Title A critique on T t he Policy Statement of the American Academy

advertisement
1
Title
2
The Policy Statement of the American Academy of Pediatrics – Children as
3
Hematopoietic Stem Cell Donors – a proposal of amendments for better
4
protection of minors
5
6
Authors’ names
7
CHAN Tak Kwong
8
Assistant Professor, Anatomy, University of Hong Kong
9
Email: theo@hku.hk; Tel: 852-93863620; Fax: 852-28199205
10
Postal Address: L1-59, Laboratory Block, 21 Sassoon Road, Hong Kong
11
12
TIPOE George Lim
13
Associate Professor, Department of Anatomy, University of Hong Kong,
14
Hong Kong
15
Postal Address: L1-59, Laboratory Block, 21 Sassoon Road, Hong Kong
16
17
Correspondence to CHAN TK at theo@hku.hk
18
19
Word count: 2085
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
Keywords: policy, haematopoietic stem cell transplant, ethical concerns, donor
siblings
1
1
2
3
Abstract:
4
With a view to addressing the moral concerns about the use of donor siblings, the
5
Policy Statement of the American Academy of Pediatrics - Children as Hematopoietic
6
Stem Cell Donors (the Policy) has laid out the criteria upon which tissue harvest from
7
a minor would be permissible.
Background
8
9
Discussion
10
Although tissue harvest serves the best interests of recipient siblings, parents are also
11
obliged to act in the best interests of the donor sibling. Tissue harvest should proceed
12
if and only if it serves the best interests of both the donor and recipient. Parents
13
should be forbidden, and they are by law, to consent to tissue harvest unless there are
14
substantial benefits for an incompetent minor that can outweigh the potential harm.
15
There is no basis to subject a minor to the medical risks of tissue harvest if the
16
recipient sibling can wait without significant risks of complications until the donor
17
becomes Gillick competent. We also argue that the Policy fails to take into account
18
recent advances in haematopoietic transplantation from haploidentical donors or
19
related tissue-matched donors. As a proper ethical evaluation should have regard to
20
the availability of different types of suitable donors, fulfilling the criteria specified in
21
the Policy alone is not sufficient to justify tissue harvest from a donor sibling.
22
23
Summary
24
Unless a recipient sibling will suffer from serious complications or die without the
25
transplantation and no other medically equivalent donors are available, there is no
26
moral or legal basis to violate the donor sibling’s right to bodily integrity.
2
1
Accordingly, we propose that the Policy should be revised in order to fully address
2
our moral concerns in relation to tissue harvest from donor siblings.
3
4
BACKGROUND
5
6
In conjunction with preimplantation genetic diagnosis (PGD), assisted reproduction
7
can be used to avoid inheritable diseases. After successful in-vitro fertilization, PGD
8
can identify whether any of the embryos is affected by a genetic condition. Parents
9
now can even request selection of embryos on the basis of tissue type in order to
10
create a child to cure an existing sick child. In response to the moral concerns about
11
the use of paediatric haematopoietic cell donor siblings (donor siblings), the Policy
12
Statement of the American Academy of Pediatrics – Children as Hematopoietic Stem
13
Cell Donors (the Policy) suggests that tissue harvest should only proceed upon
14
satisfaction of all the following five criteria:
15
16
‘(1) there is no medically equivalent histo-compatible adult relative who is willing
17
and able to donate;
18
(2) there is a strong personal and emotionally positive relationship between the donor
19
and recipient;
20
(3) there is some likelihood that the recipient will benefit from the transplantation;
21
(4) the clinical, emotional, and psychosocial risks to the donor are minimized and are
22
reasonable in relation to the benefits expected to accrue to the donor and to the
23
recipient; and
24
(5) parental permission and, where appropriate, child assent have been obtained.’1
3
1
Except that the fourth criterion requires the physician to minimise the risks of medical
2
procedures by, e.g. avoiding central venous catheter insertion and reducing
3
psychological risk by proper communication skills and the fifth requires that child
4
assent should be obtained where appropriate, the remaining criteria seem to merely
5
state the facts common to most cases of tissue harvest rather than regulating the
6
process. We contend that the Policy fails to sufficiently protect the interests of donor
7
siblings without addressing the availability of other types of donors and the type of
8
disease.
