Adapting financial rationality: Is a New Paradigm Emerging? Mona Soufian1, William Forbes2, Robert Hudson3 1Newcastle 2School Business School, Northumbria University of Business and Economics, Loughborough University 3Newcastle University Business School, Newcastle University 1 Abstract We discuss the implications of an alternative to the efficient market hypothesis (EMH) the adaptive market hypothesis (AMH). The AMH may give a theoretical basis for a new financial paradigm which can better model such phenomena as the recent financial crisis. The AMH regards the financial market order as evolving, tentative and defined by creative destruction in which trading strategies are introduced, mutate to survive or face abandonment. The concept of investor rationality is less helpful than the distinction between investment strategies which are more or less well adapted to the prevailing market environment in which they are deployed. We outline how a more systematic and grounded basis for behavioural finance can be developed in line with the later approach. Based on this we develop testable hypotheses allowing the AMH to be distinguished from the EMH. Finally we discuss how the AMH can aid our understanding of important issues in finance. A crucial feature is that in the survival of richest, as opposed to fittest, implied by the AMH there is much room for misallocation of resources as price and value uncouple. In this evolution of the financial market order the regulatory State features as a further market in which the vote market verifies or disrupts settled market conditions. Acknowledgements We would like to acknowledge very insightful and helpful comments by the editor and three anonymous referees on an earlier draft of this paper which have considerably improved the work. 2 1. Introduction The recent global financial crisis has dealt a huge and largely unanticipated shock to the world economy. The Queen of England surely expressed the thoughts of much of the world’s population in November 2008 when she asked in a visit to the London School of Economics why no one had seen the crisis coming. We believe the fundamental answer to her question lies in the dominance of the neoclassical financial paradigm. A few far-sighted people had seen problems ahead but were largely ignoredi. The idea that markets rationally price assets and risk was so entrenched amongst influential academics, practitioners, regulators and politicians that dissenting views were completely marginalised. Recent years have seen an almost continuous succession of financial crises including the emerging markets crisis of the late 1990s, LTCM, the bursting of the ‘dot com’ bubble, the accounting scandals at Enron and Worldcom, cumulating in the near collapse of the global banking system in 2008 and on going problems with sovereign debt. As Hyman Minksy (1986) has taught us financial crises are a recurring theme of economic history. What is so disturbing is the escalating frequency and intensity of the crises we now observe. Galbraith (1990, p viii) states the case thus “Recurrent speculative insanity and the associated financial deprivation and larger devastation are, I am persuaded, inherent in the system. Perhaps it is better this can be recognised and accepted.” Recently Ferguson (2012) has portrayed the 2008 Crisis as a critical point in a “great degeneration” of Western capitalist economises as they enter a “stationary state” characterised by the rule of law being replaced by the rule of lawyers and an intense rent-seeking amongst market participants for shares of a pie that has ceased to grow or has even entered decline. Mainstream finance theory has clearly failed to anticipate, or even convincingly explain, the recent crises. Indeed to a large extent it might be considered to have caused them by giving intellectual authority to the ideal of unrestrained financial markets and dogmatically suppressing dissenting views. There seems a vital need to address this situation with new research programmes to better model reality. In the terms of Kuhn’s seminal work on the structure of scientific revolutions the crises are anomalies; that is a failure of the current 3 paradigm to take into account observed phenomena (Kuhn, 1962). An accumulation of anomalies eventually leads to a change of paradigm. The current crisis may act as the breakpoint enabling serious consideration of different theoretical approaches. Perhaps we can finally now accept the cyclical nature of financial crises and move on to explaining the function they serve. Periods of trauma and destruction may intensify the speed at which differentiation based on evolutionary fitness proceeds. This suggests seeking to build financial institutions that can withstand further crises may be a misplaced effort. It may be better to try to put in place bank resolution procedures that are both easily triggered and avoid capable of protecting the taxpayer’s purse. Taleb (2012) identifies a category of trader/entrepreneurs who thrive of volatile, if not destructive times. Such innovators are “antifragile” in the sense that they enter their own in periods when pressures to survive are there most intense. As one would expect a crisis of the magnitude we are experiencing has given rise to enormous debate. There have been hundreds of popular and academic articles and books on the subjectii. Different authors have emphasised different perspectives. Much of the popular coverage has personalised the issues. Often individuals have