Whitman College Tournament 2009 1 File Title Topic Overview ..................................................................................................................... 2 Research Guide ..................................................................................................................... 8 Definitions .......................................................................................................................... 11 Affirmative Case .................................................................................................................. 13 Affirmative Extensions......................................................................................................... 16 Factory Farming is Cruel ......................................................................................................................................16 Factory Farming is Inhumane ..............................................................................................................................17 Factory Farming is bad .........................................................................................................................................18 Animal Testing is Cruel ........................................................................................................................................19 Animal Testing does not help create cures..........................................................................................................20 The Fur Industry is Cruel ......................................................................................................................................21 Animals are Intelligent .........................................................................................................................................22 Animals Communicate .........................................................................................................................................23 Animal are feel pain .............................................................................................................................................23 Animals are Morally Relevant ..............................................................................................................................24 Animal Rights are important ................................................................................................................................25 Speciesism ...........................................................................................................................................................26 Animal Rights don’t cause bad consequences .....................................................................................................27 Humans need to treat animals well .....................................................................................................................28 Negative Case ...................................................................................................................... 29 Negative Extensions ............................................................................................................ 32 Animal Research is Justified.................................................................................................................................32 Animal Research is done humanely .....................................................................................................................34 Animal Agriculture/Hunting is Justified ...............................................................................................................35 Animals are Excluded from the Social Contract...................................................................................................36 Animals don’t have a claim to moral rights .........................................................................................................38 Animals are Amoral .............................................................................................................................................39 Animal Rights not justified ...................................................................................................................................40 Animals Lack Intelligence for Rights ....................................................................................................................41 Treating animals well does not mean they should have rights ...........................................................................42 Rejecting Animal Rights Does Not Endorse Cruelty .............................................................................................43 A2: Speciesism .....................................................................................................................................................44 A2: Speciesism continued ....................................................................................................................................45 Whitman College Tournament 2009 2 File Title Topic Overview RESOLVED: JUSTICE REQUIRES THE RECOGNITION OF ANIMAL RIGHTS. An Introduction to Animal Rights Although animals have recently risen to preeminence in ethical and moral philosophy, this is a fairly new development. For most of Western academic history, animals were generally considered on par with inanimate objects when they were considered at all. In the 1960’s, the growth of factory farming practices and increasingly publicized research on primate and other animals’ mental capacities sparked interest in the ethical dimension of human relationships with non-human animals. Peter Singer’s seminal work, Animal Liberation, and other scholarly pieces in the 1970’s led to a rapid growth in the field. During the same time period, the proliferation of animal rights and animal welfare organizations brought the issue to the forefront of popular consciousness and pressured Congress to pass a number of new animal welfare regulations and restrictions. Despite these developments, however, the moral status and treatment of animals by society remains more or less unchanged. From the time of the ancient Greeks to the enlightenment, few philosophers seriously considered animals in formulating ethical theories. Plato, Aristotle, and their peers devote little attention to animals except to draw distinctions between people and animals on the basis of intellect, language, and capacity for moral reasoning. With the spread of Christianity came the concept of human “dominion” over the natural world generally and animals in particular. This idea helped to reinforce notions of human superiority and justified the consumption of animals for food, clothing, etc…Early Christians like Augustine, however, did condemn unnecessary cruelty to animals on the basis that it contributed to cruelty towards human beings. During the Enlightenment, attitudes towards animals remained basically the same. Social contract theorist John Locke viewed animals as property akin to land or capital, as did his contemporaries. Descartes went further, famously describing animals as ‘automatons,’ machines capable of responding to stimuli but categorically distinct from human beings. This justified humans in treating animals in any way they chose, which was bad news for the animals. In addition to using animals as a source of labor, food, and clothing, scientists during the enlightenment and well into the 20 th century practiced vivisection, the performance of surgery on fully conscious living creatures, for purposes of surgical education and the study of anatomy. Animals finally caught a philosophical break during the 1800s when Jeremy Bentham and J.S. Mill founded the utilitarian school of thought. For utilitarians, it was difficult to find a reason to exclude animals from moral consideration because the avoidance of pain was the building block of the philosophy. Without sound evidence that, as Descartes had argued, animals didn’t feel pain, their exclusion was problematic. Bentham and Mill were thus among the first academics to call for better treatment of animals. The same time period also saw the establishment of the first animal welfare groups, institutions often associated with abolitionists. The ASPCA, among others, didn’t call for animal rights but did demand better living conditions and treatment for animals. These groups were sometimes highly influential and compelled many local and state governments to legislate the treatment of some higher mammals like horses. This period also saw the initial development of the concept of animal rights, although most thinkers of the time still opposed the concept. Public interest in animal rights subsided for the next several decades. By the post-World War II period, the condition of animal rights had actually deteriorated due to the widespread practice of factory farming the increasing use of animals as research subjects. In the 1960’s, a group of scholars at Oxford University known as the Oxford group began publishing material calling for the end of animal exploitation. Their work, coupled with the publication of Ruth Harrison’s Animal Machines, a biting critique of factory farming, helped to spark renewed interest in animal rights. A decade later, with Peter Singer’s work Animal Liberation, animal rights became a primary issue in ethics and moral philosophy. Singer’s book generated several waves of literature attacking his position (Fox, Cohen, etc…) and defending his position or adopting new justifications for animal rights (most notably Regan). Whitman College Tournament 2009 3 File Title This flurry of literature on the subject helped generate support for a number of new animal rights organizations, including People for the Ethical Treatment of Animals (PETA) and the Animal Liberation Front (ALF). Under pressure from these organizations, governments around the world began enacting new legislation aimed at protecting animals. However, the scope of these laws has generally been very narrow and riddled with exemptions for livestock animals and research animals. Animal rights groups have also attempted to secure animal liberation using the judicial system, but so far these efforts have proved unsuccessful. In 2008, an Australian court rejected the claim that a chimpanzee is a legal person, and similar lawsuits in the United States have also failed. Today, the animal rights movement is somewhat divided along philosophical lines. Academics like Tom Regan support animal rights on the basis of the inherent value of animals, and argue that the conception of “natural rights” should be extended to sentient creatures. Utilitarian thinkers like Singer reject the natural rights view and instead argue that animals should be granted equal consideration of interests. Both groups are distinct from animal welfare advocates, who do not believe animals have rights per se but do support stronger anti-cruelty laws, agricultural reforms, and greater regulation of animal testing. Many opponents of the animal rights movement, for example Michael Fox, fall in to this camp. Animal Rights and Social Contract Theory Social contract is a term describing a range of theories, which seek to justify and explain the existence of the state and systems of social order. Social contract theories arise from a “state of nature” or “original position” in which individuals live in the absence of any social order or state control. This is a purely hypothetical condition used to illustrate the disadvantages of the absence of any form of state. Without any sort of police force, rights are essentially non-existent and individuals are entirely without protection. There is not security, no protection of life, liberty or property, and life is, as Hobbes put it, “nasty, brutish, and short.” According to social contract theorists, individuals in the state of nature are compelled to join together and establish rules for living for their mutual benefit. Concepts of property rights, for example, require the cooperation of all members of a society; individuals must agree to sacrifice their freedom to, for example, farm on someone else’s land in exchange for the assurance that no one will farm on their own land. These agreed-upon rules or principles form the basis of the social contract. Social contract theory is a valuable source of arguments against animal rights because animals are almost certainly incapable of participating in the contract. First, we can be almost positive that no non-human animals have the intellectual capacity or communicative ability to understand and respect the rights of others. Conversations with dolphins about how they can’t eat this particular tuna because the fisherman has already caught it are unlikely to be fruitful. Second, even if animals did have sufficient intellectual capacity, their interests are often diametrically opposed in such a way as to make compromise impossible. Lions, for example, must hunt and kill zebras in order to survive. Zebras, on the other hand, must not be hunted and killed by lions if they are to survive. Among all rights, the right to life is probably the most fundamental because it is a prerequisite to all other rights. If lions and zebras both had an intrinsic right to life, there would be no mechanism for adjudicating their competitive claims. Humans can unite under a social contract with other humans because their survival needs do not typically directly conflict. The predator-prey relationships in the natural world preclude this luxury for animals. For this reason, social contract theorists like John Lock and John Rawls have either disregarded animals entirely in their theories or have identified animals as objects of human property. Animal Rights and Utilitarianism Many thinkers examine the question of animal rights through the lens of utilitarianism, an ethical system which determines the morality of an action by examining its consequences. In utilitarian ethics, the morally correct position is that which acheives the greatest good for the greatest number. Utilitarianism has been used to justify demands for animal rights and to deny the legitimacy of those demands. Peter Singer, a professor at Princeton University and a prominent utilitarian thinker, is one of the foremost animal rights thinkers. Singer argues that animals should be given ”equal consideration of interests” in any ethical calculus because they have the ability to suffer and feel pain. The “ability to suffer” standard is controversial because it requires that a human being unable to suffer due to impaired mental capacity, for Whitman College Tournament 2009 4 File Title example, is entitled to less consideration than a fully sentient animal. Singer justifies this Standard with an “argument from marginal cases.” He says that any other standard for determining who is or is not worthy of ethical consideration would have to leave out some humans and include some animals. If intelligence is the brightline, for example, mentally impaired people should count less than dolphins or chimpanzees. If morality is the brightline, we would have to exclude sociopaths from consideration. To Singer, the exclusion of animals from consideration is arbitrary and ”speciesist,” akin to sexism or racism. Importantly, equal consideration of interests isn´t the same as equal rights. Singer doesn´t think pigs should be allowed to vote, for example, but he does believe that humans should consider the effects their actions will have on pigs and other animals. This means that activities causing pain to animals like factory farming, medical research, etc…are ethically permissible only if the pain caused is outweighed by the positive benefits of the activity. Singer, and many other scholars, say this would only occur in very rare circumstances like medical research on a deadly disease. Eating an animal would only be justified to prevent starvation of another animal with a higher capacity to feel pain and pleasure. Utilitarianism can also be used to deny animal rights claims in two primary ways. The first is to argue that animals should not be given consideration under a utilitarian calculus. This requires drawing some distinction between humans and animals. To avoid the marginal case argument discussed above, philosophers have usually pointed to human potential. Even though severely retarded people aren´t intelligent, as human beings they have the potential to be, which distinguishes them from other animals. Second, some utilitarians argee that animal interests should be considered but deny that this would change anything about human behavior. Their argument is that even though factory farming is probably fairly unpleasant for livestock, livestock animals are not nearly as conscious of their plight as a human being would be. Cows don´t realize they are about to be slaughtered, and they don´t know what live is like outside a feed lot. Humans, on the other hand, are very aware of how much they like a juicy burger. These thinkers argue that activites that harm animals are nearly always justified by the positive results they produce in humans, because humans have a far greater capacity to feel pain and pleasure than do animals. If this argument is true, utilitarianism would justify continuing to treat animals as we do. Utilitarianism poses a number of significant problems as an ethical system, however. For one, it may be unimaginably hard to actually calculate the utility of a particular action. We don’t know enough about human psychology to accurately assess the impacts of certain actions, like whether spanking a child for wandering into the street is good or bad for the child in the long run. We know even less about animal psychology or physiology, which makes determining a moral course of action very difficult. Second, utilitarianism can be used to justify things which most people find morally repugnant. Some utilitarians defend infantacide in certain conditions in the beleif that it is better to kill a newborne child than to allow it to suffer in a miserable life. Ayn Rand famously argued that utilitarian ethics jusfified the enslavement of 49% of the population for the benefit of 51%. That said, utilitarianism has the advantage of being extremely intuitive in normal cases, and unlike many moral philosophies it does not rely on an abstract and often unprovable metaphysics. Rights-based Animal Liberation Rights-based philosophies offer a non-utilitarian defense of animal rights. Scholars like Tom Regan, agreeing with Singer about the need to respect sentient creatures but unwilling to endorse all-out utilitarianism, helped to pioneer this field. Academics endorsing a rights-based view of animal liberation contend that, like people, individual animals have inalienable rights. They justify this claim in several ways. First, some rights-based theorists have argued that animal rights must be respected due to animals’ cognitive capacity. They point out that many animals exhibit greater intelligence than many humans, and that the full extent of animal intelligence is not yet known by science. They also point to examples of animals exhibiting “human” characteristics like language, problem-solving, the use of tools, and the expression of emotions of reasons why the moral circle must be extended. These claims can be persuasive, but they tend to rely on empirical data which can be disproved by future investigation or reinterpretation of the existing