9
10
DISCUSSION
11
The legal and ethical principles
12
One would not dispute that tissue harvest serves the best interests of recipient siblings.
13
As one’s liberty cannot be allowed to such an extent that another person suffers
14
harm,2 a donor sibling does not have an obligation to save the life of the recipient
15
sibling given the medical risks of transplantation. A Gillick competent donor should
16
be free to make an informed decision of whether to save the life of a recipient
17
sibling.3 In case the donor sibling is an incompetent minor, a parent must proceed to
18
assess the best interests of the donor. The assessment of best interests is a balance of
19
the benefits and risks of transplantation for the donor. The procedures need not be risk
20
free but parents should only consent to tissue harvest if the possible benefits for the
21
donor outweigh the potential harm. Although parents have the rights to make
22
decisions for incompetent minors, the Children Act 1989 in the United Kingdom
23
empowers the court to intervene if parents fail to act in the best interests of both
24
children.4, 5 In Birmingham City Council v H (a minor), Balcombe LJ said the
25
question of welfare of both children should be approached ‘without giving one
4
1
priority over the other.’6 Although the parents’ wishes should command very great
2
respect, the court is to exercise an independent and objective judgment.7 The ethical
3
principles of beneficence and non-maleficence also demand that parents should
4
consent to tissue harvest only if it serves the best interests of both the donor and
5
recipient.
6
7
8
The best interests of donor siblings
Well-documented risks
9
The most ethically sound basis to oppose tissue harvest is that it imposes risks of
10
bodily injuries associated with the medical procedures of tissue harvest. The risks
11
depend on the source of cells namely bone marrow, peripheral blood and umbilical
12
cord blood, each with their own benefits and risks. It is known that harvest by
13
umbilical cord blood carries no medical risks except in case of modified delivery.
14
Therefore my analysis below focuses on bone marrow and peripheral blood
15
transplantation only. Minor complications like pain at collection sites, fatigue and
16
pain may occur in a small proportion of donors (6%-20%). Major and life-threatening
17
complications following marrow donation like anesthesia-related events, injuries to
18
bones, sacroiliac joint and sciatic nerve were estimated to occur in 0.1%-0.3% of
19
cases.8 Major risks of peripheral blood transplantation are mainly associated with
20
sedation, general anaesthesia and central venous catheter insertion, estimated to be
21
about 1.1% of cases.9 In light of one’s inviolable right to bodily integrity, minors
22
should not be exposed to the medical risks unless there are well-established benefits
23
of a significant magnitude that they can accrue from tissue harvest.
24
Potential benefits
5
1
The possible benefits for donor siblings are merely psychosocial. In an American case
2
Curran v. Bosze, Calvo J said that ‘the psychological benefit is grounded firmly in the
3
fact that the donor and the recipient are known to each other in a family. There may be
4
a psychological benefit to the child from donating bone marrow to a sibling.’10 We
5
consider that tissue harvest can have short-term and long-term psychosocial effects
6
for donor siblings. When presented with the idea of donation, younger donors were
7
found to focus more on the immediate pain and the frightening experience of the
8
procedure,12 whereas older children might feel pressure from family members or
9
medical staff to become a donor.11 MacLeod and others found that about a third of the
10
siblings donors thought that doctors and family members limited their opportunity to
11
say no, making them perceive they had a ‘forced no choice’.12 And donor siblings
12
reported higher levels of anxiety and lower self-esteem than non-donor siblings,13
13
which may be attributed to the lack of choice in the decision to donate. It follows that
14
a donor sibling is more likely to have short-term psychosocial burdens rather than
15
benefits.
16
17
Long term positive effects for the donor siblings include greater sensitivity to the
18
needs of others14, enhanced self-sufficiency and independence15, increased family
19
closeness16, and most important of all, the possible companion of a healthy recipient
20
sibling. On the other hand, negative emotions were reported when their recipient
21
siblings developed long-lasting complications from the procedure. Furthermore,
22
anger, guilt, and blame were common amongst donor siblings with unsuccessful
23
transplant.12 While the Policy cited the findings of three studies that all donor siblings
24
agreed that the psychosocial benefits and harm of serving as a donor outweighed the
25
physical harms, Macleod,Wieners and others found that only 66.6% and 67% of
6
1
donor siblings reported a predominantly positive psychosocial experience.12, 17
2
Importantly, all reporting predominantly positive psychosocial experience had
3
successful transplant and only donors with unsuccessful transplant reported a
4
predominantly negative experience in Macleod’s study.12 As the psychosocial
5
experience is highly associated with the outcome for the recipient, we contend that the
6
long-term benefits for donor siblings mainly derive from the survival of the recipient
7
sibling rather than from process of tissue harvest per se.