become scapegoats for behaviour they personify, for example Richard Fuld, Sean Fitzpatrick and Fred Goodwin, the CEOs who presided over the demise of Lehman Brothers, Anglo-Irish, and the need for the government rescue of RBS, respectively. A simple assertion that we have a flawed and greedy banking culture is now commonplace as a result. Whilst it is surely prudent to rapidly address particular flaws in financial practices and regulations much of the post crisis response has been very piecemeal and ad-hoc in nature. This type of response is inevitable given the evident lack of an appropriate and credible theoretical basis to inform policy. The deficit in theory has been recognised even in some essentially practical and hard-headed assessments of the crisis. This is one of the primary insights of the UK's Turner Review into the failure of regulatory authorities to head off the burgeoning securitised debt crisis (Turner, 2009). Turner concludes (Turner, 2009, pp 85) “the conventional wisdom relating to the global financial system – that risks had been diversified – was widely accepted and was wrong”. If the ability to diversify as a risk reduction strategy now looks tarnished in the face of systemic risk then the very 4 fundamentals of received professional wisdom are in doubt. In a related review of the UK’s equity market’s John Kay explicitly demures from a view (Kay, 2012), that “public policy should proceed as if these ‘irrational’ behaviours did not exist: such an approach would not be consistent with the fundamental goals of performing high performance companies.” This insight echoes Jean-Claude Trichet’s (Governor of ECB) view that many of the economic models used by advisors during the financial crisis (Trichet, 2010) “seemed incapable of explaining what is happening in the economy in a convincing manner.” Thus the EMH seems to have been discarded as the basis of sound public policy and the race is now on to gain acceptance of a credible alternative. The AMH could become such an alternative source of guidance. In this paper we question the core assumption of the EMH which is the ‘rationality’ of economic agentsiii. Following Gigerenzer et al (2003) we argue that true evolved rationality emerges when the response when investors’ cognition is a good match to the demands of the environment in which they find themselves trading. The distinction here is between the investment strategy and its cognitive and external context, as opposed to a proposed statistical property which is conjectured to prevail regardless of context or cognition. Based on the above, in this paper we discuss directions for future research which offer some hope to build a more persuasive and useful theorisation of financial decision-making. Initially we propose replacement of the concept of the Efficient Markets Hypothesis (EMH) that financial markets always act to set prices ‘rationally’ by an understanding that prices change as investors’ constantly adapt their behaviour as markets evolve their own internal order. The latter process is known as the Adaptive Markets Hypothesis (AMH) and was initially proposed by Lo (2004, 2005). The AMH recognises the importance of behavioural finance and was partly designed to offer a way to reconcile this emergent literature with the mainstream. Our second, and complimentary, proposal is to work towards a more systematic and theoretically grounded basis for behavioural finance, building on the work of Herbert Simon on bounded rationality, and the research programme of Gigerenzer on heuristics. At the moment behavioural finance is somewhat fragmented from a theoretical point of view and can be criticised as often being an arbitrary catalogue of observed departures from rationality without a unifying theoretical vision to explain those anomalies. 5 Rebuilding financial theory is a huge task and it would be naive to over-commit to a specific way forward at this stage. However, the research agenda we propose is far from exclusive in scope. The AMH is much less theoretically restrictive than the existing paradigm in that it recognises the possibility of a wide range of responses by players in the markets rather than taking a particular view of investor rationality as axiomatic. An advantage of the approach is that it may reconcile understandings from various research traditions, including neo-classical economics, behavioural finance and psychology. modelling approaches. It can also accommodate different This is important as the rapid development of computing is introducing radically new research tools such as the direct modelling of economic agents (agent-based modelling). These can be characterised as a ‘bottom-up’ approaches as they focus on the behaviour of the individual agents in the market and then aggregate this behaviour to deduce the implications for the overall market. This is, of course, a largely meaningless activity within the neo-classical world as the agents are axiomatically assumed to be both homogeneous and rational, according to the normative construction of the “representative agent” model. In contrast to the agent-based approach most research to date, both neo-classical and behavioural, takes a modelling approach that can be characterised as being ‘top-down’ with an emphasis on observing movements in the prices of financial instruments rather than the underlying behaviour of market participants. In general, the motivation of the participants cannot be directly observed. This creates difficulties for