evidence. Additionally, Whitman College Tournament 2009 5 File Title there is virtually no evidence to indicate that any species of animal as a whole is more intelligent than Homo sapiens. The second justification for a rights-based approach relies on the concept of “intrinsic value,” and is more appealing. Intrinsic value in this context is the idea that an animal has moral importance in and of itself, regardless of what characteristics it displays. Regan links the idea of intrinsic value to his invented term “subject-of-a-life,” an entity which is aware of itself and capable of acting autonomously. For Regan, any subject-of-a-life has rights which must be recognized and respected regardless of its intelligence, its moral capability, its means of communication, or any other factor. This justification is appealing because it avoids some of the moral hazards posed by utilitarianism—Regan’s theory would never justify animal testing, would never allow infanticide, etc…On the other hand, Regan’s theory may be a hard pill to swallow in some circumstances. He and his colleagues expressly identify medial research on animals even if the research would definitely save human lives. Singer’s utilitarianism might allow for testing in that circumstance. The Affirmative The first issue the affirmative debaters must consider is the scope of animal rights they are willing to defend. Narrow interpretations of the resolution could focus exclusively on higher primates like chimpanzees, gorillas and bonobos. Others could hone in on the cruelest practices of factory farming, like raising veal calves. Narrow cases have the advantage of solving many of the negative’s best arguments about animal rights harming human rights, but these advantages come at a cost. In any discussion of rights, it will be difficult to justify a narrow scope. If chimpanzees get rights, why don’t spider monkeys or dolphins or orcas? If veal is inhumane, why aren’t feed lots? Absent a coherent reason for the narrower scope, it can be difficult for the affirmative to win. Likewise, broader cases have the advantage of greater philosophical consistency, but are more likely to cause harm to humans. All in all, I recommend the big stick approach of a broader affirmative. The best affirmative strategies on this topic will need to accomplish three objectives: first, they should provide compelling evidence that animals have interests. Second, they must either prove the differences between humans and animals non-existent or morally irrelevant. Third, they should move to establish that recognition of animal rights would not cause substantial harm to human beings. The first objective, demonstrating that animals have interests, should not prove difficult. Interests, in the philosophical sense, are most easily defined as things that would be good the subject, or alternatively, the avoidance of things that would be bad for the subject. For example, we might say that a mouse has an interest in eating cheese and an interest in not having his back snapped in a trap. It’s vital that the affirmative win this point, because if animals cannot be shown to have interests there is no way to establish how humans should behave towards them. Fortunately, the task should be easy. Most authors, even many of those who oppose animal rights, acknowledge that animals do have interests. It seems difficult to deny that animals benefit from seeking out certain things and avoiding others. Objections tend to rest either on the old Cartesian argument that animals are automatons, outdated since cognitive science indicates otherwise, or by attempting to separate interests from “desires,” which can only be felt by humans. Both these arguments can be effectively pressed during cross examination with questions about why we can assume humans and only humans want things. If we can’t assume a dog scratching at the door wants to come inside, it’s difficult to justify assuming our neighbor wants to come inside when he knocks at the door. The second objective is more difficult. Virtually every author on the topic spends a substantial amount of ink either refuting the claim that humans possess morally relevant characteristics lacked by animals or supporting it. An increasing body of evidence suggests that higher animals like dolphins, primates, and whales are more intellectually and linguistically complex than we were previously aware. Many animals, including those mentioned above as well as elephants and parrots, have based “self-awareness” tests by recognizing their reflections in mirrors. Stories about dogs courageously rescuing toddlers from certain death abound in the news. However, there is not much of a case to support the argument that animals in general are anywhere near as sophisticated as human beings in terms of mental capacity, moral capacity, or any other characteristic considered important. Whitman College Tournament 2009 6 File Title Since the affirmative is unlikely to prove that animals and humans are literally equivalents, we’ll have to settle for neutralizing human-animal differences as irrelevant to the concerns of justice. Several authors, most notably Singer, make this precise argument. Singer’s call for “equal consideration of interests” explicitly acknowledges that humans and animals are different in a variety of important ways. However, he argues, they share a similarity of profound importance: they have the ability to suffer and feel pain. For Singer, this is the only rational cutoff point for moral standing because it is the only line we can draw that would include all humans in the moral equation. If intelligence were the rule, infants, senile people, and mentally retarded people would all fail to qualify for moral consideration along with animals. If a sense of morality was the cutoff point, sociopaths would be excluded. Drawing the line at the ability to feel pain avoids this problem—it includes all humans and all animals, at least all animals with a central nervous system. The third objective, proving that recognition of animal rights would not harm humans, is likely to prove the most difficult. It’s hard to imagine a world in which animal rights are fully recognized and human quality of life remains the same. At a minimum, we’d all have to give up leather jackets, medical testing on animals, and circuses. We’d probably have to call it quits on hamburgers, too. The key winning this point for the affirmative will be to show that any harm to humans would be easily outweighed by the massive benefit attained by animals. If animal interests count, too, then harm to humans could be small enough to be acceptable. Towards this end, I’ve included several cards indicating the high degree of pain caused by our current practices towards animals and evidence that animal testing and factory farming aren’t really necessary for humans. In addition to this type of mitigation, affirmatives could also take a hard line by arguing that even substantial loss of human life would be justified in order to recognize animal rights. Several authors, most notably Regan, state unequivocally that conducting tests on rats is wrong even if not conducting the tests causes humans to die. This approach has a lot of support in the literature, but may be difficult for some judges to swallow, so I recommend you combine mitigation with this hard line. I suspect that a lot of affirmative cases on this topic will spend a lot of time spelling out in gory detail the deplorable conditions of animals in research facilities, factory farms, and some zoos. While graphic descriptions may make useful rhetorical devices, they miss the point of this resolution. Whether or not animal rights should be recognized is not dependent on how we treat animals—it’s the other way around. Sound affirmatives will focus on establishing what rights are and why animals have them, rather than the other way around. The Negative The negative side of this topic has the advantage of the culturally engrained “common sense” of human superiority and the disadvantage of being accused of defending puppy torture. The best negative strategies will focus on winning three important arguments: first, that animals can’t be considered as moral agents and therefore do not have rights; second, that even if animals are moral agents, recognition of their rights would be completely untenable; and third, that refusing to recognize animal rights does not mean endorsing the mindless torture of animals (like puppies). The first argument, that animals aren’t moral agents, could be a one-shot kill for the negative. The affirmative pretty much has to win that animals are self-aware creatures which impose some sort of moral obligation on humans. Winning that claim necessary condition for establishing that animals have rights, but it isn’t sufficient. The negative’s best response arguments to this claim lie in social contract theory. Contract theorists from Locke to Rawls predicate the existence of rights on the contract—it’s because all people agree to live peacefully together in a society that we have an obligation to respect their rights and we theirs. Animals, however, lack the capacity to join in the social contract. They have no real sense of right and wrong, so we can’t expect them to respect our property rights, or even (in the case of tigers) our right to life. Moreover, animals have directly conflicting vital interests. Humans can get together and agree to respect rights because we don’t need to eat each other to survive. Lions and zebras don’t have that luxury. Nature makes it impossible for animals to participate in the social contract, so if the social contract is the basis of rights then animals must not have them. The second argument, that animals’ interests are secondary to human interests, takes a more moderate stance than the first. It focuses more on the practical problems presented by animal rights. Animals are an Whitman College Tournament 2009 7 File Title essential part of modern human societies. We use them as food, clothing, companions, security guards, and research guinea pigs (get it!?), all of which might be prohibited if animal rights were recognized. Furthermore, some societies like the Intuits in Alaska and some tribes in Africa are completely dependent on animal flesh for their survival. If humanity were to suddenly agree that animals have the right not to be eaten by people, what would happen to these groups? This problem is made even worse by the concept of land rights. If we recognize the right of wild animals to live freely, we have to make sure they have someplace to live. But what if we need that land to grow crops to feed people? And what about the rodents that want to eat the crops? They, too, have a right to live. These issues, particularly medical research, resonate with judges and offer the negative a chance to claim the moral high ground by answering graphic stories about the abuse of animals with graphic stories about terrible diseases that could not be cured without animal research. The key to winning on this argument is to show that the harm caused to human beings from recognizing animal rights is so huge that it eclipses the harm caused to animals by not recognizing their rights. The third point negatives should strive to win is that refusing to recognize animal rights does not amount to an endorsement of animal cruelty. Several authors make this point ad nauseam, as they should. Several justifications for protecting animals from undue harm fall outside the scope of animal rights. For example, Augustine, Singer, and Regan all point out that cruelty towards animals tends to lead to cruelty towards other human beings. Several thinkers, including Cohen and Fox, emphasize that we can have obligations to animals without saying they have rights. Rights are not the reciprocal of obligations, they argue. We may have an obligation not to cause unnecessary pain to a sentient being, but that doesn’t mean the being has a right not to be harmed. Again, this argument is important because it allows the negative to sidestep all the terrible, emotionallydriven accusations of baby monkey torture the affirmative is likely to lob. Whitman College Tournament 2009 8 File Title Research Guide Elisa Aaltola, Researcher in Philosophy at University of Turku in Finland. “Animal Ethics and Interest Conflicts.” Ethics and the Environment Vol. 10, No. 1 (Spring, 2005). In this article, Aatola examines conflicts of interest between humans and animals and how to resolve them. She discusses the problem through six different methodologies for conflict resolution: the rights model, the interest model, the mental complexity model, the special relations model, the multi-criteria model, and the contextual model. Of these, the contextual model is the strongest, and carries clear consequences for the practical use of animals. Michael Y. Barilan, Department of Behavioral Sciences at Tel Aviv University. “Speciesism as a Precondition to Justice.” March, 2004. Barilan provides a highly analytical argument for excluding animals from moral consideration. His thesis is that the very structure of relationships between natural organisms makes it impossible for them to participate in any form of social contract and that they are therefore excluded from moral relevancy. Lions and lambs cannot possibly find any cooperative way of surviving alongside eachother. Max Black, Professor of Philosophy (1972) The Labyrinth of Language, Harmondsworth: Penguin Books. This book is focused on the development and operation of human languages, but Black does devote considerable page space to language in relation to animals. He contends that while animals do communicate with each other and with humans, this communication differs from human language because of the inability of animals to communicate symbolically. He applies his criticism to the studies involving teaching sign language to great apes. Carl Cohen, Professor of Philosophy at the University of Michigan. 2001. The Animal Rights Debate. Oxford: Rowman and Littlefield Publishers. Cohen presents a fairly vitriolic attack on animal rights theories, including those of Regan and Singer. He focuses especially intently on establishing morally relevant differences between humans and animals, and ultimately concludes that humans are entitled to rights because they are members of the species Homo sapiens. He acknowledges that this conclusion is speciesist and argues that speciesism is not only morally defensible but morally required. He also devotes substantial space to rebutting claims that research on animals is inhumane, and offers a theoretical defense of experimentation. David Degrazia, Professor of Philosophy at George Washington University. “The Moral Status of Animals and Their Use in Research: A Philosophical Review.” Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal Vol. 1, No. 1 (March 1991). Degrazia provides a brief but extremely helpful summary of the views of Frey, Midgley, Regan, Sapontzis, and Singer, five of the most important animal rights authors. Degrazia also applies these authors’ ethical views to the specific problem of the use of animals in medical and other research environments, and discusses the various problem that each theory faces in that particular context. Joel Fienberg, Professor of Religion. “Human Duties and Animal Rights.” On the Fifth Day. Eds. Morris and Fox (1986). Fienberg’s article focuses primarily on religious objections to animal rights, but his discussion of the presence of conscience and morality in animals is useful. His stance is that, while animals may understand that a particular action is likely to result in punishment, they don’t understand the reason the punishment will result. For Fienberg, this means they lack moral capacity. R.G. Frey, 1980. Interests and Rights: The Case Against Animals. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Like Singer, Frey is an act utilitarian. However, he makes a compelling argument that animals lack the capacity to have interests because they lack language. His principle argument is that language is essential to having interests because interests are associated with concepts that cannot exist in a mind without linguistic ability. Whitman College Tournament 2009 9 File Title Michael Fox, Vice President of the Farm Animals and Bioethics section of the Human Society of the United States and former psychology lecturer at Washinton University. The Case for Animal Experimentation: An Evolutionary and Ethical Perspective (1986). Fox, whose background is in clinical psychology, focuses his book on the ethics of using animals in medical and human health testing. He spends much of the book on the ethical and moral debate surrounding animal testing, addressing issues including animal intelligence, capacity to suffer, and the question of animal autonomy and personhood. He also addresses the practical problems outlawing animal testing would pose, and comes down decidedly for continuing to use animals as laboratory subjects. Michael Fox, Adjunct Professor at Queens University. “Animal Liberation: A Critique.” Ethics Vol. 88, No. 2 (Jan., 1978). This critique of Singer’s seminal work focuses on the question of whether animals have moral agency. Fox argues they do not, citing as evidence the diminished intellectual, moral, and linguistic capacities of animals. The crux of his argument is that animals lack in autonomy and so cannot be considered equals in ethical calculus. Michael P.T Leahy, Senior Lecturer in Philosophy at the University of Kent. Against Liberation: Putting Animals in Perspective (1991). Leahy’s book is a valuable resource for the negative. It sums up and attacks the positions held by Singer and Regan, summarizes the case presented by Frey, and applies the work of several other philosophers including Aristotle, Darwin, and Wittgenstein to the topic of animal rights. Leahy also includes an afterword in which he answers critiques given by Singer and others. This section may be particularly useful in cutting response evidence. Edwin Locke, Professor Emeritus at the University of Maryland. “Animal ‘Rights’ and the New Man-Haters.” Accessed 7/8/10 http://www.aynrand.org/site/PageServer?pagename=objectivism_animal_rights. In this brief article, Locke argues that morality is the basis of any rights claim. Though he doesn’t state it explicity, his argument is similar to that of social contract theorists who also exclude animals. Locke also lobs some ad-hominem attacks at animal rights advocates and accuses them of shoddy science. H. J. McCloskey. 1987. The Moral Case for Animal Experimentation. The Monist 70 6:64-82. McCloskey’s defense of animal experimentation is largely utilitarian. His thesis is that animal experimentation is humane, that there is no alternative for many types of research, and that animal pain is superficial compared to human pain. He also makes some theoretical arguments about why animals are not members of the moral community and hence lack rights, although their pain is morally considerable. Richard Posner, 7th Circuit Court of Appeals, “Animal Rights Debate Between Peter Singer and Richard Posner.” Slate. (2001) http://www.utilitarian.net/singer/interviews-debates/200106--.htm, Accessed 7/14/10 This article is a series of letters exchanged between Singer and Posner debating the merits of animal rights. The article is useful because it offers good response arguments to a number of claims likely to arise in debates on both sides of the resolution. Tom Regan. 