8
9
Balance of benefits and risks
10
Whereas the advantages of tissue harvest for donor siblings are long-term and merely
11
psychosocial, the other side of balance sheet consists of short-term psychological
12
burden and life-threatening physical harm. One should bear in mind that the notion of
13
benefits and risks are both relative concepts. To consider the potential gains or losses
14
for donor siblings, we ought to consider what would likely happen to the donors and
15
recipients without tissue harvest. It cannot be said that tissue harvest can offer any
16
significant long-term benefits for the donor sibling if other available source of
17
transplant can offer a similar chance of success or if the sick sibling can survive
18
without serious complications even without transplantation. Those who do not agree
19
may argue that a donor sibling may in the future relish and take pride in being a donor
20
and therefore still want to donate even if other donors are available. Parents may
21
legitimately consider this factor when making decisions for incompetent minors. But
22
the remoteness of this benefit should take its edge off from the evaluation. The sense
23
of pride may not materialize if the grown-up donor sibling does not accept the filial or
24
social responsibility to save the recipient sibling, is disinterested in altruistic donation,
25
or does not relish in living in the shadows of the recipient sibling. In any event, it is
7
1
only for a competent individual to decide whether they want to take the risks in
2
exchange for just the goodwill and the pride of being ‘a donor and a saviour’. For
3
minors, we hold that the benefits of this alone are too remote and small in magnitude
4
to justify the medical risks of life-threatening bodily intrusion. In short, the only
5
circumstance where tissue harvest would serve the best interests of a minor donor is
6
that without the proposed transplantation taking place, the sick sibling will more
7
likely suffer serious complications or die.
8
9
Availability of other donors
10
In light of foregoing discussion, to determine whether tissue harvest is in a donor
11
sibling’s best interests, one should assess first whether the recipient sibling would
12
likely die or suffer from serious complications without a transplantation. If the answer
13
is affirmative, then one should see if donation from any mentally competent donors
14
can offer a similar chance of successful transplantation.
15
16
In the past, tissue-matched related donors were considered to be the best sources of
17
donation. But now, many drawbacks of unrelated or haplo-identical transplants such
18
as graft failure and significant graft-versus-host diseases have been overcome due to
19
the development of new extensive T-cell depletion techniques with mega dose stem
20
cell administration over the last two decades. New approaches such as alloreactive T
21
cell depletion and post-transplant cell therapy have also improved immune
22
reconstitution in tissue-matched unrelated or haplo-identical transplants. Using haplo-
23
identical donors are now considered to be equally safe and effective transplant
24
strategies as tissue-matched donors for advanced leukemia.18 Leung and others
25
showed that the five year survival rates of recipient siblings with high risk leukemia
8
1
are promising regardless of donor types (68% for donor siblings, 74% for unrelated
2
donors and 77% for haplo-identical donors), and that the risks of death from graft-
3
versus-host diseases at five years is not significantly associated with the types of
4
donors (6.6% for donor siblings, 7.0% for unrelated donors, and 3.4% for haplo-
5
identical donors).19 Therefore, a search for competent family members, local and even
6
international bone marrow donor registry should be undertaken before parents are
7
permitted to consent to tissue harvest from donor siblings for recipients suffering
8
from advanced lymphoma or leukemia. For other diseases, Sodani and others reported
9
that haplo-identical transplant in thalassemia has 93% chance of survival and only 7%
10
mortality using new conditioning regimen.20 Bolaños-Meade and others showed that
11
the use of haplo-identical transplant for patients with sickle cell disease is highly
12
effective and safe despite the fact that graft failure still remains an obstacle.21
13
14
Proposed amendments of the Policy
15
It is already well established that the use of haplo-identical transplant is equally safe
16
and effective for advanced lymphoma or leukemia, whereas studies are still underway
17
to evaluate the results with non-malignant diseases like aplastic anemia, lupus and
18
sickle cell diseases. The above literature search by no means suggests that haplo-
19
identical transplant can replace tissue-matched transplant but, given the success of
20
new regimens of transplantation, doctors should look beyond the availability of
21
tissue-matched related donors for certain types of diseases. Parents and doctors should
22
make sure, if the medical conditions of the sick sibling permit a search, that no other
23
sources of equally or similarly effective transplant are available before subjecting a
24
minor to the physical risks and short-term psychological harm of tissue harvest.