practitioners of behavioural finance as motivations can only be deduced from indirect evidence. From a methodological point of view it would be premature to definitely favour the new agent-based approaches over much more established methods but equally it would be foolish to reject them out of hand. They certainly permit the testing of hypotheses that relate much more directly to the behaviour and motivations of individual market participants. While the AMH seems like a radical new departure to standard finance theorists evolutionary theory has a history of use within transaction cost perspectives on both the development of corporate organisational form and governance structures operating within any chosen form (Nelson and Winter, 1982). This evolutionary theory of economic change shifted the analytical focus from managers maximising a given objective of profits, or sales, etc, to the selection of “routines” appropriate to a fluctuating and uncertain environment. 6 Rather than invoking calculus to solve for implicit maxima the evolutionary perspective favours processes, such as markov-switching processes, for rotating across alternative “routines”, selected to fit the trading environment the company faces. Such routines include “well specified technical routines for producing things, … research and development or advertising and business strategies about product diversification and overseas investment.” (Nelson and Winter, 1982, p 14). In tranquil times old established routines are likely to remain unchallenged and comfortably embedded. But in more turbulent periods, rapid technological, or regulatory, change induces threats to survival requiring major revisions to the set of routines adopted. In such critical periods, as Nelson and Winter (1982, p 58) state “it is more natural to represent large scale motivational forces as a kind of persistent pressure on decisions, a pressure to which the response is sluggish, halting and sometimes inconsistent…. an … evolutionary purging of motives that diverge excessively from survival requirements.” However, within these bounds, imposed by the need to survive, established, comfortable, if sub-optimal, routines abound. So while within the Nelson and Winter (1982) schema environmental changes initiate switches in prevailing routines. Realised learning (RL) methods characterise routine rotations as emerging from the diffusion of individual successful adaptions through a broader investment community. The evolutionary perspective on organisational form reflects a much older interest in the analogy between economic and biological processes which dates back to Bernard Madiville’s satirical sonnet “The Fable of the Bees” (1714) where the Bee hive mimics the market by allowing the struggle for individual survival (or private vices) to produce a perfect, if brutal, social order (of questionable public virtue). Indeed Charles Darwin was much inspired in conceiving of “The Origin of Species” by Robert Malthus’s “Essay on the Principle of Population” suggesting Economics and the life sciences shared a common analytical frame in much the same way as Econophysics marries finance and the natural sciences now (Ferguson, 2012 p 63). In the next section of the paper, Section 2, we initially outline the background to current mainstream theory with its emphasis on perfect rationality and follow this with a discussion of an alternative approach which assumes that rationality is bounded and the resulting implications of this for our proposed conceptual approach. The remainder of the paper is 7 structured as follows: Section 3 reviews the Adaptive Expectations Hypothesis (AMH) followed by an examination of the role of bounded rationality in recent theoretical developments and considers how the AMH may be tested using ‘top-down’ approaches. Section 4 examines how a more systematic and theoretically grounded basis for behavioural finance can be developed. The internal and external bounds on financial decision-making are examined in sub-section 4.1. Heuristics and adaptive behaviour are examined in sub-section 4.2, followed by discussions on satisficing and investor heterogeneity in sub-section 4.3. Finally, sub-section 4.4 outlines a tentative modelling strategy for an evolutionary perspective on financial innovation based on agent-based modelling. The various sub- sections of Section 4 imply testable hypotheses, allowing us to distinguish the predictive power of the AMH from the EMH using the ‘bottom-up’ methods associated with agentbased modelling. Section 5 considers some practical examples of how the AMH and EMH differ by considering some current areas of finance research. The paper concludes with overall remarks and suggestions for future work in Section 6. 