1983. The Case for Animal Rights. Berkeley: University of California Press. Regan, like Singer, takes a fairly radical stance in advocating the need for drastic reforms in the human relationship with animals. Unlike Singer, however, Regan rejects strict utilitarianism and instead argues for a rightsoriented ethic towards animals. For example, while Singer would allow some animal research if the benefits clearly outweigh the harm, Regan would be very reluctant to do so because of his immense respect for individual rights. Tom Regan. 2003. Animal Rights, Human Wrongs: An Introduction to Moral Philosophy. Oxford: Rowman and Littlefield Publishers. Regan’s book is an easy-to-read introduction to ethical and moral philosophy centered on animal rights. He examines the various foundations of ethical philosophy, including direct and indirect duty views, utilitarianism and social contract theory from an animal rights perspective. This is an excellent resource for summing up the implications of various philosophical systems on the topic. S. F. Sapontzis 1987. Morals, Reason, and Animals. Philadelphia: Temple University Press. Whitman College Tournament 2009 10 File Title Sapontzis defends animal rights from a more nuanced position than Singer or Regan’s hard line. The argument incorporates less well-known aspects of ethical philosophy including moral proximity and relatability, and concludes that animals are not sufficiently distinct from human beings to justify mistreatment. The author also discusses some particularly grizzly practices at factory farms. Peter Singer. 1975. Animal Liberation: A New Ethics for Our Treatment of Animals. New York: New York Review of Books. Singer’s book jumpstarted the focus on the problem of animal rights in philosophy and ethics. He is an act utilitarian and argues persuasively that because animals have the ability to suffer or feel pain, they are entitled to equal consideration of interests. Whether this can be called an appeal for animal rights is questionable, however, because Singer’s goal as a utilitarian is to maximize pleasure and minimize pain regardless of any one individual’s rights. This book is exceptionally clearly written and is a superb starting point for affirmative research. Peter Singer, Professor of Philosophy at Princeton University, “Animal Rights Debate Between Peter Singer and Richard Posner.” Slate, (2001) http://www.utilitarian.net/singer/interviews-debates/200106--.htm, Accessed 7/14/10 This article is a series of letters exchanged between Singer and Posner debating the merits of animal rights. The article is useful because it offers good response arguments to a number of claims likely to arise in debates on both sides of the resolution. Bonnie Steinbock, Professor of Philosophy at the State University of New York—Albany. “Speciesism and the Idea of Equality.” Philosophy Vol. 53, No. 204 (1978). Steinbock opposes animal rights on the basis that there are meaningful, relevant difference between humans and non-human animals which justify speciesism. She claims that human intellect provides the necessary cutoff point for rights due to its practical and philosophical implications. Steinbock also offers a compelling argument that speciesism is a sensible reaction to this innate difference, while carefully pointing out that racism, sexism, and other forms of intra-human discrimination are not. Whitman College Tournament 2009 11 File Title Definitions JUSTICE: THE EXISTENCE OF A PROPER BALANCE The Concise Oxford Dictionary of Politics, 2003, http://www.answers.com/topic/justice, accessed 7/12/2010. DISCUSSION: This definition of justice is advantageous to the negative because of the ambiguity of the phrase “proper balance.” The negative can argue that a proper balance will inevitably favor humans for some reason, which means that even if all the affirmative arguments are true justice would still demand that animal rights not be recognized. JUSTICE: A STATE OF AFFAIRS IN WHICH CONDUCT OR ACTION IS BOTH FAIR AND RIGHT, GIVEN THE CIRCUMSTANCES. Duhaime Law Dictionary, http://www.duhaime.org/LegalDictionary/J/Justice.aspx, accessed 7/12/2010. DISCUSSION: This definition of justice is fairly standard, but noticeably broad due to the phrase “given the circumstances.” This allows either side to avoid being boxed into defend specific policy options (ie…universal animal testing ban) because circumstances could conceivable justify most things. REQUIRES: TO NEED OR MAKE NECESSARY Cambridge Online Dictionary, http://dictionary.cambridge.org/dictionary/british/require#require__3, Accessed 7/13/10 DISCUSSION: A fairly typical interpretation, this could force the affirmative into a slightly harder burden of proof than other interpretations. Here, the affirmative must establish that recognition of animal rights is a prerequisite for justice. REQUIRES: TO CALL FOR AS SUITABLE OR APPROPRIATE Merriam-Webster’s Online Dictionary, http://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/requires, Accessed 7/13/2010 DISCUSSION: This interpretation may set a slightly lower burden for the affirmative, because it doesn’t necessarily see animal rights as a prerequisite for justice, but rather appropriate for justice. RECOGNITION: SPECIAL NOTICE OR ATTENTION Merriam-Webster’s Online Dictionary, http://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/recognition, Accessed 7/13/10 DISCUSSION: This definition is interesting in that the mere act of paying attention to animal rights or giving them special notice would not necessarily require any sort of behavioral or policy adjustment. An affirmative case could conceivably no-link all negative arguments RECOGNITION: AGREEMENT THAT SOMETHING IS TRUE OR LEGAL Cambridge Dictionaries Online, http://dictionary.cambridge.org/dictionary/british/recognition_1, Accessed 7/13/10 ANIMAL RIGHTS: IDEA THAT THE MOST BASIC INTERESTS OF NON-HUMAN ANIMALS SHOULD BE AFFORDED THE SAME CONSIDERATION AS THE SIMILAR INTERESTS OF A HUMAN BEINGS. Wise, Steven M. "Animal Rights", Encyclopædia Britannica, 2007, accessed May 17, 2010 DISCUSSION: This interpretation is valuable to any affirmative running Singer’s argument about equal consideration of interests. It explicitly links animal rights to equal consideration, not necessarily equal treatment. This is broad enough to allow the affirmative to avoid defending a complete ban on hunting or medical research, for example. Whitman College Tournament 2009 12 File Title ANIMAL RIGHTS: THE RIGHTS OF ANIMALS TO BE TREATED WELL, FOR EXAMPLE BY NOT BEING USED FOR TESTING DRUGS OR BY NOT BEING HUNTED. Cambridge Dictionaries Online, http://dictionary.cambridge.org/dictionary/british/animal-rights, Accessed 7/13/10 DISCUSSION: This definition is very vague, which may be to the advantage of the affirmative. This would allow the affirmative to pivot in later speeches on the meaning and scope of the word “well.” Does “well” mean the right to be free from any harm by humans? Or only animals must not be harmed without a good reason? ANIMAL: ANY MEMBER OF THE KINGDOM, ANIMALIA Dictionary.com, http://dictionary.reference.com/browse/animal, 7/13/2010 DISCUSSION: This is the scientific definition of the word animal. Notably, Homo sapiens is a member of the kingdom Animalia which means human rights can be viewed as a subset of animal rights. The affirmative might argue that rejection of animal rights is tantamount to a rejection of human rights, therefore. ANIMAL: SOMETHING THAT LIVES AND MOVES BUT IS NOT A HUMAN, BIRD, FISH, OR INSECT. Cambridge Dictionaries Online, http://dictionary.cambridge.org/dictionary/british/animal_1, Accessed 7/13/10 DISCUSSION: This is a British definition. For some reason British people often think the word “animal” refers exclusively to mammals. This interpretation could be useful for an affirmative wishing to defend the rights only of higher animals with greater intelligence or capacity for suffering. RIGHTS: COLLECTION OF ENTITLEMENTS PROTECTED BY THE GOVERNMENT Law.dictionary.com, http://dictionary.law.com/Default.aspx?selected=1858, Accessed 7/13/2010. DISCUSSION: This definition could change the debate somewhat because it views rights through the lens of the government rather than as arising from personal duties or obligations. RIGHTS: JUSTIFIED EXPECTATIONS ABOUT THE BENEFITS OTHER PEOPLE OR SOCIETY OUGHT TO PROVIDE. Philosophypages.com, http://www.philosophypages.com/dy/r9.htm#rights, Accessed 7/13/2010 DISCUSSION: This conception of rights is more closely tied to the individual and community, which could shift the focus of the debate away from policy and towards personal obligations towards animals. Whitman College Tournament 2009 13 File Title Affirmative Case DEFINITIONS JUSTICE: A STATE OF AFFAIRS IN WHICH CONDUCT OR ACTION IS BOTH FAIR AND RIGHT, GIVEN THE CIRCUMSTANCES. (you wouldn’t give a madman back his sword as Socrates says in one of his dialogues) Duhaime Law Dictionary, http://www.duhaime.org/LegalDictionary/J/Justice.aspx, accessed 7/12/2010. RECOGNITION: AGREEMENT THAT SOMETHING IS TRUE OR LEGAL Cambridge Dictionaries Online, http://dictionary.cambridge.org/dictionary/british/recognition_1, Accessed 7/13/10 ANIMAL RIGHTS: THE RIGHTS OF ANIMALS TO BE TREATED WELL, FOR EXAMPLE BY NOT BEING USED FOR TESTING DRUGS OR BY NOT BEING HUNTED. Cambridge Dictionaries Online, http://dictionary.cambridge.org/dictionary/british/animal-rights, Accessed 7/13/10 VALUE: JUSTICE CRITERION: EQUAL CONSIDERATION OF INTERESTS Equal consideration of interests is the moral principle that we should evaluate the interests of all beings effected by a given action in determining whether or not that action is moral. The affirmative will prove that animals have interests, and that justice requires that those interests be weighed equally because refusal to do so is baseless, arbitrary, and prejudiced. I should note that equal consideration does not necessarily mean equal treatment; I don’t advocate voting rights for pigs any more than I would advocate abortion rights for men. Rather, equal consideration simply means that we must evaluate the impact of our actions on all sentient creatures. CONTENTION 1: ANIMALS HAVE INTERESTS ANIMALS FEEL PAIN—EXTERNAL BEHAVIOR PROVES Singer, Peter, Professor of Philosophy at Princeton. Animal Liberation. 1990, pp 10-12. Nearly all the external signs that lead us to infer pain in other humans can be seen in other species, especially the species most closely related to us--the species of mammals and birds. The behavioral signs include writhing, facial contortions, moaning, yelping or other forms of calling, attempts to avoid the source of the pain, appearance of fear at the prospect of its repetition, and so on. In addition, we know that these animals have nervous systems very like ours, which respond physiologically like ours do when the animal is in circumstances in which we would feel pain: an initial rise of blood pressure, dilated pupils, perspiration, an increased pulse rate, and, if the stimulus continues, a fall in blood pressure. Although human beings have a more developed cerebral cortex than other animals, this part of the brain is concerned with thinking functions rather than with basic impulses, emotions, and feelings. These impulses, emotions, and feelings are located in the diencephalon, which is well developed in many other species of animals, especially mammals and birds. ANIMALS FEEL PAIN—PHYSIOLOGY PROVES Singer, Peter, Professor of Philosophy at Princeton. Animal Liberation. 1990, pp 10-12. We also know that the nervous systems of other animals were not artificially constructed--as a robot might be artificially constructed--to mimic the pain behavior of humans. The nervous systems of animals evolved as our own did, and in fact the evolutionary history of human beings and other animals, especially mammals, did not diverge until the central features of our nervous systems were already in existence. A capacity to feel pain obviously enhances a species' prospects for survival, since it causes members of the species to avoid sources of injury. It is surely unreasonable to suppose that nervous systems that are virtually identical physiologically, have a common origin and a common evolutionary function, and result in similar forms of behavior in similar circumstances should actually operate in an entirely different manner on the level of subjective feelings. Whitman College Tournament 2009 14 File Title This evidence establishes that animals do have interests, which clearly demonstrates that equal consideration of those interests is at least possible. SENTIENCE IS THE BASIS OF RIGHTS Steinbock, Bonnie, Professor of Philosophy at the State University of New York—Albany. “Speciesism and the Idea of Equality.” Philosophy Vol. 53, No. 204 (1978). If the capacity to suffer is the reason for ascribing a right to freedom from acute pain, or a right to well being, then it certainly looks as though these rights must be extended to animals as well. This is the conclusion Singer arrives at. The demand for human equality rests on the equal capacity of all human beings to suffer and to enjoy well being. But if this is the basis of the demand for equality, then this demand must include all beings which have an equal capacity to suffer and enjoy well being. That is why Singer places at the basis of the demand for equality, not intelligence or reason, but sentience. And equality will mean, not equality of treatment, but 'equal consideration of interests'. The equal consideration of interests will often mean quite different treatment, depending on the nature of the entity being considered. (It would be as absurd to talk of a dog's right to vote, Singer says, as to talk of a man's right to have an abortion.) The Steinbock evidence establishes that the ability of animals to feel pain is the only appropriate standard for determining whose interests should be considered. We must evaluate animal interests as equal to human interests for the sake of justice. CONTENTION 2: HUMAN/ANIMAL DISTINCTIONS ARE ARBITRARY AND SPECIESIST HUMAN-ANIMAL SIMILARITIES OUTWEIGH DIFFERENCES Regan, Tom, Professor Emeritus of Philosophy at North Caroline State University. “The Case for Animal Rights.” Animal Rights and Human Obligations, Eds. Singer and Regan, 1989. Animals, it is true, lack many of the abilities humans possess. They can't read, do higher mathematics, build a bookcase, or make baba ghanoush. Neither can many human beings, however, and yet we don't (and shouldn't) say that they (these humans) therefore have less inherent value, less of a right to be treated with respect, than do others. It is the similarities between those human beings who most clearly, most noncontroversially have such value (the people reading this, for example), not our differences, that matter most. And the really crucial, the basic similarity it simply this: we are each of us the experiencing subject of a life, a conscious creature having an individual welfare that has importance to us whatever our usefulness to others. We want and prefer things, believe and fee things, recall and expect things. And all these dimensions of our life including our pleasure and pain, our enjoyment and suffering, our satisfaction and frustration, our continued existence or our untimely death -- all make a difference to the quality of our life as lived, as experienced, by us as individuals. As the same is true of those animals that concern us (the ones that are eaten and trapped, for example), they too must be viewed as the experiencing subjects of a life, with inherent value of their own. This evidence establishes that because there are no morally relevant differences between human beings, which leads to the conclusion that refusing to evaluate the interests of animals is inherently speciesist. INTELLIGENCE IS NOT A MORALLY RELEVANT DIFFERENCE Aaltola, Elisa, Researcher in Philosophy at University of Turku in Finland. “Animal Ethics and Interest Conflicts.” Ethics and the Environment Vol. 10, No. 1 (Spring, 2005). As has been pointed out, the fact that Liz is mentally complex does not mean that she has a right to cut down an old elm tree to satisfy her curiosity. The point is simple: even if a is more mentally complex than b, this does not mean that a ought to be always prioritized in interest conflicts against b. The relation between the weight of interests and mental complexity remains unjustified. To appreciate this, we only need to consider the consequences of the model. If we are to concentrate solely on mental skills, we are entitled to use not only other animals, but also other human beings to further our own benefit. Ultimately we could have a hierarchical society, where each individual’s moral status would be proportional to how much she scores in a cognitive skills test. LANGUAGE IS IRRELEVANT Whitman College Tournament 2009 15 File Title Singer, Peter, Professor of Philosophy at Princeton University. 