25
9
1
In the circumstances, I propose that the following should replace the original first and
2
third criteria in the Policy:
3
4
1. If the medical conditions of the recipient permit a search, there is no medically
5
equivalent haplo-identical/histo-compatible adult who is willing and able to
6
donate;
7
8
9
3. The recipient sibling will likely suffer from serious complications or die
without transplantation before the donor sibling becomes Gillick competent,
10
11
CONCLUSIONS
12
The parental choice to harvest tissues from donor siblings reflects the immense
13
‘emotive desire to do something to help the recipient sibling’.22 However, donor
14
siblings may not necessarily reap any benefits in light of the risks of serious injuries
15
arising from bone marrow or peripheral blood transplantation. Fulfilling the criteria
16
specified in the Policy of the Academy alone is not sufficient to justify tissue harvest
17
from minors. Unless a recipient sibling will likely suffer from serious complications
18
or die without the transplantation and no tissue-matched unrelated donors or related
19
haploidentical donors are available, there is no moral or legal basis to violate the
20
donor sibling’s right to bodily integrity. In short, the Policy should be revised to fully
21
address our moral concerns in relation to tissue harvest from minor donor siblings.
22
23
24
Competing interests
10
1
The authors declare that they have no competing interests.
2
Author’s Contributions
3
Corresponding and first author Chan TK is the main researcher, writer and editor
4
responsible for the legal research and ethical analysis.
5
6
The co-author Tipoe GL, was responsible for identifying ethical issues, overseeing the
7
research and giving expert input into the ethical analysis and review. Both authors
8
read and approved the final manuscript.
9
10
Authors’ Information
11
CHAN TK, MBChB, MRCS, LLM(Medical Law and Ethics)
12
Assistant Professor
13
Anatomy
14
University of Hong Kong
15
L1-59 Laboratory Block, Faculty of Medicine Building, 21 Sassoon Road, Hong
16
Kong
17
18
19
TIPOE GL, MD, PhD
20
Asscoiate Professor
21
Anatomy
22
University of Hong Kong
23
24
1/F Laboratory Block, Faculty of Medicine Building, 21 Sassoon Road, Hong Kong
25
26
Acknowledgements
27
We would like to thank the reviewers Dr Wendy Rogers, Dr Joerg Halter, Dr Elaine
28
Morgan and Dr Heidi Mertes for their invaluable comment in revision of the
29
manuscript.
11
1
2
Funding
3
Funding not required
4
5
Ethical Approval
6
Ethical approval not required.
7
8
References
9
. American Academy of Pediatrics: Policy Statement—Children as Hematopoietic
10
Stem Cell Donors. Pediatrics 2010, 125:392-404.
11
2. Mill JS: On Liberty. Penguin Edition: 1974.
12
13
3. Gillick v West Norfolk and Wisbech Area Health Authority [1985] 3 All ER AC
14
112.
15
16
4. Section 1, Children Act 1989
17
[http://www.legislation.gov.uk/ukpga/1989/41/section/1]
18
19
5. Re C & F (Children) 2003 EWHC 1376 (Fam).
20
21
6. Birmingham City Council v H (a minor) [1993] 1 FLR 883.
22
23
7. Re Z (a minor) (freedom of publication) [1995] 4 All ER 961 at 986, [1997] Fam 1
24
at 32.
12
1
2
8. Bojanić I, Cepulić BG, Mazić S: Collection of hematopoietic progenitor cells
3
from healthy donors. Acta Med Croatica 2009, 63(3):237-44.