2. Background 2.1 Mainstream Theory and Perfect Rationality The classical assumptions of Finance theory are broadly that individuals are rational, seek to maximise the expected utility of their wealth, are risk averse and follow the tenets of subjective probability. Capital markets in turn are perfect and generate financial returns which are not predictable. Despite broad critiques, not least in this journal, (see, for example, Hudson et al, 1999; Keasey and Hudson, 2007; Hudson and Maioli, 2010; Shiller, 2000; Clarkeson, 2009; Krugman, 2009 and Akerlof and Shiller, 2009) this mainstream approach has remained very dominant. There are reasons for this rigidity, all the elite finance departments and academic journals are overwhelmingly dominated by scholars steeped in the mainstream approach (see Whitley, 1986 and Fox, 2010 for accounts of the rise of this dominance). In addition, the mainstream approach is very closely allied to the philosophical belief that free markets are the best way to allocate resources. This was almost a point of patriotic faith in the US during the Cold War era when mainstream finance was developed and certainly an easy and powerful argument to make after the collapse of the Soviet Union. However, it may be that, like reason itself, markets are a good servant but 8 a poor master. Below we discuss the concept of rationality as employed in mainstream theory and then outline how the concept has become so associated with free market policies. The standard notion of rationality employed by economists is that of purposive rationality. There are no value judgements of the desired ends simply whether the methods used to achieve them are optimal. This notion lends itself to logical axioms which can be used to determine rationality. For example, in his seminal multi-million copy selling text book, Paul Samuelson, often considered the most influential post war economist, codified four principles of rationality: completeness, transitivity, non-satiation and convexity (Samuelson, 1948, p45)iv. From this viewpoint the human being is seen as a utility maximising, calculating machine (or “Laplacean Demon”) which raises obvious difficulties once we reflect upon studies of actual human behaviour or merely our own social observation. Even Kenneth Arrow, a Nobel Prize winning economist whose work is synonymous with the logical analysis of economic issues, admitted that human beings could not be rational in this sense (Arrow, 1986). In practice the notion of rationality described above is often blurred in the literature around financial markets with the prominence of the concept that financial markets are rational in the sense that they produce the best social outcome. In much of the literature dealing with finance the various notions of rationality are used in a rather cavalier and inter-changeable manner often to make the rhetorical point that free markets are the best (and most rational) way to allocate resources. For clarity in this paper we try to distinguish precisely what we mean by rationality. The academic theory most strongly justifying the approach of leaving allocative decisions to the market is the EMH. The history of the development of the EMH is very revealing and can be seen as not a disinterested scientific endeavour but one strongly influenced by ideological considerations and the need to preserve the core methodological approaches of neo-classical economics (see Fox, 2010, for an excellent account of its development). In broad terms, by the 1950s mainstream economics had largely adopted the still dominant neo-classical approach based on utility maximisation by rational agents. The methodology of this approach draws very heavily on deterministic optimisation methods similar to those 9 used in classical (pre – quantum theory) natural sciences such as physics and chemistry. Paul Samuelson in particular drew heavily on methods from thermodynamics in his writings (see Samuelson, 1986). Securities markets were problematic within this framework. In popular discourse their behaviour had long been a byword for irrationality and the random nature of their behaviour was becoming mathematically formalised by the early 1960s (see, for example, Kendall, 1953; Mandlebrot, 1963; Cootner, 1964). Samuelson rose to the challenge and wrote an ingenious article seemingly squaring the circle by reconciling randomness with rationality (Samuelson, 1965). The very title of the article ‘Proof that Properly Anticipated Prices Fluctuate Randomly’ and the liberal use of mathematics in the article gave an air of dispassionate scientific rigor to the exercise. The reasoning in the article is in fact very straightforward and superficially persuasive. Since it is hard to predict stock prices then surely they incorporate all available information and therefore are rationally determined. It is hard to overestimate the influence of this argument on subsequent financial theory and practice. A very substantial body of academic work was seen as supportive of Samuelson’s view. This work was built up by a number of scholars through the 1960s. The general research pattern was to find empirical evidence that prices were hard to predict by some metric and then tacitly or explicitly assume that this showed that prices were properly anticipated. The scholar that is most closely associated with this enterprise is Eugene Fama of the University of Chicago which personified fervent support of free markets and positive economics. Fama developed the term ‘efficient markets’. In 1965 in an article in the Financial Analysts Journal he wrote “In an efficient market, however, the actions of the many competing participants should cause the actual price of a security to wander randomly about its intrinsic value” Fama (1965, p56). But the meaning of randomness was left unclear and thus left open to opportunistic use by EMH advocates in later discussion (Mlodinow, 2008, p 84-85). One interpretation of randomness is that any of the conceivable outcomes are equally likely, rain or shine for example. This meaning to the word is sometimes termed the frequency interpretation of randomness. Another is that rain or shine are not equally likely but I cannot predict which will occur with any reasonable degree of accuracy. This