1975. Animal Liberation: A New Ethics for Our Treatment of Animals. New York: New York Review of Books. It may be that the use of a public, rule-governed language is a pre-condition of conceptual thought. It may even be, although personally I doubt it, that we cannot meaningfully speak of a creature having an intention unless that creature can use language. But states like pain, surely, are more primitive than either of these, and seem to have nothing to do with language. Indeed, as Jane Goodall points out in her study of chimpanzees, when it comes to the expression of feelings and emotions, humans tend to fall back on non-linguistic modes of communication which are often found among apes, such as a cheering pat on the back, an exuberant embrace, a clasp of hands, and so on…so there seems to be no reason to at all to believe that a creature without language cannot suffer. The evidence from Singer and Aaltola indicates that none of the typically mentioned reasons why humans are superior to animals is legitimate, which means that refusing to evaluate the interests of animals is speciesist. SPECIESISM IS WRONG Regan, Tom, Professor of Philosophy at North Carolina State University 2003. Animal Rights, Human Wrongs: An Introduction to Moral Philosophy. Oxford: Rowman and Littlefield Publishers. The question, then, is whether any defensible, relevant reason can be offered in support of the speciesist judgement that the moral importance of the pains of humans and those animals, equal in other respects (I note that the same applies to equal pleasures, benefits, harms, and interests, for example), always should be weighted in favor of the human being over the animal being? To this question, neither Rawls nor Cohen (nor any other philosopher, for that matter) offers a logically relevant answer. To persist in judging human interests as being more important than the like interests of other animals because they are human interests is not rationally defensible. Speciesism is a moral prejudice. And (contrary to Cohen’s assurances to the contrary), it is wrong, not right Behaving in a speciesist manner is wrong. Only by considering the interests of all sentient creatures equally can we uphold the value of justice. Whitman College Tournament 2009 16 File Title Affirmative Extensions Factory Farming is Cruel FACTORY FARMING IS HORRIBLE TO ANIMALS Tom Regan, Professor of Philosophy at North Caroline State University. “The Case for Animal Rights.” The Animal Rights Debate. (2001) In a word, calves raised in veal crates are denied virtually everything that answers to their nature. That they display behavioral patterns (e.g., repetitive movements and tongue rolling) associated with psychological maladjustment should surprise no one. These animals are not well, not in body, not in mind. When the day arrives for them to go to their foreordained slaughter, not as the frolicsome creatures they might have been but as the stunted “fancy” meat machines their producers and consumers have made them, death arguably offers these forlorn animals a better bargain than the life they have known. MEAT IS 100% UNNECESSARY FOR HUMANS Tom Regan, Professor of Philosophy at North Caroline State University. “The Case for Animal Rights.” The Animal Rights Debate. (2001) The “protein myth” (“You have to eat meat to get your protein”) once employed wide currency among the general public. Times have changed. Today, more and more people understand that all the protein humans need for optimal health can be obtained without eating meat (a vegetarian diet) and without eating meat or any other food derived from animals, including milk, cheese, and eggs (a vegan diet). Even the United States Department of Agriculture (USDA), no friend of vegetarianism in the past, today waves a dietary flag of truce. In its most recent assessment, the USDA acknowledges that vegetarianism and veganism offer positive, healthy dietary options. FACTORY FARMING IS CRUEL TO COWS People for the Ethical Treatment of Animals (PETA), http://www.peta.org/mc/factsheet_display.asp?ID=103, Accessed 7/14/10. Cows who are free to roam pastures and care for their young form life-long friendships with one another and have demonstrated the ability to be vain, hold grudges, solve problems, and play games. But cows raised for the meat and dairy industries are often far removed from lush pastures and nursing calves. Cattle raised for beef may be born in one state, fattened in another, and slaughtered in yet another. They are fed an unnatural diet of high-bulk grains and other “fillers,” which can include expired dog and cat food, poultry feces, and leftover restaurant food. They are castrated, their horns are ripped out, and they have third-degree burns inflicted on them (branding)—all without any painkillers. During transportation, cattle are crowded onto trucks, where they suffer from trampling and temperature extremes and lack food, water, and veterinary care. At the slaughterhouse, cattle may be hoisted upside down by their hind legs and dismembered while they are still conscious. The kill rate in a typical slaughterhouse is 400 animals per hour, and “the line is never stopped simply because an animal is alive,” according to one slaughterhouse worker. Calves raised for veal are the male offspring of dairy cows. They’re taken from their mothers within a few days of birth, and they are chained in stalls that have slatted floors and are only 2 feet wide and 6 feet long. Since their mothers’ milk is used for human consumption, the calves are fed a milk substitute that is designed to help them gain at least 2 pounds a day. The diet is purposely low in iron so that the calves become anemic and their flesh stays pale and tender Whitman College Tournament 2009 17 File Title Factory Farming is Inhumane FACTORY FARMING IS CRUEL TO CHICKENS People for the Ethical Treatment of Animals (PETA), http://www.peta.org/mc/factsheet_display.asp?ID=103, Accessed 7/14/10. Chickens are inquisitive animals, and in their natural surroundings, they form friendships and social hierarchies, recognize one another and develop pecking orders, love and care for their young, and enjoy full lives that include dust-bathing, making nests, and roosting in trees. On factory farms, however, chickens are denied these activities and suffer because of it. Laying hens live in battery cages stacked tier upon tier in huge warehouses. Confined seven or eight to a cage, they don’t have enough room to turn around or spread even one wing. Conveyor belts bring in food and water and carry away eggs. Farmers often induce greater egg production through “forced molting”: Chickens are denied food and light for days, which leads to feather and weight loss. To prevent stressinduced behaviors caused by extreme crowding—such as pecking their cagemates to death—hens are typically kept in semi-darkness, and the ends of their sensitive beaks are cut off with hot blades without any painkillers. The wire mesh of the cages rubs their feathers and skin off and causes their feet to become crippled. Chickens can live for more than a decade, but laying hens on factory farms are exhausted and unable to produce as many eggs by the time they are 2 years old, so they are slaughtered. More than 100 million “spent” hens die in slaughterhouses each year. Ninety-eight percent of the egg industry’s hens are confined to cages on factory farms. More than 9 billion “broiler” chickens are raised in sheds each year. Artificial lighting is manipulated to keep the birds eating as often as possible. To keep up with demand and to reduce production costs, genetic selection calls for big birds and fast growth (it now takes only six weeks to “grow out” a chick to “processing” weight), which causes extremely painful joint and bone conditions. Undercover investigations into the “broiler” chicken industry have revealed that birds routinely suffer from dehydration, respiratory diseases, bacterial infections, heart attacks, crippled legs, and other serious ailments. At the slaughterhouse, chickens are hung upside down, their legs are forced into metal shackles, their throats are cut, and they are immersed in scalding-hot water in defeathering tanks. They are often conscious throughout the entire process FACTORY FARMING IS CRUEL TO PIGS People for the Ethical Treatment of Animals (PETA), http://www.peta.org/mc/factsheet_display.asp?ID=103, Accessed 7/14/10. Pigs are very clean animals who take to the mud primarily to cool off and evade flies. They are just as friendly and gregarious as dogs, and according to Professor Donald Broom at the Cambridge University Veterinary School, “They have the cognitive ability to be quite sophisticated. Even more so than dogs and certainly three-year-olds.” Mother pigs on factory farms in the U.S. spend most of their lives confined to crates that measure 7 feet long and 2 feet wide, barely larger than the pigs themselves. They display signs of extreme boredom and stress, such as biting the bars of their cages and gnashing their teeth. Their piglets are taken away three weeks after birth and packed into pens until they are singled out to be raised for breeding or for meat. Like chickens and turkeys, pigs are genetically manipulated and pumped full of drugs, and many become crippled under their own weight. Although pigs are naturally affable and social animals, the confinement of these crowded pens causes neurotic behaviors such as cannibalism and tail-biting, so farmers cut off piglets’ tails without any painkillers and use pliers to break off the ends of piglets’ teeth. Pigs are transported through all weather extremes, often freezing to the sides of transport trucks in leading pig-slaughtering states such as Iowa and Nebraska, or dying from dehydration in states such as North Carolina. According to industry statistics, more than 1 million pigs die en route to slaughter each year. At the slaughterhouse, improper stunning means that many hogs reach the scalding-hot water baths—which are intended to soften their skin and remove their hair—while they are still conscious. USDA inspection records documented 14 humane slaughter violations at one processing plant, including finding hogs who “were walking and squealing after being stunned [with a stun gun] as many as four times.” A PETA investigation found that workers at an Oklahoma farm were killing pigs by slamming the animals’ heads against the floor and beating them with a hammer. At a Hormel supplier in Iowa, PETA investigators witnessed rampant cruelty to animals, including that workers beat pigs with metal gate rods and jabbed clothespins into pigs’ eyes and faces Whitman College Tournament 2009 18 File Title Factory Farming is bad FACTORY FARMING IS BAD FOR HUMANS AND THE ENVIRONMENT People for the Ethical Treatment of Animals (PETA), http://www.peta.org/mc/factsheet_display.asp?ID=103, Accessed 7/14/10. Factory farms are harmful to the environment as well as being cruel to animals. The 3 trillion pounds of waste produced by factory-farmed animals each year are usually sprayed on fields, and they subsequently run off into waterways—along with the drugs and bacteria that they contain. According to the EPA, agricultural runoff is the number one source of water pollution.Two-thirds of all agricultural land in the U.S. is used to raise animals for food or to grow grain to feed them.(26) Chickens, pigs, cattle, and other animals raised for food are the primary consumers of water in the U.S.—a single pig consumes 21 gallons of drinking water per day, while a cow on a dairy farm drinks as much as 50 gallons daily. It takes more than 2,400 gallons of water to produce 1 pound of cow flesh, whereas it takes about 180 gallons of water to produce 1 pound of whole-wheat flour. Food-related illnesses affect more than 76 million people annually and kill more than 5,000. Consumer Reports found that two-thirds of chickens studied were infected with either salmonella or campylobacter or both. Eggs pose a salmonella threat to approximately one out of every 50 people each year in some parts of the U.S. Potentially deadly E. coli bacteria sickens more than 62,000 people each year, and the USDA reports that most of the cattle slaughtered for food in the U.S. are likely infected with it. VEGAN DIET SUPPLIES ALL NECESSARY PROTEIN People for the Ethical Treatment of Animals (PETA), http://www.peta.org/mc/factsheet_display.asp?ID=105, Accessed 7/14/10. While virtually all vegan foods contain some protein, soybeans deserve special mention. Soybeans contain all the essential amino acids and surpass all other plant foods in the amount of protein that they can deliver to humans. The human body is able to digest 92 percent of the protein found in meat and 91 percent of the protein found in soybeans. The availability of many different and delicious soy products (e.g., tempeh, tofu, and soy-based varieties of hot dogs, burgers, and ice cream) in grocery and health-food stores suggests that the soybean, in its many forms, can accommodate a wide range of tastes. Other rich sources of non-animal protein include legumes, nuts, seeds, food yeasts, and freshwater algae. Although food yeasts, such as nutritional yeast and brewer’s yeast, do not lend themselves to being the center of one’s diet, they are extremely nutritious additions to many dishes, including soups, gravies, breads, casseroles, and dips. Most yeasts are 50 percent protein. Whitman College Tournament 2009 19 File Title Animal Testing is Cruel TOXICITY TESTS ARE AWFUL Tom Regan, Professor of Philosophy at North Caroline State University. “The Case for Animal Rights.” The Animal Rights Debate. (2001) The LD50 (test to discover what dosage of a chemical will kill 50% of subjects) works this way. The test substance is orally administered to the test animals, some of whome are given the substance in more, others in less, concentrated forms. In theory, anything and everything has a lethal dose. Even water has been shown to be lethal to 50% of test animals, if enough is consumed in a short enough period of time. To control variables, and because the animals themselves will not “volunteer” to swallow such things as paint thinner or Christmas tree spray, a measured amount is passed through a tube and down the animals’ throats. Variables are also controlled by withholding anesthetic. Anywhere from ten to sixty animals are used. Observation of their condition may last up to two weeks, during which time the requisite 50% normally die, after which the remaining animals are killed and their dissected bodies examined…tests like LD50 are the invisible history behind the “Harmful or fatal if swallowed” labels on cans of items such as brake fluids, household lubricants, and industrial solvents. ANIMAL RESEARCH IS GETTING MORE CRUEL, AND IT’S WASTEFUL People For the Ethical Treatment of Animals (PETA), http://www.peta.org/mc/factsheet_display.asp?ID=126 Accessed 7/14/10 Because of the unpredictable nature of genetic manipulation, any “mistakes” that are made can have disastrous consequences for the animals involved. Transgenic pigs who were bred to grow faster and leaner have suffered from arthritis, lethargy, abnormal skull growth, and impaired immune systems. The widely recognized potential for genetic manipulation to result in adverse effects on animals’ health and well-being prompted the Canadian Council on Animal Care to classify these experiments in the second-most severe “category of invasiveness”––with the potential to cause “moderate to severe distress or discomfort.” The creation of new strains of genetically manipulated animals is also incredibly wasteful and inefficient. Only between 1 and 10 percent of animals successfully incorporate the foreign genetic material injected into their embryos; those who do not are killed.This means that as many as 99 animals may be killed for every “viable” transgenic animal who is born. As a result, the number of animals subjected to genetic-manipulation experiments in the U.K. since 1990 has increased more than tenfold. Today, one out of every four animals in U.K. labs has been genetically manipulated in some way. CAPTIVITY IS BAD FOR ANIMALS Marc Bekoff and Ned Hettinger, Department of Environmental, Population, and Organismic Biology at the University of Colorado—Boulder. “Animals, Nature, and Ethics.” Journal of Mammology. Vol. 95, No. 1 (Feb. 1994) We also should not accept Howard's claim that the quality of animal lives is superior in human culture than in wild nature. For example, with rare exceptions the life of a tiger is not improved by putting it in a zoo. Although its food will be provided, hunting has played a large role in the evolution of tigers and is essential to a tiger's way of life. Movement also will be severely restricted, and for animals that typically roam in search of food and shelter, captivity produces an impoverished existence. Furthermore, it is not at all clear that captive animals live longer than their wild counterparts. Further discussion is needed concerning if and how appeals to the "ways of nature" bear on the morality of treatment of other animals by humans. Superficial appeals to nature's brutality to justify the treatment of nonhumans will not do (for a field biologist's perspective). Whitman College Tournament 2009 20 File Title Animal Testing does not help create cures TOXICITY TESTING ON ANIMALS IS INEFFECTIVE People for the Ethical Treatment of Animals (PETA), http://www.peta.org/mc/factsheet_display.asp?ID=91, Accessed 7/14/10. Acute toxicity testing began during the World War I era with the now infamous lethal dose 50 percent (LD50) test, which even today, remains the most common form of animal-poisoning study. In this test, groups of animals are force-fed increasing amounts of a substance until 50 percent of them die. Despite its decades of use, the LD50 test and its more contemporary adaptations have never been scientifically validated to confirm that their results are indeed predictive of chemical effects in people. One international study that examined the results of rat and mouse LD50 tests for 50 chemicals found that these tests were able to predict toxicity in humans with only 65 percent accuracy––while a series of human cell-line tests was found to predict toxicity in humans with about 75 percent accuracy. TESTING ON ANIMALS IS BAD SCIENCE Andrew Rowan, Professor at Tufts University School of Veterinary Medicine and Director of the Tufts Center Animals and Public Policy. “The Use of Animals in Experimentation: An Examination of the ‘Technical’ Arguments Used to Criticize the Practice.” Animal Rights: The Changing Debate (1996). Sharpe states that: ‘the real choice is not between dogs and children, it is between good science and bad science; between methods that directly relate to humans and those that do not. By its very nature vivisection is bad science: it tells us about animals, usually under artificial conditions, not about people. ANIMAL RESEARCH DOES NOTHING TO CURE HUMAN DISEASE People For the Ethical Treatment of Animals (PETA), http://www.peta.org/mc/factsheet_display.asp?ID=126 Accessed 7/14/10 Diseases that are artificially induced in animals in a laboratory are never identical to those that occur naturally in human beings. And because animal species differ from one another in many biologically significant ways, it becomes even more unlikely that animal research will yield results that will be correctly interpreted and applied to the human condition in a meaningful way. The fact that the species most often used in laboratory experiments are chosen largely for nonscientific reasons, such as cost and ease of handling, casts further doubt on the validity of this research. In addition, the results of animal experiments are often so variable and easily manipulated that researchers have used them to “prove”––depending on the source of funding––that cigarettes do cause cancer and that they do not! A careful scientific review of 10 randomly chosen “animal models” of human disease found that they made little, if any, contribution toward the treatment of human patients Whitman College Tournament 2009 21 File Title The Fur Industry is Cruel THE FUR INDUSTRY IS CRUEL TO ANIMALS People for the Ethical Treatment of Animals (PETA), http://www.peta.org/mc/factsheet_display.asp?ID=56, Accessed 7/14/10. The most commonly farmed fur-bearing animals are minks, followed by foxes. Chinchillas, lynxes, and even hamsters are also farmed for their fur. Fifty-eight percent of mink farms are in Europe, 10 percent are in North America, and the rest are dispersed throughout the world, in countries such as Argentina, China, and Russia. Mink farmers usually breed female minks once a year. There are about three or four surviving kittens in each litter, and they are killed when they are about 6 months old, depending on what country they are in, after the first hard freeze. Minks used for breeding are kept for four to five years. The animals—who are housed in unbearably small cages—live with fear, stress, disease, parasites, and other physical and psychological hardships, all for the sake of an unnecessary global industry that makes billions of dollars annually. FUR RANCHES ARE HORRIBLE PLACES Tom Regan, Professor of Philosophy at North Caroline State University. “The Case for Animal Rights.” The Animal Rights Debate. (2001) The premium placed on not spoiling the coat carries over to the method of killing. No throat slitting here, as is true in the case of the slaughter of veal calves. Noninvasive methods, none of which involves the use of anesthetics, are the rule…these small animal are…frequently asphyxiated through the use of carbon dioxide or carbon monoxide. In the case of fox, anal electrocution may be the method of choice. It works this way. First, a metal clamp is fastened around the animals’ muzzle. Next, one end of an electrified metal rod is shoved up the fox’s anus. Then a switch is turned on and the animal is electrocuted to death, from the inside out. When properly done, these methods yield unblemished plelts. Whitman College Tournament 2009 22 