument lays in the possibility of identifying case I and case II. For Bilgrami, the identification of case I and case II is exactly the point of Davidson’s argument against the third dogma of empirism. This is how it is possible to distinguish pragmatism from relativism. In his words: “when it is reported that two inquirers or two inquirer-stages confidently judge respectively that p and not-p, relative to their doctrines or background sets of beliefs, there is no scope to make this harmless report slide into the quite different and relativistic point that the truth of p and not-p is relative to their respective doctrines or background sets of beliefs. Such a slide is blocked, despite the fact that the pragmatist denies the segregation of confident judgment from truth, because the pragmatist has now (by Davidson's argument) been given the resources to say that only one of these two contradictory beliefs of the two inquirers or inquirer-stages is right, just as much as he has the resources to say it of two contradictory beliefs of one inquirer at a single stage of inquiry” 4. In order to face this rejoinder from Bilgrami I want to address to the following perplexity. Giving the way in which he formulates his point, case I and case II should be characterized in terms of beliefs, not in terms of hypotheses, for only of the first we can predicate truth in an indubitable way. Now, what does it mean, from Bilgrami’s standpoint, that an inquirer maintains, at the same time, contradictory beliefs? Note that the situation should be such that wouldn’t involve doubts for the inquirer, that is, none of these beliefs should become a hypothesis tested against the rest of the beliefs sustained by the inquirer. In cannot either be claimed that one of the two beliefs (or both) is (are) sustained unconsciously, for then the entire bilgramian characterization of beliefs as indubitable objects of knowledge seems to become banal (or, more charitably, it may end closer to the wittgensteinian non-cognitivism of the “hinge propositions”). In order to the argument to work in 3 4 “Realism and Relativism” Ibid. terms of Bilgrami, this situation must be possible in stronger terms than those of the mere logical possibility. But if, following Peirce, beliefs are guides to action, and according to Bilgrami, they are those items of our cognitive system about which we do not doubt and that serve as standards in the assessment of hypotheses, is it possible, epistemically or practically, an inquirer believing both p and not-p? Isn’t this actually the situation that motorizes the justificatory process, with opposing hypotheses in play? Let’s present a last argument, a more rortian one I think, against the idea that truth is not a goal of inquiry. The argument runs as follows. AV3 Premise 1- If something doesn’t make difference in practice, then it should not make difference in philosophy. Premise 2- The practice of pursuing the truth consists in the elimination of doubt. Premise 2- The justificatory practice consists in remove the challenges placed against my belief. Premise 3- The removal of challenges eliminates doubt. Premise 4- Free of doubt beliefs are true. Conclusion1- In the context of investigation, the practice of pursuing truth doesn’t differ from the practice of pursuing justification. Conclusion 2- There is no philosophical difference between truth and justification. Conclusion 3- Truth as a goal of inquiry is, in the best case, just a rhetoric device for alluding to the idea that inquiry has justification as a goal. I think that when facing this argument, Bilgrami should have to accept all the premises, but he should also denounce a non-sequitur. Now, I don’t find in Bilgrami’s papers any way to state this report. The only way of doing this would be by protesting against the non inclusion in the argument of a premise preventing the drawing of the difference: the premise that would claim that, besides the practice of justification, there is another practice (it is important that it should be something that the person does and not something he suffers) by which an inquirer can dispel his doubts. I haven’t found in Bilgrami’s papers any explicit signal of an epistemic non justificatory practice whatsoever. It seems difficult in its turn that Bilgrami’s approach would contain implicitly the idea of such a practice. For, once one has justified his hypothesis, is there anything else that the inquirer should do in order to believe it? It should be something that the individual does to beliefs, and not merely to hypotheses. Here, Ortega seems more enlightened than Bilgrami when he tells us that “with beliefs we don’t do strictly anything” 5. As a final remark, I want to point out that an anti-veroteleologist pragmatist as Rorty (and more explicitly, as Brandom) also assumes that inquiry happens within a frame of beliefs that are not doubted. And, by virtue of the laudatory use of truth, he wouldn’t have any problem whatsoever 5 J. Ortega y Gasset, “Ideas y creencias”, p. 19. in saying that we take them as true, because, along with Michael Williams or Brandom, he considers these beliefs as justified by default, justified in practice, and the trademark of such tacit justification shows itself in the unchallenged global consensus that they bear. Thus, so far, the difference to Bilgrami wound’t has to be more than terminological. But apparently Bilgrami wants to say more, he wants to say that truth is the goal of inquiry. Now, in his approach, if truth is identified with the unquestioned, then the goal of inquiry is not truth but agreement. This is the possible goal, undoubtabitity being just a by-product of the absence of challenge by our epistemic peers. Bilgrami is right in noting that the cautionary use of truth doesn’t have perlocutionary consequences for the inquirer. For the warning that any of the beliefs that we take as true can be false instead is a general remark incapable of defying our conception of the world (this is actually Peirce’s critique to Descartes´ model of doubt-belief). But what does indeed raise doubts is the presence of disagreement with our peers. It is curious that Bilgrami disdains the epistemological import of audiences to which the inquirer addresses. It seems enough for him to admit that, insofar it is the precautory use of truth what supports premise 2 of AV1, and such a use doesn’t have any practical consequence, then premise 2 can be given up from a strictly pragmatist point of view. But an antiveroteleologist as Rorty does not stand on the cautionary use in order to finishing his point on truth not being the goal of inquiry. If the goal of inquiry is, for Peirce and according to Bilgrami, the dissolving of the doubt, it is not reached until we stop being challenged by our peers. Once we have reached consensus, and as a consequence we have added new beliefs to our world-view, we have then new candidates to praise with the truth predicate. But, would it be possible to dispel our doubts and take a belief as true even when our community disagrees with us regarding it, being that this disagreement does not make appeal to the cautionary use of truth but to details relevant to the context of acceptance of the belief? I don’t understand how this possibility could be defended and maintained within pragmatism. This contributes to maintain Rorty’s idea that it is justification, construed as an inter-subjective enterprise through which we reach the relevant consensus that eases our doubts, the goal of which we can make sense of in characterizing the practice of inquiry. The idea of truth as a goal of inquiry, idea that supports the veroteleologist conception, continues without making any difference whatsoever in practice, even when adopting the first person perspective so dear to Bilgrami.