is sometimes termed the subjective definition of randomness. The frequency interpretation judges the randomness of the sample ex-post, by the frequency of outcomes. But the subjective interpretation of 10 randomness judges its presence ex-ante by simply asking whether I could know if it will rain tomorrow or not. Flipping between these meanings gives EMH advocates considerable scope for avoiding unwelcome refutations of their preferred theory. Fama subsequently continued to refine the Efficient Markets Hypothesis to classify different types of efficiency (Fama, 1970). The term ‘efficient market’ was a brilliantly persuasive choice of words. Efficiency is one of the highest social values in the West and generally assumed to be a good thing, albeit that in the context efficiency is given a meaning far different from its normal usage. People who are not scholars of finance invariably and understandably assume that an efficient market refers to the operational efficiency of market trading, for example, how fast or how cheaply trades can be processed. The main achievement, and perhaps purpose, of the efficient market project was, however, to show that intrinsic value and market value of traded assets were one and the same with profound implications. If market prices are a perfect guide to intrinsic value the market can then be taken as an infallible guide to human affairs. This view of the world is aptly summed up by mathematician David Orrell who describes the market under the EMH as “..some kind of hyper-rational being that can outwit any speculator or government regulator” (Orrell, p 265). Only a few mavericks have raised dissenting voices against the EMH project. Many years before our present difficulties Robert Shiller pointed out a basic logical mistake in this reasoning. Just because prices are difficult to predict it does not imply that they are rational in the sense that they represent intrinsic value. Unpredictability is a necessary but not sufficient condition for market prices to be rational. “This argument for the efficient markets hypothesis represents one of the most remarkable errors in the history of economic thought. It is remarkable in the immediacy of its logical error and in the sweep and implications of its conclusion” (Shiller, 1984, p. 459). Shiller’s critique, however, has largely fallen on deaf ears and the mainstream view remains dominant. There has been much institutionalised inertia in the research approaches adopted within Finance. Findlay and Williams (1985) argue that in conventional Finance the positivist assertion that ‘‘assumptions do not matter if the model works’ has been subverted into the notion that assumptions cannot be criticised so long as the model cannot be shown not to 11 work’’. In the relatively benign US financial environment between 1950 and the late 1990s, the years of the “great moderation”, it was hard to show that the mainstream model was clearly not working, despite the short sharp shock of the 1987 market crash. But in the subsequent, more tumultuous, years its shortcomings have become transparent. It is untenable to argue that the stock market in the dot-com years, or the US housing and financial market in the run up to the financial crisis in 2008, were acting in an way that reflected underlying intrinsic values. Even Alan Greenspan, the well known advocate of free markets and the Federal Reserve Chairman from 1987 to 2006, was forced to admit in testimony to a House of Representative Committee that his pro-market ideology was flawed (Greenspan, 2008). The development of finance theory is certainly not merely an “academic” issue in the pejorative sense that few outside the academy know or care about such developments. In a now well developed body of work Donald MacKenzie has illustrated the “performative” nature of modern finance theory and especially the Black-Scholes-Merton option pricing theory and the portfolio insurance schemes that the formula underpinned (MacKenzie, 2004, 2006 (a) and (b)). While the Black-Scholes-Merton model was “performative” in the sense of moving the quoted price of options to be more like those implied by the model it also embedded the possibility of a “counter-performative” pricing distortions. This counterperformative feature of options pricing theory was perhaps most dramatically revealed by the October 1987 Crash. Portfolio insurance, undertaken by creating “synthetic puts” in the form of sell orders against the futures’ index contract, created positive feedback when sales of the spot market contract became too heavy for the futures contract price to be speedily constructed and quoted. Large sell orders were greatly amplified once effective hedging of downside risk was nullified because market-makers were either unwilling or unable to execute investors’ trades. Finance theory is rarely tested for validity upon data unaffected by its own development. Rather the role of finance theory as an “engine not a camera” (MacKenzie, 2004) means financial theories often create new market realities which the theory was not initially designed to describe or understand. 