File Title Animals are Intelligent ANIMALS ARE INTELLIGENT AND HAVE PREFERENCES Regan, Tom, Professor of Philosophy at North Carolina State University 2003. Animal Rights, Human Wrongs: An Introduction to Moral Philosophy. Oxford: Rowman and Littlefield Publishers. Writing of mammalian animals, Darwin observes that “there is no fundamental difference between man and the higher animals and their mental faculties.” The difference in the mental life of human beings and other mammals, he adds, is “one of degree, not of kind.” What Darwin means, I think, is that these animals are like us in having a rich, unified mental life. Darwin himself catalogs the mental attributes he finds in other mammals, basing his findings on his own and others’ observations of their behavior. It is an impressive list, including…such emotions as terror, suspicion, courage, rage, shame, jealousy, grief, love, and affection, and such higher order cognitive abilities as curiosity, attention, memory, imagination, and reason. INTELLIGENCE IS NOT A MORALLY RELEVANT DIFFERENCE Aaltola, Elisa, Researcher in Philosophy at University of Turku in Finland. “Animal Ethics and Interest Conflicts.” Ethics and the Environment Vol. 10, No. 1 (Spring, 2005). As has been pointed out, the fact that Liz is mentally complex does not mean that she has a right to cut down an old elm tree to satisfy her curiosity. The point is simple: even if a is more mentally complex than b, this does not mean that a ought to be always prioritized in interest conflicts against b. The relation between the weight of interests and mental complexity remains unjustified. To appreciate this, we only need to consider the consequences of the model. If we are to concentrate solely on mental skills, we are entitled to use not only other animals, but also other human beings to further our own benefit. Ultimately we could have a hierarchical society, where each individual’s moral status would be proportional to how much she scores in a cognitive skills test. TESTS MEASURING ANIMAL INTELLIGENCE ARE ANTHROPOCENTRIC Elisa Aaltola, Professor of Philosophy at the University of Turku, Finland. “Personhood and Animals: Three Approaches.” Accessed July 4, 2010: http://www.cep.unt.edu/ISEE2/aaltola.pdf The approach to animal minds has tended to be anthropocentric. Animals have been expected to demonstrate capacities in a similar manner to humans without paying attention to matters such as species-specific traits. Cognitive capacities have been defined through the human point of view, placing the human version of the capacities as the “prototype” for any capacities…animals have been expected to be “Little scientists”, where as human beings are given “allowances” in their capacities: “When people fail to live up to this idea, we say they are all too human. When animals fail, they are said to be machine-like”… “It is not just that humans are different from ‘other animals’; ‘every [kind of] animal is the smartest’ if you know how to ask questions of its intelligence that are appropriate to its way of life rather than questions dictated by beliefs in an underlying animal stupidity. “Other animals are not simply a package of territoriality or other ‘drives’, but complex, decision-making creatures engaging with their environment.” Whitman College Tournament 2009 23 File Title Animals Communicate ANIMALS CAN COMMUNICATE LIKE HUMANS Fox, Michael, Vice President of the Farm Animals and Bioethics section of the Human Society of the United States and former psychology lecturer at Washinton University. The Case for Animal Experimentation: An Evolutionary and Ethical Perspective (1986). The capacity for language used to be thought of as Homo sapiens’ most distinctive behavior trait. We now realize that this belief was naïve. Animals of a wide variety communicate among themselves in their own often complex and indecipherable ways, and captive chimpanzees can be taught to manipulate humanly meaningful symbols, teach their young to do likewise, and communicate with one another using these same signs. LANGUAGE IS IRRELEVANT Singer, Peter, Professor of Philosophy at Princeton University. 1975. Animal Liberation: A New Ethics for Our Treatment of Animals. New York: New York Review of Books. It may be that the use of a public, rule-governed language is a pre-condition of conceptual thought. It may even be, although personally I doubt it, that we cannot meaningfully speak of a creature having an intention unless that creature can use language. But states like pain, surely, are more primitive than either of these, and seem to have nothing to do with language. Indeed, as Jane Goodall points out in her study of chimpanzees, when it comes to the expression of feelings and emotions, humans tend to fall back on non-linguistic modes of communication which are often found among apes, such as a cheering pat on the back, an exuberant embrace, a clasp of hands, and so on…so there seems to be no reason to at all to believe that a creature without language cannot suffer. Animal are feel pain ANIMALS FEEL PAIN—PHYSIOLOGY PROVES Singer, Peter, Professor of Philosophy at Princeton. Animal Liberation. 1990, pp 10-12. We also know that the nervous systems of other animals were not artificially constructed--as a robot might be artificially constructed--to mimic the pain behavior of humans. The nervous systems of animals evolved as our own did, and in fact the evolutionary history of human beings and other animals, especially mammals, did not diverge until the central features of our nervous systems were already in existence. A capacity to feel pain obviously enhances a species' prospects for survival, since it causes members of the species to avoid sources of injury. It is surely unreasonable to suppose that nervous systems that are virtually identical physiologically, have a common origin and a common evolutionary function, and result in similar forms of behavior in similar circumstances should actually operate in an entirely different manner on the level of subjective feelings. ANIMALS FEEL PAIN—EXTERNAL BEHAVIOR PROVES Singer, Peter, Professor of Philosophy at Princeton. Animal Liberation. 1990, pp 10-12. Nearly all the external signs that lead us to infer pain in other humans can be seen in other species, especially the species most closely related to us--the species of mammals and birds. The behavioral signs include writhing, facial contortions, moaning, yelping or other forms of calling, attempts to avoid the source of the pain, appearance of fear at the prospect of its repetition, and so on. In addition, we know that these animals have nervous systems very like ours, which respond physiologically like ours do when the animal is in circumstances in which we would feel pain: an initial rise of blood pressure, dilated pupils, perspiration, an increased pulse rate, and, if the stimulus continues, a fall in blood pressure. Although human beings have a more developed cerebral cortex than other animals, this part of the brain is concerned with thinking functions rather than with basic impulses, emotions, and feelings. These impulses, emotions, and feelings are located in the diencephalon, which is well developed in many other species of animals, especially mammals and birds. Whitman College Tournament 2009 24 File Title Animals are Morally Relevant SUFFERING IS THE CRITERION FOR MORAL CONSIDERATION Jeremy Bentham, English Philospher and Jurist. Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation, p. 283 (1789) The day has been, I grieve to say in many places it is not yet past, in which the greater part of the species, under the denomination of slaves, have been treated by the law exactly upon the same footing, as, in England for example, the inferior races of animals are still. The day may come when the rest of the animal creation may acquire those rights which never could have been witholden from them but by the hand of tyranny. The French have already discovered that the blackness of the skin is no reason a human being should be abandoned without redress to the caprice of a tormentor. It may one day come to be recognized that the number of the legs, the villosity of the skin, or the termination of the os sacrum are reasons equally insufficient for abandoning a sensitive being to the same fate. What else is it that should trace the insuperable line? Is it the faculty of reason or perhaps the faculty of discourse? But a full-grown horse or dog, is beyond comparison a more rational, as well as a more conversable animal, than an infant of a day or a week or even a month, old. But suppose the case were otherwise, what would it avail? the question is not, Can they reason?, nor Can they talk? but, Can they suffer? HUMAN-ANIMAL SIMILARITIES OUTWEIGH DIFFERENCES Regan, Tom, Professor Emeritus of Philosophy at North Caroline State University. “The Case for Animal Rights.” Animal Rights and Human Obligations, Eds. Singer and Regan, 1989. Animals, it is true, lack many of the abilities humans possess. They can't read, do higher mathematics, build a bookcase, or make baba ghanoush. Neither can many human beings, however, and yet we don't (and shouldn't) say that they (these humans) therefore have less inherent value, less of a right to be treated with respect, than do others. It is the similarities between those human beings who most clearly, most noncontroversially have such value (the people reading this, for example), not our differences, that matter most. And the really crucial, the basic similarity it simply this: we are each of us the experiencing subject of a life, a conscious creature having an individual welfare that has importance to us whatever our usefulness to others. We want and prefer things, believe and fee things, recall and expect things. And all these dimensions of our life including our pleasure and pain, our enjoyment and suffering, our satisfaction and frustration, our continued existence or our untimely death -- all make a difference to the quality of our life as lived, as experienced, by us as individuals. As the same is true of those animals that concern us (the ones that are eaten and trapped, for example), they too must be viewed as the experiencing subjects of a life, with inherent value of their own. DIFFERENT CAPACITIES JUSTIFY DIFFERENT TREATMENT, NOT DIFFERENT RIGHTS Steinbock, Bonnie, Professor of Philosophy at the State University of New York—Albany. “Speciesism and the Idea of Equality.” Philosophy Vol. 53, No. 204 (1978). What is Singer's response? He agrees that non-human animals lack certain capacities that human animals possess, and that this may justify different treatment. But it does not justify giving less consideration to their needs and interests. According to Singer, the moral mistake which the racist or sexist makes is not essentially the factual error of thinking that blacks or women are inferior to white men. For even if there were no factual error, even if it were true that blacks and women are less intelligent and responsible than whites and men, this would not justify giving less consideration to their needs and interests. SENTIENCE IS THE BASIS OF RIGHTS Steinbock, Bonnie, Professor of Philosophy at the State University of New York—Albany. “Speciesism and the Idea of Equality.” Philosophy Vol. 53, No. 204 (1978). If the capacity to suffer is the reason for ascribing a right to freedom from acute pain, or a right to well being, then it certainly looks as though these rights must be extended to animals as well. This is the conclusion Singer arrives at. The demand for human equality rests on the equal capacity of all human beings to suffer and to enjoy well being. But if this is the basis of the demand for equality, then this demand must include all beings which have an equal capacity to suffer and enjoy well being. That is why Singer places at the basis of the demand for equality, not intelligence or reason, but sentience. And equality will mean, not equality of treatment, but 'equal consideration of Whitman College Tournament 2009 25 File Title interests'. The equal consideration of interests will often mean quite different treatment, depending on the nature of the entity being considered. (It would be as absurd to talk of a dog's right to vote, Singer says, as to talk of a man's right to have an abortion.) Animal Rights are important ABILITY TO RECOGNIZE RIGHTS IS NOT REQUIRED TO HAVE RIGHTS Bekoff, Marc and Ned Hettinger, Department of Environmental, Population, and Organismic Biology at the University of Colorado—Boulder. “Animals, Nature, and Ethics” Feb. 1994 "A right," Howard tells us, "implies concomitant responsibilities, which certainly are not displayed by animals." If this were true, human infants, mentally disabled humans, and those who suffer from different forms of dementia, including Alzheimer's disease, also would lack rights because they too have no responsibilities. Ethicists, caregivers, and many others who are concerned with the rights of young (prelinguistic) humans or those humans who are mentally impaired find this conclusion to be extremely disturbing. ABSENT ABSOLUTE CERTAINTY, ASSUME ANIMAL EQUALITY Bekoff, Marc, Professor of Biology at the University of Colorado—Boulder. “Specieism and Expanding the Community of Equals.” Bioscience Vol. 48, No. 8 (Aug. 1998). Even within the confines of moral individualism, decisions about how individuals may be used are extremely difficult. As Linzey has stressed, as humans' own moral sensibilities develop and our scientific understanding increases, moral distinctions are likely to change as well. I have argued that when we are un- sure about an individual's ability to reason or to think, then we should assume that he or she can do so, in his or her ways. And when we are uncertain about an individual's ability to experience pain, anxiety, and suffering, then we must assume that he or she can do so. We should err on the side of the animals. In the end, it really is the compromising of other lives that needs to be dealt with in a serious manner, regardless of whether individuals are smart or are able to feel pain and to suffer physically or psychologically. ABILITY TO FEEL PAIN, NOT INHERENT VALUE, IS THE CRITERION FOR RELEVANCE Richard Ryder, former chairman of the Royal Society for the Prevention of Cruelty to Animals. “All Beings that Feel Pain Deserve Human Rights.” (2005) http://www.guardian.co.uk/uk/2005/aug/06/animalwelfare Accessed 7/14/10. Our concern for the pain and distress of others should be extended to any "painient" - pain-feeling - being regardless of his or her sex, class, race, religion, nationality or species. Indeed, if aliens from outer space turn out to be painient, or if we ever manufacture machines who are painient, then we must widen the moral circle to include them. Painience is the only convincing basis for attributing rights or, indeed, interests to others. Many other qualities, such as "inherent value", have been suggested. But value cannot exist in the absence of consciousness or potential consciousness. Thus, rocks and rivers and houses have no interests and no rights of their own. This does not mean, of course, that they are not of value to us, and to many other painients, including those who need them as habitats and who would suffer without them. Whitman College Tournament 2009 26 File Title Speciesism SPECIESISM IS DISCRIMINATION ON THE BASIS OF SPECIES MEMBERSHIP Peter Singer, Professor of Philosophy at Princeton University, Animal Liberation (1975). Speciesism is…a prejudice or bias in favor of the interests of members of one’s own species and against those of members of other species. MORAL INTUITION DOES NOT JUSTIFIY SPECIESISM Peter Singer, Professor of Philosophy at Princeton University, “Animal Rights Debate Between Peter Singer and Richard Posner.” Slate, http://www.utilitarian.net/singer/interviews-debates/200106--.htm, Accessed 7/14/10 But on the whole, I am more suspicious of common moral intuitions than you seem to be. It is not so long ago that laws persecuting homosexuals were justified by references to the sound moral instincts of ordinary people, and even the Nazis claimed to rest their laws on "the healthy sensibility of the people." Isn't it likely that such reactions rest on instincts that have their roots in our evolutionary history? If so, while we would ignore them at our peril, we do not have to grant them any probative weight. In other words, the fact that people commonly have a given moral reaction does not go much distance toward showing that this reaction is the one they ought to have. Hence I would turn on its head what you say in regard to the clash between intuitive moral reactions and philosophy: Insofar as we are thinking, ethically reflective beings, it is the instinctive reactions, not the philosophy, that have to go. If you do not accept this, then are you also prepared to defend the preference Americans show for those of their own racial or ethnic group? Is it even possible, consistently with the view of ethics that you appear to take, for us to argue on ethical grounds against racism, if we live in a society in which the racist intuitions are deeply entrenched? SPECIESISM IS WRONG Regan, Tom, Professor of Philosophy at North Carolina State University 2003. Animal Rights, Human Wrongs: An Introduction to Moral Philosophy. Oxford: Rowman and Littlefield Publishers. The question, then, is whether any defensible, relevant reason can be offered in support of the speciesist judgement that the moral importance of the pains of humans and those animals, equal in other respects (I note that the same applies to equal pleasures, benefits, harms, and interests, for example), always should be weighted in favor of the human being over the animal being? To this question, neither Rawls nor Cohen (nor any other philosopher, for that matter) offers a logically relevant answer. To persist in judging human interests as being more important than the like interests of other animals because they are human interests is not rationally defensible. Speciesism is a moral prejudice. And (contrary to Cohen’s assurances to the contrary), it is wrong, not right. Whitman College Tournament 2009 27 File Title Animal Rights don’t cause bad consequences ANIMAL RIGHTS DOESN’T MEANS AMOEBA RIGHTS Regan, Tom, Professor of Philosophy at North Carolina State University. 2003. Animal Rights, Human Wrongs: An Introduction to Moral Philosophy. Oxford: Rowman and Littlefield Publishers. A common criticism of animal rights attempts to reduce the idea to absurdity…the criticism alleges that if any nonhuman animal has rights, then every nonhuman animal has rights…Is it absurd to believe in amoeba rights? “Absurd” might be too harsh a word. “False” is more temperate and expresses my thinking. Why? Because I have no good reason to believe that such simple forms of animate life are subjects-of-a-life and very good reasons (for example, reasons based on comparative anatomy and physiology) for believing that they are not. Thus, the rights view offers principled grounds for believing in the rights of some non-human animals without our having to believe in the rights of all nonhuman animals, amoebas included. ANIMALS EAT ANIMALS…THAT DOESN’T MEAN PEOPLE SHOULD EAT ANIMALS Regan, Tom, Professor of Philosophy at North Carolina State University. 