The 4th International Seville Conference on Future-Oriented Technology Analysis (FTA): 12 & 13 May 2011 FTA and Grand Societal Challenges: Shaping and Driving Structural and Systemic Transformations THE EPISTEMOLOGY OF TECHNOLOGICAL FORESIGHT Authors: Dr. Sandra M. Dingli (Sandra.m.dingli@um.edu.mt) The Edward de Bono Institute, University of Malta, Malta http://www.um.edu.mt/create Keywords: Epistemology, knowledge, futures, foresight, theoretical underpinnings. A theoretical underpinning for what counts as valid knowledge in foresight and FTA is urgently required. A clear deliniation of the epistemology of foresight could provide the justification required for increased legitimacy to the knowledge claims made by practitioners with the consequence that ‘buy-in’ from experts, policy makers, funding agencies and stakeholders would posses increased conviction and augment integrity. A theoretical and interdisciplinary approach to exploring issues related to the epistemology of foresight is adopted. This is a relevant issue for foresight practice as the ‘scientific quality and validity of outcomes is still an issue’ (Theme 3, call for papers), in spite of the fact that the results of foresight practice often inform key policy decision making. The aim is to provide a ‘better understanding of ... epistemological positions that practitioners and theorists of FTA might adopt implicitly or explicitly’. Helmer and Rescher (1959) provided an interesting discussion on the possibility of knowledge and the inexact sciences in a paper entitled ‘On the Epistemology of Page 1 of 4 <Title>: the Inexact Sciences’. They had acknowledged that : While the value of scientific prediction for sound decision making is beyond question, it can hardly be claimed that the inexact sciences have the situation regarding the use of predictive expertise well in hand. Quite to the contrary, it is our strong feeling that significant improvements are possible in the predictive instruments available to the decision maker. These improvements are contingent on the development of methods for the more effective predictive use of expert judgment. (1959, p.41) One of the main considerations which Helmer and Rescher (1959) address is the use of ‘experts’, a concept which often plays a key role in foresight activities where ‘experts’ in particular areas are engaged to provide input and to assist with either scenario building or with creating visions. One example which Helmer and Rescher (1959) provide is the prediction of presidential elections, where statistical information may be attributed less relevance than a holistic insightful outlook, as they state that ‘For instance, in assessing the chances of a Republican presidential victory in 1960, a knowledge of the record of past election successes matters less than an insight into current trends and tendencies ...’ (1959: 38) Experts, for Helmer and Rescher, do not look into a crystal ball to create predictions. Rather, their role is as ‘predictors’. The role of experts is clearly spelt out as they ‘anticipate ... some of the major critical junctures (‘branch points’) on which the course of these developments will hinge, and ... make contingency predictions with regard to the alternatives associated with them.’ (1959: 412) Contingency is a key issue here. The type of imaginative ‘leap’ into the future which both foresight and innovation require involves risk taking and it is always considered to be a contingent prediction. No amount of assurance or evidence could possibly allow for certainty, since the future is always unknown and wild cards or unexpected events (such as a a financial crisis, political uprisings, terrorist attacks, tsunamis or earthquakes, which should be considered if and when relevant) may disrupt the best strategy design. Helmer and Rescher claim that ‘The use of experts for prediction does not constitute a line of demarcation Page 2 of 4 The Epistemology of Technological Foresight between the social and the physical sciences, but rather between the exact and the inexact sciences.’ (1959: 41) Experts have at their disposal: ‘a large store of (mostly inarticulated) background knowledge and a refined sensitivity to its relevance, through the intuitive application of which he is often able to produce trustworthy personal probabilities regarding hypotheses in his area of expertness.’ (1959: 38) How can the advice and predictions which experts provide be considered as objective data? According to the judgement which Helmer and Rescher provide, Our ‘data’ are supplemented by the expert's personal probability valuations and by his judgments of relevance (which, by the way, could be derived from suitable personal probability statements), and our ‘theory’ is supplemented by information regarding the performance of experts. In this manner the incorporation of expert judgment into the structure of our investigation is made subject to the same safeguards which are used to assure objectivity in other scientific investigations. The use of expertise is therefore no retreat from objectivity or reversion to a reliance on subjective taste. (1959: 43) According to Helmer and Rescher, there are various degrees of certainty where predictions by experts are concerned: In domains in which the flux of events is subject to gradual transitions and constant regularities (say, astronomy), a high degree of predictive expertise is possible. In those fields, however, in which the processes of transition admit of sharp jolts and discontinuities, which can in turn be the effects of so complex and intricate causal processes as to be ‘chance’ occurrences for all practical purposes, predictive expertise is inherently less feasible. (1959: 44) It is important to seriously explore a number of arguments, both for and against the possibility of legitimizing knowledge claims. Philosophical sources that argue against the legitimacy of epistemology provide a valuable input to this topic. Some questions which arise include: Is it possible to argue for an epistemology of foresight? Is it possible to provide epistemological justification for knowledge obtained from foresight? Page 3 of 4 <Title>: Does technological foresight give rise to knowledge? Does ‘learning’ constitute ‘knowledge’? Is truth merely indicative? Or could it be considered as ‘socially constructed’? Does this apply to all disciplines or only to disciplines which are ‘uncertain’ because of their future orientation? are numerous socially constructed concepts which we take as providing valid knowledge claims in many spheres of life. What are the implications which emerge for an epistemology of technological foresight, particularly where evaluation and dissemination issues are concerned? Reflection on epistemological aspects implies a metacognitive perspective which could inform and improve practice. This perspective gives rise to the view that knowledge claims which result from foresight practice possess elements of validity, in spite of the fact that they may also be viewed as ‘socially constructed’, yet there References Acceleration Watch (2006) DL 011110 Futurist (definition): Common Types of Futures Thinking http://www.accelerationwatch. com/futuristdef.html. Helmer, O. And Rescher, N. (1959) ‘On the Epistemology of the Inexact Sciences’, Management Science, Vol. 6, No. 1, October 1959, pp. 25-52. Rubel, R.C. (2006) ‘The Epistemology of War Gaming’, Naval War College Review, Spring 2006, Vol. 59, No. 2 pp.108-128. Page 4 of 4