Magic, Science and Religion Part II, Lecture 6 The Rationality of Primitive Thought 1. Two conceptions of rationality Jon Elster distinguishes between the ‘thin’ and ‘broad’ theories of rationality. (i) Thin rationality: formal consistency between systems of belief, systems of desires and actions. (ii) Broad rationality: Rationality of substantive beliefs and desires. To be rational these should be based on the available evidence and should involve rational judgement. 2. Evans-Pritchard and the rationality of the Azande We may see EP as saying that the Azande are thinly rational, broadly rational, and broadly irrational when it comes to their beliefs in witchcraft, oracles and magic. 3. Universality of ‘thin’ rationality? Is it the case, then, that all societies possess the ‘thin’ conception of rationality? Winch argues that something like this must be the case: ‘Rationality is not just a concept in a language like any other; it is this too, for, like any other concept it must be circumscribed by an established use: a use, that is, established in language. But I think it is not a concept that a language may, as a matter of fact, have and equally well may not have, as is, for instance, the concept of politeness. It is a concept necessary to the existence of any language: to say of a society that it has a language is also to say that it has a concept of rationality’ (‘Understanding a Primitive Society’, p. 99). ‘Rationality’ may then be thought to be a feature of all natural languages as without it language could not convey meanings (which is what we usually understand to be its main function) consistent with our beliefs about the world and our desires. What implications does this have for our understanding of other cultures? How is translation of an alien language possible? W. V. O. Quine, claimed that we could never be certain that our translations of other languages captures the meanings held by the language speakers (‘indeterminacy of translation’) while Donald Davidson defended the thesis of ‘radical interpretation’ and the ‘principle of charity’. 4. The ‘broad’ rationality of primitive societies? In some respects, Winch is sympathetic to EP. But he points to a number of problems with this approach. First problem – EP suggests that scientific notions are superior to mystical notions because they are ‘in accord with objective reality’. Scientific notions can be checked by reference to an independent reality, with what really exists. But for Winch: 1 (i) It is not just scientific notions that check themselves against an independent reality. For religion, god(s) can be understood as independently real, real beyond our belief in him (them); (ii) ‘Reality is not what gives language sense. What is real and unreal shows itself in the sense that language has’ (p. 82). The use of the concepts of the real and unreal occur in language and only in language. For Winch, the Zande’s system of belief operates in much the same way that a modern science like particle physics does. That is, it is an internally coherent body of beliefs about a reality that is constructed by it and which checks itself against that reality. Again, Winch is not interested here in the question of whether what these different bodies of knowledge say exist does ‘really’ exist. Rather, why should we consider internally coherent systems of belief that clearly play a social role of some significance (as witchcraft beliefs do in Zande society and scientific beliefs in western societies) to be ‘irrational’ or ‘wrong’? 5. The problem of the broad conception of rationality Available evidence and rational judgement: what counts as evidence what counts as a rational judgement? i. ‘Available evidence’ is not given. What is to count as ‘available’ depends on the kinds of evidence that the system of beliefs admits as relevant. ii. From Winch’s point of view, there can be no ‘autonomous’ rational judgements. All judgements are made within language according to a system of beliefs. 6. Rationality/ Relativism The kind of argument that Winch puts forward worries some people because it is an example of relativism. In other words, Winch appears to make our judgements of the world a function of our beliefs without providing us with any means of determining whether our beliefs are true or false. In the end, truth appears as a product of the beliefs we possess and the social relations that generate them. But should we be worried? 2