2003. Animal Rights, Human Wrongs: An Introduction to Moral Philosophy. Oxford: Rowman and Littlefield Publishers. Critics point out that lions eat gazelles, then ask how it can be wrong if we eat chickens. The most obvious difference in the two cases is that lions have to eat other animals in order to survive. We do not. So what a lion must do does not logically translate into what we may do. Besides, it is worth noting how much this objection diverges from our normal practice. Most Americans live in houses that have central heating and indoor plumping, ride in cars, and wear clothes. Other animals do not do any of these things. Should we therefore stop living as we live and stat imitating them? Should we go feral, leaving our home home and our clothes behind? I know of no critic of animal rights who advocates anything remotely like this. Why, then, place what carnivorous animals eat in a unique category as being the one thing animals do that we should imitate? NO BRIGHTLINE IS NECESSARY FOR ANIMAL RIGHTS Regan, Tom, Professor of Philosophy at North Carolina State Univewrsity. 2003. Animal Rights, Human Wrongs: An Introduction to Moral Philosophy. Oxford: Rowman and Littlefield Publishers. “Critics sometimes challenge animal rights by asking, “Where do you draw the line? How do you know exactly which animals are subjects-of-a-life and which animals are not?” There is an honest answer to these vexing questions: We do not know exactly where to draw the line…But neither do we need to know this. We do not need to know exactly how tall a person must be to be tall, before we can know that Shaq O’Neal is tall. We do not need to know exactly how old a person must be to be old, before we know that Grandma Moses was old. Similarly, we do not need to know exactly where an animal must be located on the phylogenic scale to be a subject-of-a-life, before we can know that the animals who concern us—the mammals and birds who are raised to be eaten, those who are ranched or trapped for their fur, or those who are used as models of human disease, for example, are subjects-of-a-life. ANIMAL RIGHTS DOES NOT REQUIRE SACRIFICING BASIC HUMAN INTERESTS Peter Singer, Professor of Philosophy at Princeton University, “Animal Rights Debate Between Peter Singer and Richard Posner.” Slate, http://www.utilitarian.net/singer/interviews-debates/200106--.htm, Accessed 7/14/10 You also attribute to me the peculiar position that "provided only that a chimpanzee has 1 percent of the mental ability of a normal human being, would require the sacrifice of the human being to save 101 chimpanzees." There is nothing in my position that requires me to draw that conclusion. Even if the words "1 percent of the mental ability of a normal human being" can be given a clear sense, I have never said that mental ability can be aggregated in this way so as to decide which lives should be saved. On the contrary, in books like Practical Ethics and Rethinking Life and Death I have suggested that the ability to see oneself as existing over time, with a past and a future, is an important part of what makes killing some beings more seriously wrong than killing others. So if having only 1 percent of the mental ability of a normal human being means that an animal lacks that capacity, then there are grounds to reject the mathematical approach that you describe. Whitman College Tournament 2009 28 File Title Humans need to treat animals well WELFARE IS INSUFFICIENT, RIGHTS MUST BE RECOGNIZED. Francione, Gary L., Co-Director of the Rutgers Animal Rights Law Center. “Animal Rights: An Incremental Approach.” Animal Rights: The Changing Debate. Ed. Garner p. 46-7. Despite the existence of literally hundreds of animal welfare laws that require the ‘humane’ treatment of animals, eight billion animals annually in the United States alone are raised in barbaric conditions of intensive agriculture and slaughtered on brutal assembly lines of death. Current standards of animal welfare also permit the use of animals for completely trivial purposes, such as circuses, zoos, rodeos, pigeon shoots, and the wearing of luxury items like fur. Indeed, in light of the development of intensive agricultural practices, the uses of animals in bioengineering, and the destruction of entire ecosystems to accommodate ostensibly limitless human expansion, it may be argued that the plight of animals in 1994 is much worse than it was in 1894. And throughout that entire period, there were animal welfare laws that protected animals from ‘unnecessary’ cruelty. HUMANS MUST TREAT ANIMALS BETTER THAN NATURE DOES Bekoff, Marc and Ned Hettinger, Department of Environmental, Population, and Organismic Biology at the University of Colorado—Boulder. “Animals, Nature, and Ethics.” Journal of Mammology. Vol. 95, No. 1 (Feb. 1994) Do we really want an ethic that sanctions treatment of animals by humans as long as it is better than what nature typically has in store for similar animals? For example, would we allow mammalogists who are accused of animal cruelty to justify their behavior with the argument that they caused them less suffering than their wild predators would have caused them? Although the sorts of lives animals lead in the wild is an important consideration for insuring appropriate care and management of animals (e.g., animals in zoos and wildlife parks), an ethic that permits any use of animals by humans that causes them less suffering or allows them a longer life than is typical for wild animals is far too weak. CRUELTY TO ANIMALS LEADS TO CRUELTY TO HUMANS Regan, Tom, Professor of Philosophy at North Carolina State University 2003. Animal Rights, Human Wrongs: An Introduction to Moral Philosophy. Oxford: Rowman and Littlefield Publishers. Recent studies confirm, what people of common sense have long suspected, that a pattern of cruelty to animals in a person’s youth is frequently correlated with a pattern of violent behavior toward humans in adult life. This is certainly a reason to discourage cruelty to animals. Still, this cannot be the only reason, nor can it be the main one, if cruelty-kindness is interpreted as a direct duty view. Interpreted this way, both the duty to be kind and the duty not to be cruel are owed to animals themselves. UTILITARIANISM IS BETTER THAN CONTRACT THEORY Regan, Tom, Professor of Philosophy at North Carolina State University. 2003. Animal Rights, Human Wrongs: An Introduction to Moral Philosophy. Oxford: Rowman and Littlefield Publishers. Utilitarianism’s egalitarianism clearly represents an improvement over simple and Rawlsian contractarianism when it comes to saying who has moral standing. Who counts morally? For utilitarians, the answer is, “All those who have interests.” Who does not count morally? For utilitarians, the answer is, “Whatever does not have interests.” Because rationally competent members of various minority groups have interests, these individuals (unlike the verdict available to simple contractarians) have moral standing according to utilitarians. And because children who lack a sense of justice have interests, these children (unlike the verdict reached by Rawlsian contractarians) have moral standing too. Everyone’s interests count, and equal interests must be counted equally, no matter whose interests they are. Whitman College Tournament 2009 29 File Title Negative Case VALUE: JUSTICE CRITERION: UPHOLDING THE SOCIAL CONTRACT The social contract is an unwritten agreement between all members of society to surrender some freedoms, like the freedom to harm others, in exchange for assurances that our basic property rights will be respected by others. The social contract is the foundation of justice because it is the source and defines the scope of all rights possessed by members of a society. The negative will prove that animals are not party to the social contract and consequently have no rights. CONTENTION 1: ANIMALS CANNOT PARTICIPATE IN THE SOCIAL CONTRACT NATURE PREVENTS ANIMALS FROM PARTICIPATION IN SOCIAL CONTRACT Barilan, Y. Michael, Department of Behavioral Sciences at Tel Aviv University. “Speciesism as a Precondition to Justice.” Politics and the Life Sciences Vol. 23 No. 1 (March, 2004). Consider the following worlds: Wl: 500 lions starve, 500 lambs range happily. W2: 500 lions are satiated, 500 lambs are mangled. W3: 250 lions starve, 250 lions are satiated, 250 lambs range freely, 250 lambs are mangled by the 250 satiated lions, and so forth. From a utilitarian perspective, worlds Wl, W2, and W3 are equivalent. The lion and the lamb cannot move in behind the "veil of ignorance" because the former cannot realize its own good without eating the latter. An animal-rights advocate would never know how to negotiate behind such a veil. A would-be lion must participate in the deliberations in ways that would undermine the welfare of a would-be lamb, and vice versa. Deliberation would become even more hopelessly intricate when factoring in all life-forms sharing the ecosystem within which justice is due to be realized. A veiled animal advocate would have to stay mute to avoid self-contradiction. OPPOSING NEEDS OF SPECIES MAKE ANIMAL RIGHTS IMPOSSIBLE Barilan, Y. Michael, Department of Behavioral Sciences at Tel Aviv University. “Speciesism as a Precondition to Justice.” Politics and the Life Sciences Vol. 23 No. 1 (March, 2004). Some Anonymi (morally relevant animals) we cannot invite into the community of justice simply because their way of living is incompatible with the circumstances of justice. The lion, the lamb, and the gorilla may count as such. Each seems morally considerable, but none is morally sociable, and those not morally sociable cannot truly be morally considerable, since moral rights cannot be exercised in isolation from a society of justice. This evidence establishes that the basic structure of relationships between different species makes a social contract including animals impossible to image. ANIMALS ARE EXCLUDED FROM CONCEPTIONS OF JUSTICE Rawls, John, Professor of Philosophy at Harvard University. A Theory of Justice (1971). …No account is given of the right conduct in regard to animals and the rest of nature. A conception of justice is but one part of a moral view. While I have not maintained that the capacity for a sense of justice is necessary in order to be owed the duties of justice, it does seem that we are not required to give strict justice anyway to creatures lacking this capacity. But it does not follow that there are no requirements at all in regard to them, nor in our relations with the natural world…They are outside the scope of the theory of justice, and it does not seem possible to extend the contract doctrine so as to include them in a natural way. As Rawls notes, there is no way to include animals in a theory of justice because they cannot participate in the social contract. Whitman College Tournament 2009 30 File Title ANIMALS HAVE NO CONSCIENCE. Fienberg, Joel, Professor of Religion. “Human Duties and Animal Rights.” On the Fifth Day. Eds. Morris and Fox (1986). Well-trained dogs sometimes let their masters down; they anticipate punishment or other manifestations of displeasure; they grovel and whimper, and they even make crude efforts at redress and reconciliation. But do they feel remorse and bad conscience? They have been conditioned to associate manifestations of displeasure with departures from a norm, and this is a useful way of keeping them in line, but they haven’t the slightest inkling of the reasons for the norm. They don’t understand why departures from the norm are wrong, or why their masters become angry or disappointed. They have a concept perhaps of the mala prohibita—the act that is wrong because it is prohibited, but they have no notion of the mala in se—the act that is prohibited because it is wrong. Even in respect to the mala prohibita their understanding is grossly deficient, for they have no conception of rightful authority. For dogs, the only basis of their master’s “right” to be obeyed is his de facto power over them. Even when one master steals a beast from another, or when an original owner deprives it of its natural freedom in the wild, the animal will feel no moralized emotion, such as outraged propriety or indignation. That animals lack understanding for why certain things are wrong and others are right is a fundamental barrier to their participation in a social contract. Without any understanding as to why something is wrong, animals would be incapable of being members of a society. CONTENTION 2: RECOGNIZING ANIMAL RIGHTS WOULD VIOLATE HUMAN RIGHTS ANIMAL RIGHTS IS IRRECONCILABLE WITH HUMAN AGRICULTURE Benton, Ted, Professor of Sociology at the University of Essex. “Animal Rights: an Eco-Socialist View.” Even someone convinced by the arguments of both utilitarians and rights-theorists that vegetarianism is morally required will surely accept that the growing of sufficient vegetable food will itself have ecological effects. Large areas of land will still be required for the growing of food for humans which might otherwise have sustained large populations of herbivorous animals, and their predators. It is also hard to imagine how such purely arable systems could operate without some method of prima facie rights-infringing pest control…The philosophy of animals rights seems not well placed to deal with these issues. Conflict between humans and animals over arable land means that recognizing animal rights would necessarily harm human property rights. MILLIONS IN AFRICA MUST EAT MEAT TO SURVIVE Cohen, Carl, Professor of Philosophy at the University of Michigan. 2001. The Animal Rights Debate. Oxford: Rowman and Littlefield Publishers. In the Horn of Africa, where agriculture cannot sustain the population, and drought results in periodic famines because livestock suffer, cattle are the principal source of food. In Ethiopia and Eritrea and Somalia and Sudan, and also in Kenya and Uganda farther south, respecting the “rights” of those cattle will result in the early death of millions of people. Replacing the nutrition that animals provide is simply not possible there, and elsewhere. INUITS MUST HUNT TO SURVIVE Cohen, Carl, Professor of Philosophy at the University of Michigan. 2001. The Animal Rights Debate. Oxford: Rowman and Littlefield Publishers. In many human communities animal products are essential for survival. Ceasing to use them would entail a wholesale transformation of diet, of work, of life itself. Such a transformation would probably prove impossible for many and would result in uncountable deaths. Parts of the price of implementing animal rights would be the resultant impact on entire human cultures…The Inuit peoples of the Arctic are utterly dependent on hunting and fishing; their very bodies have evolved so as to be able to survive on the high-calorie fats that alone make life possible in so frigid an environment. Whitman College Tournament 2009 31 File Title MEDICAL RESEARCH ON ANIMALS IS ESSENTIAL TO HUMAN SURVIVAL Still, Tom, President of the Wisconsin Technology Council. “Beyond the Protests, Instances of Mistreatment are Rare.” Accessed 7/8/2010 http://wistechnology.com/articles/2489/ Animal-based research has helped provide cures and treatments in those case and many more. Biotechnology companies have depended on animal research to develop more than 160 drugs and vaccines approved by the U.S. Food and Drug Administration, according to the Biotechnology Industry Organization. Those discoveries have helped hundreds of millions of people worldwide and prevented incalculable human suffering. In addition, BIO has reported, animal research has led to 111 USDA-approved biotech-derived veterinary biologics and vaccines that improve the health of livestock, poultry and companion animals. The above evidence includes just a few examples of the many ways human property rights, and even the right to life, would be inexcusably harmed by recognition of animal rights. We owe nothing but kindness to animals and any other entities incapable of participating in the social contract. We do owe fair consideration to fellow humans. Whitman College Tournament 2009 32 File Title Negative Extensions Animal Research is Justified MUST UNDERSTAND ANIMALS TO MAXIMIZE THEIR INTERESTS Howard, Walter E., Professor of Wildlife and Fisheries Biology at the University of California-Davis. “Animal Research is Defensible.” Journal of Mammology, Vol. 74, No. 1 (Feb., 1993). To effectively promote something requires understanding it. To make a responsible estimate of how large a monkey's cage should be, we need to understand in what sense and to what degree confinement is harmful to the monkey. To decide reasonably how many monkeys should be placed in a cage, we need to understand the companionship needs of monkeys and how monkeys interact in groups. And to do all of this requires grasping a great deal about the nature of monkeys—biological, psychological, and social. As another example, when we give repeated electric shocks to rats, how bad, qualitatively, are their experiences? Do they experience only pain, or also highly emotional forms of suffering? Answering such questions is necessary for determining the extent of harm caused by particular cases of inflicted pain, suffering, and other unpleasant experiences. RESEARCH ANIMALS ONLY EXIST FOR RESEARCH PURPOSES Howard, Walter E., Professor of Wildlife and Fisheries Biology at the University of California-Davis. “Animal Research is Defensible.” Journal of Mammology, Vol. 74, No. 1 (Feb., 1993). Humans, in their moral consciousness, often accept the doctrine that animals should not be mistreated. But note, this is an obligation made to humanity, not to non-human animals. A right implies concomitant responsibilities, which certainly are not displayed by animals. People for Ethical Treatment of Animals (PETA) claim that 5.7 million animals-mostly frogs and pigs-are killed every year to be used in high school and college classes. None of these animals would be born if not wanted, and they have a quality life and die humanely rather than live nature's torturous life. From the stand point of a quality life, the need for this resource produces an improvement of life for some individuals of these species. LINK: ANIMAL RIGHTS MEANS NO MEDICAL RESEARCH ON ANIMALS Regan, Tom, Professor Emeritus of Philosophy at North Caroline State University and Animal Rights Activist. “The Case for Animal Rights.” Animal Rights and Human Obligations, Eds. Singer and Regan, 1989. In the case of the use of animals in science, the rights view is categorically abolitionist. Lab animals are not our tasters; we are not their kings. Because these animals are treated routinely, systematically as if their value were reducible to their usefulness to others, they are routinely, systematically treated with a lack of respect, and thus are | their rights routinely, systematically violated. This is just as true when they are used in trivial, duplicative, unnecessary or unwise research as it is when they are used in studies that hold out real promise of human benefits. We can't justify harming or killing a human being (my Aunt Bea, for example) just for these sorts of reason. Neither can we do so even in the case of so lowly a creature as a laboratory rat. It is not just refinement or reduction that is called for, not just larger, cleaner cages, not just more generous use of anesthesia or the elimination of multiple surgery, not just tidying up the system. It is complete replacement. The best we can do when it comes to using animals in science is -- not to use them. That is where our duty lies, according to the rights view. THERE IS NO GOOD SUBSTITUTE FOR LIVE ANIMAL RESEARCH