4
5
9. Pulsipher MA, Levine JE, Hayashi RJ, Chan KW, Anderson P, Duerst R, Osunkwo
6
I, Fisher V, Horn B, Grupp SA: Safety and efficacy of allogeneic PBSC collection
7
in normal pediatric donors: the pediatric blood and marrow transplant
8
consortium experience (PBMTC) 1996 –2003. Bone Marrow Transplant 2005,
9
35(4):361–367.
10
11
10. Curran v. Bosze (1990) 566 N.E. 2d 1319
12
13
11. Wass H: Helping children cope with death. In Papadatou D, Papadatou C:
14
Children and Death. New York: Hemisphere;1991:11-32.
15
16
12. MacLeod KD, Whitsett S, Mash EJ, Pelletier W: Pediatric Sibling Donors of
17
Successful and Unsuccessful Hematopoietic Stem Cell Transplants (HSCT): A
18
Qualitative Study of Their Psychosocial Experience. J Pediatr Psychol 2003,
19
28(4):223-230.
20
21
13. Packman WL, Crittenden MR, Schaeffer E, Bongar B, Fischer JB, Cowan MJ:
22
Psychosocial consequences of bone marrow transplantation in donor and
23
nondonor siblings. Journal of Developmental & Behavioral Pediatrics 1997, 18:244-
24
253.
25
13
1
14. Heffernan S, Zanelli A: Behavior changes exhibited by siblings of pediatric
2
oncology patients: A comparison between maternal and sibling descriptions.
3
Journal of Pediatric Oncology Nursing 1997, 14:3–14.
4
5
15. Barbarin OA, Sargent JR, Sahler OJ, Carpenter PJ, Copeland DR, Dolgin MJ:
6
Sibling Adaptation to Childhood Cancer Collaborative Study: Parental views of
7
pre- and post diagnosis adjustment of siblings of children with cancer. Journal of
8
Psychosocial Oncology 1995, 13:1–20.
9
16. Chesler MA, Allswede J, Barbarin OO: Voices from the margin of the family:
10
Siblings of Children with Cancer. Journal of Psychosocial Oncology 1991, 9:19–
11
42.
12
17. Wiener LS, Steffen-Smith E, Battles HB, Wayne A, Love CP, Fry T: Sibling
13
stem cell donor experiences at a single institution. Psychooncology 2008,
14
17(3):304-7.
15
16
18. Tischer J, Stemmler HJ, Engel N, Hubmann M, Fritsch S, Prevalsek D, Schulz C,
17
Zoellner AK, Bücklein V, Hill W, Ledderose G, Hausmann A: Feasibility of
18
clofarabine cytoreduction followed by haploidentical hematopoietic stem cell
19
transplantation in patients with relapsed or refractory advanced acute leukemia.
20
Ann Hematol 2013, doi 10.1007/s00277-013-1862-6.
21
22
19. Leung W, Campana D, Yang J, Pei D, Coustan-Smith E, Gan K, Rubnitz JE,
23
Sandlund JT, Ribeiro RC, Srinivasan A, Hartford C, Triplett BM, Dallas M, Pillai A,
24
Handgretinger R, Laver JH, Pui CH: High success rate of hematopoietic cell
14
1
transplantation regardless of donor source in children with very high-risk
2
leukemia. Blood 2011, 118(2):223–230.
3
4
20. Sodani P, Isgro A, Gaziev J, Paciaroni K, Marziali M, Simone MD, Roveda A, De
5
Angelis G, Gallucci C, Torelli F, Isacchi G, Zinno F, Landi F, Adorno G, Lanti A,
6
Testi M, Andreani M, Lucarelli G: T cell-depleted HLA-haploidentical stem cell
7
transplantation in thalassemia young patients. Paediat Rep 2011, 3(s2):e13.
8
9
21. Bolaños-Meade J, Fuchs EJ, Luznik L, Lanzkron SM, Gamper CJ, Jones RJ,
10
Brodsky RA: HLA-haploidentical bone marrow transplantation with post-
11
transplant cyclophosphamide expands the donor pool for patients with sickle cell
12
disease. Blood 2012 Sep 6 doi:10.1182/blood-2012-07-438408.
13
14
22. Lyons B: The good that is interred in their bones: are there property rights in
15
the child? Medical Law Review 2011, 19(3):372–400.
15
Download