Fox, Michael, Adjunct Professor at Queens University. “Animal Liberation: A Critique.” Ethics Vol. 88, No. 2 (Jan., 1978). Singer points out that there are alternatives to experiments on animals, such as the use of tissue cultures and computer simulations. No doubt further advances will be made in these areas. But he misleads the reader seriously when he suggests that virtually all animal experiments could be eliminated by such surrogates. For the biomedical researcher and the teacher there is no substitute for a complete and healthy cardiovascular or central nervous system. Whitman College Tournament 2009 33 File Title Whitman College Tournament 2009 34 File Title Animal Research is done humanely ANIMAL RESEARCH IS REGULATED AND HUMANE Howard, Walter E., Professor of Wildlife and Fisheries Biology at the University of California-Davis. “Animal Research is Defensible.” Journal of Mammology, Vol. 74, No. 1 (Feb., 1993). Current use of animals in research is highly regulated. Abuses are rare and the benefits of the knowledge acquired to people and animal welfare are enormous. Before animals are used in research, there should be a reasoned judgement that the benefit derived from the research is sufficient to justify the use of animals and that reasonable means will be employed to provide for the welfare of its subjects. There is an extensive review process of proposed methods to be used and how the animals will be affected to ensure that only the lowest number necessary will be used. The use of alternatives to animals in research, when available, is ethically commendable, but alternatives will never be able to replace all needs of labo ratory and field research with live animals. Responsible mammalogy is ethically and morally justified and desirable. MEDICAL RESEARCH ON ANIMALS IS ESSENTIAL TO HUMAN SURVIVAL Still, Tom, President of the Wisconsin Technology Council. “Beyond the Protests, Instances of Mistreatment are Rare.” Accessed 7/8/2010 http://wistechnology.com/articles/2489/ Animal-based research has helped provide cures and treatments in those case and many more. Biotechnology companies have depended on animal research to develop more than 160 drugs and vaccines approved by the U.S. Food and Drug Administration, according to the Biotechnology Industry Organization. Those discoveries have helped hundreds of millions of people worldwide and prevented incalculable human suffering. In addition, BIO has reported, animal research has led to 111 USDA-approved biotech-derived veterinary biologics and vaccines that improve the health of livestock, poultry and companion animals. HUMANS ARE NICER TO ANIMALS THAN NATURE Howard, Walter E., Professor of Wildlife and Fisheries Biology at the University of California-Davis. “Animal Research is Defensible.” Journal of Mammology, Vol. 74, No. 1 (Feb., 1993). Nature's right-to-life requires taking lives no matter how cruelly. But when people exploit wild animals it is usually followed by replacement of others of that species, most of which would have no life at all if some had not been killed. And because of our ethics and social customs, people are an un- usually efficient and humane predator. In contrast to the brutality of natural predation, people must operate under regulations to protect the exploited animals and their populations. Billions of rodents, livestock and other animals are raised annually and managed for our use. These genetically and behaviorally different domestic animals would not be born, to live a quality and longer than average life, if not wanted. Domestic species are genetically programmed to depend upon humans for their safe existence and, fortunately, they always die relatively humanely rather than suffering one of nature's brutal deaths. Whitman College Tournament 2009 35 File Title Animal Agriculture/Hunting is Justified LINK: ANIMAL RIGHTS MEANS NO COMMERCIAL AGRICULTURE Regan, Tom, Professor Emeritus of Philosophy at North Caroline State University. “The Case for Animal Rights.” Animal Rights and Human Obligations, Eds. Singer and Regan, 1989. As for commercial animal agriculture, the rights view takes a similar abolitionist position. The fundamental moral wrong here is not that animals are kept in stressful close confinement or in isolation, or that their pain and suffering, their needs and preferences are ignored or discounted. All these are wrong, of course, but they are not the fundamental wrong. They are symptoms and effects of the deeper, systematic wrong that allows | these animals to be viewed and treated as lacking independent value, as resources for us -- as, indeed, a renewable resource. Giving farm animals more space, more natural environments, more companions does not right the fundamental wrong, any more than giving lab animals more anesthesia or bigger, cleaner cages would right the fundamental wrong in their case. Nothing less than the total dissolution of commercial animal agriculture will do this, just as, for similar reasons I won't develop at length here, morality requires nothing less than the total elimination of hunting and trapping for commercial and sporting ends. The rights view's implications, then, as I have said, are clear and uncompromising. LINKS: ANIMAL RIGHTS IS IRRECONCILABLE WITH HUMAN AGRICULTURE Benton, Ted, Professor of Sociology at the University of Essex. “Animal Rights: an Eco-Socialist View.” Even someone convinced by the arguments of both utilitarians and rights-theorists that vegetarianism is morally required will surely accept that the growing of sufficient vegetable food will itself have ecological effects. Large areas of land will still be required for the growing of food for humans which might otherwise have sustained large populations of herbivorous animals, and their predators. It is also hard to imagine how such purely arable systems could operate without some method of prima facie rights-infringing pest control…The philosophy of animals rights seems not well placed to deal with these issues. INUITS MUST HUNT TO SURVIVE Cohen, Carl, Professor of Philosophy at the University of Michigan. 2001. The Animal Rights Debate. Oxford: Rowman and Littlefield Publishers. In many human communities animal products are essential for survival. Ceasing to use them would entail a wholesale transformation of diet, of work, of life itself. Such a transformation would probably prove impossible for many and would result in uncountable deaths. Parts of the price of implementing animal rights would be the resultant impact on entire human cultures…The Inuit peoples of the Arctic are utterly dependent on hunting and fishing; their very bodies have evolved so as to be able to survive on the high-calorie fats that alone make life possible in so frigid an environment. MILLIONS IN AFRICA MUST EAT MEAT TO SURVIVE Cohen, Carl, Professor of Philosophy at the University of Michigan. 2001. The Animal Rights Debate. Oxford: Rowman and Littlefield Publishers. In the Horn of Africa, where agriculture cannot sustain the population, and drought results in periodic famines because livestock suffer, cattle are the principal source of food. In Ethiopia and Eritrea and Somalia and Sudan, and also in Kenya and Uganda farther south, respecting the “rights” of those cattle will result in the early death of millions of people. Replacing the nutrition that animals provide is simply not possible there, and elsewhere. Whitman College Tournament 2009 36 File Title Animals are Excluded from the Social Contract NATURE PREVENTS ANIMALS FROM PARTICIPATION IN SOCIAL CONTRACT Barilan, Y. Michael, Department of Behavioral Sciences at Tel Aviv University. “Speciesism as a Precondition to Justice.” Politics and the Life Sciences Vol. 23 No. 1 (March, 2004). Consider the following worlds: Wl: 500 lions starve, 500 lambs range happily. W2: 500 lions are satiated, 500 lambs are mangled. W3: 250 lions starve, 250 lions are satiated, 250 lambs range freely, 250 lambs are mangled by the 250 satiated lions, and so forth. From a utilitarian perspective, worlds Wl, W2, and W3 are equivalent. The lion and the lamb cannot move in behind the "veil of ignorance" because the former cannot realize its own good without eating the latter. An animal-rights advocate would never know how to negotiate behind such a veil. A would-be lion must participate in the deliberations in ways that would undermine the welfare of a would-be lamb, and vice versa. Deliberation would become even more hopelessly intricate when factoring in all life-forms sharing the ecosystem within which justice is due to be realized. A veiled animal advocate would have to stay mute to avoid self-contradiction. UTILITARIANISM IS INCOMPATIBLE WITH THE NATURAL WORLD. (to give the right to live to some you would have to deny it to others-lions eat lambs) Barilan, Y. Michael, Department of Behavioral Sciences at Tel Aviv University. “Speciesism as a Precondition to Justice.” March, 2004. Even if lions and lambs were reasoned to value pain and pleasure differently, equivalence could still be maintained simply by adjusting the numbers starving, ranging, satiated, and mangled. Therefore, utilitarians finds themselves committed equally to a world in which all lions suffer and to a world in which all lions are happy. Such an outcome if meaningful at all cannot guide action. W2 appears balanced or even fair, but only in the eyes of an outsider and only after species is factored in and individual rights are ignored. Even if ecological harmony were somehow optimized, individual points of view would not be reconciled. OPPOSING NEEDS OF SPECIES MAKE ANIMAL RIGHTS IMPOSSIBLE Barilan, Y. Michael, Department of Behavioral Sciences at Tel Aviv University. “Speciesism as a Precondition to Justice.” Politics and the Life Sciences Vol. 23 No. 1 (March, 2004). Some Anonymi (morally relevant animals) we cannot invite into the community of justice simply because their way of living is incompatible with the circumstances of justice. The lion, the lamb, and the gorilla may count as such. Each seems morally considerable, but none is morally sociable, and those not morally sociable cannot truly be morally considerable, since moral rights cannot be exercised in isolation from a society of justice. NATURE DICTATES ONLY HUMANS CAN LIVE JUSTLY because to be just you can’t live off of someone else Barilan, Y. Michael, Department of Behavioral Sciences at Tel Aviv University. “Speciesism as a Precondition to Justice.” Politics and the Life Sciences Vol. 23 No. 1 (March, 2004). Only agents that do not harbor life plans that unequivocally impose suffering or exploitation on others can conceive of ethics based on the avoidance of suffering and on respect. If my life plan and moral identity were dependent on the infliction of suffering suppose I was a vampire who could not survive without biting humans for their blood? An ethics of non-suffering would undermine my moral and physical existence. No human's good life is inescapably conditional on the exploitation of another human. Vampires, no matter how intelligent, sentient, compassionate, and even innocent, cannot participate in a just society. They may even contribute to ethical theory, but they cannot have moral rights. Luckily, they do not exist. ANIMALS ARE EXCLUDED FROM CONCEPTIONS OF JUSTICE Rawls, John, Professor of Philosophy at Harvard University. A Theory of Justice (1971). …No account is given of the right conduct in regard to animals and the rest of nature. A conception of justice is but one part of a moral view. While I have not maintained that the capacity for a sense of justice is necessary in order to be owed the duties of justice, it does seem that we are not required to give strict justice anyway to creatures lacking this capacity. But it does not follow that there are no requirements at all in regard to them, nor in our Whitman College Tournament 2009 37 File Title relations with the natural world…They are outside the scope of the theory of justice, and it does not seem possible to extend the contract doctrine so as to include them in a natural way. Whitman College Tournament 2009 38 File Title Animals don’t have a claim to moral rights ANIMALS ARE OUTSIDE THE MORAL REALM Cohen, Carl, Professor of Philosophy at the University of Michigan. 2001. The Animal Rights Debate. Oxford: Rowman and Littlefield Publishers. Do you believe that baby zebra has the right not to be slaughtered? Or that the lioness has the right to kill that baby zebra to feed her cubs? Perhaps you are inclined to say, when confronted with such natural rapacity (duplicated in various forms millions of times each day on planet earth), that neither is right or wrong, that neither the zebra nor the lioness has a right against the other. Then I am on your side. Rights are pivotal in the moral realm and must be taken seriously, yes; but zebras and lions are rats do not live in the moral realm; their lives are totally amoral. There is no morality for them; animals do no moral wrong, ever. In their world, there are no wrongs and there are no rights. HAVING INTERESTS DOESN’T MEAN HAVING RIGHTS. Leahy, Michael P.T., Senior Lecturer in Philosophy at the University of Kent. Against Liberation: Putting Animals in Perspective (1991). Just as it is not good to deprive a dog of warmth so it is bad to expose a valuable oil-painting to strong sunlight, implying that they both have a good which can be compromised. It is perfectly proper to claim that it might not be in the interests of a new Rolls Royce to be driven as if it were a Dodgem car…Although terms like ‘harm’, ‘benefit’, and ‘good’ are used of sentient creatures, it is Frey’s contention that they are not solely applicable to them…If we wish to exclude these interests of plants and artifacts, and one certainly would not wish to make way for ‘machine rights’, then it would seem that we must also exclude those generated by animal needs. HAVING INHERENT VALUE DOES NOT MEAN HAVING RIGHTS Cohen, Carl, Professor of Philosophy at the University of Michigan. 2001. The Animal Rights Debate. Oxford: Rowman and Littlefield Publishers. The argument for animal rights that is grounded on their “inherent value” is utterly fallacious, an egregious example of the fallacy of equivocation—that informal fallacy in which two or more meanings of the same word or phrase are confused in the several propositions of an argument…Recognizing that there has been an unmarked shift from one meaning of “inherent value” to another, we see immediately that the argument built on that shift is worthless. The “case” for animal rights evaporates… Whitman College Tournament 2009 39 File Title Animals are Amoral ANIMALS LACK MORALITY, THE FOUNDATION OF RIGHTS Locke, Edwin, Professor Emeritus at the University of Maryland. “Animal ‘Rights’ and the New Man-Haters.” Accessed 7/8/10 http://www.aynrand.org/site/PageServer?pagename=objectivism_animal_rights. Rights are ethical principles applicable only to beings capable of reason and choice…Animals do not survive by rational thought (nor by sign languages allegedly taught to them by psychologists). They survive through inborn reflexes and sensory-perceptual association. They cannot reason. They cannot learn a code of ethics…Only man has the power to deal with other members of his own species by voluntary means: rational persuasion and a code of morality rather than physical force. To claim that man's use of animals is immoral is to claim that we have no right to our own lives and that we must sacrifice our welfare for the sake of creatures who cannot think or grasp the concept of morality. It is to elevate amoral animals to a moral level higher than ourselves —a flagrant contradiction. Of course, it is proper not to cause animals gratuitous suffering. But this is not the same as inventing a bill of rights for them—at our expense. ANIMALS LACK MORAL AGENCY Cohen, Carl, Professor of Philosophy at the University of Michigan. 2001. The Animal Rights Debate. Oxford: Rowman and Littlefield Publishers. To be a moral agent is to be able to grasp the generality of moral restrictions on our will. Humans understand that some acts may be in our interest and yet must not be willed because they are simply wrong. This capacity for moral judgment does not arise in the animal world;rats can neither exercise nor respond to moral claims. My dog knows that there are certain things he must not do, but he knows this only as the outcome of his learning about his interests, the pains he may suffer if he does what has been taught forbidden. He does not know, he cannot know that any conduct is wrong…Right is not in their [animals’] world. But right and wrong are the very stuff of human moral life, the ever=present awareness of human beings who can do wrong and who by seeking (often but not always) to avoid wrong conduct prove themselves members of a moral community in which rights may be exercised and respected. ANIMALS HAVE NO CONSCIENCE. Fienberg, Joel, Professor of Religion. “Human Duties and Animal Rights.” On the Fifth Day. Eds. Morris and Fox (1986). Well-trained dogs sometimes let their masters down; they anticipate punishment or other manifestations of displeasure; they grovel and whimper, and they even make crude efforts at redress and reconciliation. But do they feel remorse and bad conscience? They have been conditioned to associate manifestations of displeasure with departures from a norm, and this is a useful way of keeping them in line, but they haven’t the slightest inkling of the reasons for the norm. They don’t understand why departures from the norm are wrong, or why their masters become angry or disappointed. They have a concept perhaps of the mala prohibita—the act that is wrong because it is prohibited, but they have no notion of the mala in se—the act that is prohibited because it is wrong. Even in respect to the mala prohibita their understanding is grossly deficient, for they have no conception of rightful authority. For dogs, the only basis of their master’s “right” to be obeyed is his de facto power over them. Even when one master steals a beast from another, or when an original owner deprives it of its natural freedom in the wild, the animal will feel no moralized emotion, such as outraged propriety or indignation. Whitman College Tournament 2009 40 File Title Animal Rights not justified MORAL INTUITION REJECTS ANIMALS RIGHTS Richard Posner, 7th Circuit Court of Appeals, “Animal Rights Debate Between Peter Singer and Richard Posner.” Slate. http://www.utilitarian.net/singer/interviews-debates/200106--.htm, Accessed 7/14/10 But I do not agree that we have a duty to (the other) animals that arises from their being the equal members of a community composed of all those creatures in the universe that can feel pain, and that it is merely "prejudice" in a disreputable sense akin to racial prejudice or sexism that makes us "discriminate" in favor of our own species. You assume the existence of the universe-wide community of pain and demand reasons why the boundary of our concern should be drawn any more narrowly. I start from the bottom up, with the brute fact that we, like other animals, prefer our own—our own family, the "pack" that we happen to run with (being a social animal), and the larger sodalities constructed on the model of the smaller ones, of which the largest for most of us is our nation. Americans have distinctly less feeling for the pains and pleasures of foreigners than of other Americans and even less for most of the nonhuman animals that we share the world with. Now you may reply that these are just facts about human nature; that they have no normative significance. But they do. Suppose a dog menaced a human infant and the only way to prevent the dog from biting the infant was to inflict severe pain on the dog—more pain, in fact, than the bite would inflict on the infant. You would have to say, let the dog bite (for "if an animal feels pain, the pain matters as much as it does when a human feels pain," provided the pain is as great). But any normal person (and not merely the infant's parents!), including a philosopher when he is not self-consciously engaged in philosophizing, would say that it would be monstrous to spare the dog, even though to do so would minimize the sum of pain in the world. Whitman College Tournament 2009 41 File Title Animals Lack Intelligence for Rights ANIMALS LACK SPEECH, THE BASIS OF SELF-KNOWLEDGE Black, Max, Professor of Philosophy (1972) The Labyrinth of Language, Harmondsworth: Penguin Books. Man is the only animal that can talk (homo loquens). More generally, he is the only animal that can use symbols (words, pictures, graphs, numbers, etc.). He alone can bridge the gap between one person and another, conveying thoughts, feelings, desires, attitudes, and sharing in the traditions, conventions, the knowledge and the superstition of his culture: the only animal that can truly understand and misunderstand. On this skill depends everything that we call civilization. Without it, imagination, thought—even self-knowledge—are impossible. INTELLIGENCE IS THE CUT-OFF POINT FOR RIGHTS Steinbock, Bonnie, Professor of Philosophy at the State University of New York—Albany. “Speciesism and the Idea of Equality.” Philosophy Vol. 53, No. 204 (1978). We do not think that those with greater capacities ought to have their interests weighed more heavily than those with lesser capacities, and this, he thinks, shows that differences in such capacities are irrelevant to equality. But it does not show this at all. Kevin Donaghy argues (rightly, I think) that what entitles us human beings to a privileged position in the moral community is a certain minimal level of intelligence, which is a prerequisite for morally relevant capacities. The fact that we would reject a hierarchical society based on degree of intelligence does not show that a minimal level of intelligence cannot be used as a cut-off point, justifying giving greater consideration to the interests of those entities which meet this standard. VIRTUALLY ALL HUMANS HAVE CAPACITIES WHICH ALL ANIMALS LACK Fox, Michael, Adjunct Professor at Queens University. “Animal Liberation: A Critique.” Ethics Vol. 88, No. 2 (Jan., 1978). The search for attributes that all humans, without exception, share in common and which are supposed to furnish the grounds for the assigning of moral rights to them, as well as to any sufficiently similar beings, is bound to be futile; for even the capacity of humans to experience pain and pleasure falls short of complete universality, as we have just seen. But then if we shift our attention instead to capacities that are nearly or virtually universal among humans, as we are forced to do, it will be seen that humans generally possess them and (probably) no animals do and, hence, that the concept of a moral right to equitable treatment makes no sense except as applied to humans. AUTONOMY IS ESSENTIAL FOR RIGHTS Fox, Michael, Adjunct Professor at Queens University. “Animal Liberation: A Critique.” Ethics Vol. 88, No. 2 (Jan., 1978). I have drawn attention to certain cognitive capacities (critical self-awareness, concept manipulation, and the use of a sophisticated language) because these are the essential tools or vehicles by means of which an agent's autonomy. Regan assumes that the use of language is an uncomplicated phenomenon and that granting animals the same language capacities as humans is unproblematic. This is certainly empirically false, but it is also philosophically naive. As McCloskey points out, it is not just the capacity to use language that is involved when we refer to humans' linguistic endowment as a criterion for the assigning of rights; it is their capacity to use language "to express thoughts, decisions, wishes, choices." Ethics is evolved, made known to himself reflexively, and manifested or expressed. The possession of these cognitive capacities, therefore, is a necessary prerequisite for autonomy, which is the capacity for self-conscious, voluntary, and deliberate action, in the fullest sense of these words. Autonomy, which thus entails certain cognitive capacities, is necessary (and, together with the capacity to enjoy and suffer, sufficient) for the possession of moral rights. It follows that all (and only) those beings which are members of a species of which it is true in general (i.e., typically the case at maturity, assuming normal development) that members of the species in question can be considered autonomous agents are beings endowed with moral rights Whitman College Tournament 2009 42 File Title Treating animals well does not mean they should have rights OBLIGATIONS TO TREAT ANIMALS WELL DOESN’T PROVE THEY HAVE RIGHTS Cohen, Carl, Professor of Philosophy at the University of Michigan. 2001. The Animal Rights Debate. Oxford: Rowman and Littlefield Publishers. How, then, are rights and obligations related? When looked at from the viewpoint of one who holds a right and addresses the target of that right, they appear correlative. But they are plainly not correlative when looked at from the viewpoint of one who recognizes an obligation self-imposed, an obligation that does not stem from the rights of another. Your right to the money I owe you creates my obligation to pay it, of course. But many of my obligations to the needy, to my neighbors, to sentient creatures of every sort, have no foundation in their rights. The premise that rights and obligations are reciprocals, that every obligation flows from another’s right, is utterly false. It is inconsistent with our intuitive understanding of the difference between what we believe we ought to do and what others can justly demand we do. EVEN IF ANIMALS HAVE INTRINSIC VALUE, IT DOESN’T MEAN THEY HAVE RIGHTS. Fox, Michael, Adjunct Professor at Queens University. “Animal Liberation: A Critique.” Ethics Vol. 88, No. 2 (Jan., 1978). Let us assume, for the sake of argument, that it could be shown to everyone's satisfaction that animals experience pleasure and pain in the same way and to the same degree as humans and, further, that many also reason, have emotions, use some form of symbolic communication, and have a sense of self-identity. It still would not follow that these facts would qualify such animals to be recipients of moral rights. For, as H. J. McCloskey has recently pointed out, to appreciate (1) that the existence of certain higher animals is intrinsically valuable because they possess some capacities (like sentience, intelligence, emotionality), the exercise of which enables them to enjoy a quality of life that humans can recognize as of value, (2) that they are capable of suffering psychologically as well as physically, and, (3) that as a consequence of 1 and 2, good reasons are required to be given for killing such beings is not tantamount to, and does not entail, assigning animals moral rights. THE GREAT APE PROJECT PROVES HUMANS ARE MORALLY UNIQUE FROM CLOSEST RELATIVES Barilan, Y. Michael, Department of Behavioral Sciences at Tel Aviv University. “Speciesism as a Precondition to Justice.” Politics and the Life Sciences Vol. 23 No. 1 (March, 2004). The "Great Ape Project" (GAP), which is arguably the most ambitious animal-rights effort extant, demonstrates this point as well as the moral unsociability of even the most "human-like" animals. GAP campaigns for sanctuaries "where the needs, interests and rights of the apes come first." This vision implicitly admits to our inability to mix morally with apes. The project actually protects individual apes only from humanity, not from each other, not even from disease, whereas a truly recipient-dependent justice (El) would be blind to the sources of misfortune. Besides, GAP does not reckon with the welfare of other life forms, which the apes might abuse in the sanctuary or which might be disadvantaged by GAP on the apes' behalf. GAP is a speciesist project whose benefactors are apes, who are believed to be human-like. Ironically, if, indeed, proximity to being human is measured on a scale of moral sociability rather than on that of intelligence or physical characteristics, apes are not the most "human- like" animals. REJECTING ANIMAL RIGHTS DOES NOT MEAN REJECTING RIGHTS FOR INFANTS, SENILE PEOPLE… Cohen, Carl, Professor of Philosophy at the University of Michigan. 2001. The Animal Rights Debate. Oxford: Rowman and Littlefield Publishers. Objections of this kind are common but miss the point badly. They arise from a misunderstanding of what it means to say that humans live in a moral world. Human children, like elderly adults, have rights because they are human. Morality is an essential feature of human life; all humans are moral creatures, infants and the senile included. Rights are not doled out to this individual person of that one by somehow establishing the presence in them of some special capacity. This mistaken vision would result in the selective award of rights to some individuals but not others, and the cancellation of rights when capacities fail. On the contrary, rights are universally human, arise in the human realm, apply to humans generally. This criticism (suggesting the loss of rights by the senile or the comatose, etc.) mistakenly treats the essential moral feature of humanity as though it were a screen for sorting humans, which it most certainly is not. Whitman College Tournament 2009 43 File Title Rejecting Animal Rights Does Not Endorse Cruelty MISTREATING ANIMALS IS BAD, BUT NOT BECAUSE THEY HAVE RIGHTS. Fox, Michael, Adjunct Professor at Queens University. “Animal Liberation: A Critique.” Ethics Vol. 88, No. 2 (Jan., 1978). Undoubtedly animals should not be maltreated. They should not be made to suffer needlessly or excessively." Singer and Regan are surely correct to single out animals' capacity to suffer as the reason why we should treat them humanely. But it is no more clear how this extends moral rights to them than how our dawning ecological sense that we ought not to waste natural resources and systematically ravage the environment would establish moral rights for trees, lakes, or mineral deposits. What should be said is that we have an obligation to avoid mistreating animals, but that this is an obligation without a corresponding right on the part of the beings affected by our behavior. ANIMAL WELFARE IS NOT THE SAME AS ANIMAL RIGHTS Cohen, Carl, Professor of Philosophy at the University of Michigan. 2001. The Animal Rights Debate. Oxford: Rowman and Littlefield Publishers. Animal welfare is not at issue here. Basic care for animals is today a moral concern almost universally shared. Sentient animals must be treated with careful regard for the fact that they can feel pain; decent people will always exhibit that concern and will rightly insist that the animals we use be fed and housed properly, handled considerately. Regulations ensuring such humane treatment are not in dispute; they are entirely justified. ANIMAL WELFARE IS NOT THE SAME AS ANIMAL RIGHTS Francione, Gary L., Co-Director of the Rutgers Animal Rights Law Center. “Animal Rights: An Incremental Approach.” Animal Rights: The Changing Debate. Ed. Garner p. 44. The rights position is contrasted with the welfare position, which ‘generally holds that animals may be used for human benefit, or for the benefit of other animals, provided the animals are treated humanely. Animal welfare is couched in terms of obligations of humans to provide humane care and treatment of animals rather than interms of moral or legal rights of animals.’ The author adds that despite any ambiguity concerning the concept of animal rights, one thing is clear: ‘animal rights is not an extension of animal welfare’. ANIMAL PAIN SHOULD BE WEIGHED, BUT NOT WEIGHED EQUALLY. Cohen, Carl, Professor of Philosophy at the University of Michigan. 2001. The Animal Rights Debate. Oxford: Rowman and Littlefield Publishers. I certainly do not mean to suggest that the pain of animals is unworthy of consideration. Their pain is morally considerable, of course; animals are not machines. I note this again with emphasis. But in making a calculation of long-term utility, it is one thing to say that the pains of animals must be weighed, and another thing entirely to say that all animal and human pains must be weighed equally. Accepting the truth that lower animals are sentient surely does not oblige one to accept the liberationist conviction that animal experiences are morally equivalent to the experiences of humans. Whitman College Tournament 2009 44 File Title A2: Speciesism SPECIESISM IS DIFFERENT FROM RACISM, SEXISM Steinbock, Bonnie, Professor of Philosophy at the State University of New York—Albany. “Speciesism and the Idea of Equality.” Philosophy Vol. 53, No. 204 (1978). There is, however, an important difference between racism or sexism and 'speciesism'. We do not subject animals to different moral treatment simply because they have fur and feathers, but because they are in fact different from human beings in ways that could be morally relevant. It is false that women are incapable of being benefited by education, and therefore that claim cannot serve to justify preventing them from attending school. But this is not false of cows and dogs, even chimpanzees. Intelligence is thought to be a morally relevant capacity because of its relation to the capacity for moral responsibility. SPECIESISM IS THE CORRECT MORAL POSITION Cohen, Carl, Professor of Philosophy at the University of Michigan. 2001. The Animal Rights Debate. Oxford: Rowman and Littlefield Publishers. …in this sense speciesism, in spite of the overtones of the word, is a correct moral perspective, and by no means an error or corruption. We incorporate the different moral standing of different species into our overall moral views; we think it reasonable to put earthworms on fishhooks but not cats; we think it reasonable to eat the flesh of cows but not the flesh of humans. The realization of the sharply different moral standing of different species we internalize; that realization is not some shameful insensitivity but is rather an essential feature of any moral system that is plausible and rational. In the conduct of our day-to-day lives, we are constantly making decisions and acting on these moral differences among species. When we think clearly and judge fairly, we are all speciesists, of course. SPECIESISM IS NOT PARALLEL TO RACISM Cohen, Carl, Professor of Philosophy at the University of Michigan. 2001. The Animal Rights Debate. Oxford: Rowman and Littlefield Publishers. Racism is evil because humans really are equal, and the assumption that some races are superior to others is false and groundless. Giving advantages to some humans over others on the basis of skin color is outrageous…But among the species of animate life—between humans and rats, between dogs and sea urchins—the morally relevant differences are enormous, and almost universally appreciated. Sea urchins have no brains whatever, while dogs have very powerful brains. Humans engage in moral reflection, while rats are somewhat foreign to that enterprise. Humans are members of moral communities, recognizing just claims even when those claims work against their own interests. Human beings have rights by nature, and those rights do give humans a moral status very different from that of sea urchins, rats, or dogs. NO BRIGHTLINE FOR WHICH ANIMALS GET RIGHTS Cohen, Carl, Professor of Philosophy at the University of Michigan. 2001. The Animal Rights Debate. Oxford: Rowman and Littlefield Publishers. The octopi, on a very different evolutionary branch, are no “higher” than insects on the phylogenetic scale, although they have nervous systems, the apparent capacity to solve simple problems, and probably subjective experience of a kind sufficient to count them as “subjects-of-a-life”—in which case they would (on Regan’s view) have rights demanding respect. But the octopi are mollusks, and if some mollusks have rights other mollusks are surely entitled to the same regard—which would expand the realm of rights-holders to include the billions of tiny krill that populate the polar oceans, millions of which, every day, lose any rights they might have had to the great whales which consume them by the ton Whitman College Tournament 2009 45 File Title A2: Speciesism continued ANIMAL RIGHTS ADVOCATES USE EMOTIONAL PLOYS AND SELECTIVE EMPHASIS Richard Posner, 7th Circuit Court of Appeals, “Animal Rights Debate Between Peter Singer and Richard Posner.” Slate. http://www.utilitarian.net/singer/interviews-debates/200106--.htm, Accessed 7/14/10 You say that some readers of Animal Liberation have been persuaded by the ethical arguments in the book, and not just by the facts and the pictures. But if so, it is probably so only because these readers do not realize the radicalism of the ethical vision that powers your view on animals, an ethical vision that finds greater value in a healthy pig than in a profoundly retarded child, that commands inflicting a lesser pain on a human being to avert a greater pain to a dog, and that, provided only that a chimpanzee has 1 percent of the mental ability of a normal human being, would require the sacrifice of the human being to save 101 chimpanzees. If Animal Liberation had emphasized these implications of your utilitarian philosophy, it would have had many fewer persuaded readers; and likewise if it had sought merely to persuade our rational faculty, and not to stir our empathetic regard for animals. PETER SINGER IS A JERK Roger Scrunton, Visiting Professor of Philosophy at Oxford University, “Animal Rights.” http://www.cityjournal.org/html/10_3_urbanities-animal.html, accessed 7/14/10. Meanwhile, Princeton University's Center for the Study of Human Values has appointed the Australian philosopher Peter Singer, author of the seminal Animal Liberation (1975), to a prestigious chair, causing widespread disgust on account of Singer's vociferous support for euthanasia. (Defenders of animal rights not infrequently also advocate the killing of useless humans.) Singer's works, remarkably for a philosophy professor, contain little or no philosophical argument. They derive their radical moral conclusions from a vacuous utilitarianism that counts the pain and pleasure of all living things as equally significant and that ignores just about everything that has been said in our philosophical tradition about the real distinction between persons and animals SINGER AND REGAN ARE RADICALS AND DISREGARD THE COMMON-SENSE ASPECT OF THE USE OF ANIMALS The American Physiological Society 2006 http://www.the-aps.org/pa/animals/quest2.html Singer, Regan, and others have used explanations of animal rights to win agreement with their belief that human beings should not use animals. However, this is a radical notion, given all the ways that human beings are dependent upon animals for life and livelihood. A more common-sense approach is to recognize that there are compelling reasons to use animals for medical research and other purposes, and at the same time to affirm our obligation to treat animals with compassion.