2.2 Bounded Rationality and its Incorporation into a New Conceptual Framework 12 For some years there has been on going work into the implications of relaxing the mainstream assumptions about the behaviour of individuals (see Daniel et al, 2002). Recent events add impetus to these efforts and raise many more questions about the realism of current mainstream approaches to finance. The recent global financial crisis has certainly encouraged some scholars to re-examine the foundations upon which economics and finance are based. Mallard (2011), among others, challenges the assumption of perfect rationality in reviewing recent developments in modelling bounded rationality. As discussed above, mainstream finance theory relies on the assumption of perfect rationality of market participants and hence it is obvious that this is necessary for markets to be efficient. However, the existence of efficient markets is not consistent with empirical evidence. Evidence of departures from efficiency include the high volatility of asset prices and apparent over-reaction and under reaction in the stock markets (see early studies by, for example, Shiller, 1981 and De Bondt and Thaler, 1985). In the growing behavioural finance literature departures from market efficiency are generally attributed to behavioural biases amongst investors. Much of the mainstream approach is tacitly retained in that investors are assumed to have purposive rationality and departures from the fully rational behaviour in the mainstream models are due to the biases and cognitive limitations of the individuals involved in executing their purpose. Thus most work in behavioural finance has tended to focus on the bounded rationality of individuals leading to departures from the optimum solution given by the mainstream model. Other approaches to investigating bounded rationality offer more positive assessments of alternatives to perfect rationality and its offspring the EMH. This has been reflected in the recent development of the AMH combining Simon’s notion of bounded rationality (Simon, 1955) and evolutionary cognitive theories (see Lo, 2004, 2011). The investigation of bounded rationality is also the central theme of Gert Gigerenzer’s research programme which has provided a better understanding of modelling heuristic decision-making. Gigerenzer’s heuristic studies (1996, 2009, 2011) show that by employing specifically chosen heuristics agents/investors can make accurate, fast decisions while expending little effort in the decision-making process. 13 We advance a general conceptual framework that incorporates bounds on both an individual's internal cognition and the external environment within which it is formed. Our discussion considers how rationality emerges from the dynamic interplay between individual internal cognition and its external environment. Environments are constructed and shaped by the cognition of decision-makers who act within them. This process envisages an evolutionary chain in which heuristics arise, mutate and thrive, or die out, according to the progeny they yield. Successful heuristics/mental frames may become entrenched amongst a wealthy trading elite, while others become marginalised to a dwindling impoverished few, only to to be reborn in some new guise. A moment’s reflection on the history of chartism/technical trading, now reborn in the guise of high-frequency trading, reflects this evolutionary thread (Lo and Hasanhodzic, 2010). Similar evolutionary mechanisms to those we observe in the natural world are also observed in our social and economic lives. But crucially no one person observes all the changing heuristics and the role of the price system is then to transmit a diverse range of value signals no single investor can possess. A primary benefit of heuristic driven choices is that no one pretends they are either optimal or anything other than expedient. Hence discarding them in the face of a preferred alternative is fairly costless and unproblematic (Taleb, 2012, p 11). We argue that a true evolved rationality emerges when the response from investors is a good match to the demands of the environment in which they find themselves trading. Heuristics aid increasingly rational/optimal choice by investors in a stable trading environment. But financial markets rarely remain stable and fractures in the external environment rarely leave existing mental-frames pre-eminent, or perhaps even prominent, for long. Hence the norm for financial markets is the fluctuation of partially adopted failing, or retrieved and recycled, mental frames which allow a partial rationalisation of the market setting. In order for investors to adapt their decisions using heuristic devices it is crucial to match the joint effect of the structure of their internal cognitions to their environment. This alignment can be compared to two blades of a pair of scissors (Newall and Simon, 1972, p 55). The first blade represents the agent’s internal cognition (the heuristic mechanism/framing) while the second blade captures the market environment. An appropriate conjunction of an investor's mental frame and the environment induces boundedly rational behaviour. The constraints in our environment support the development 14 of simple strategies, using heuristics/frames that exploit the benefits/constraints on offer as opportunities and guides. Such fast and frugal decision-making is suitable for an evolved and still evolving market order. But this evolved order is rarely grasped by any single intelligence, as Hayek states (1973, p 49-50) “...The more complex the order aimed at, the greater will be that part of separate actions which will have to be determined by circumstances not known to those who direct the whole, and the more dependent control will be on rules rather than specific commands.” Hence investors must always choose an investment strategy based on partial, imperfect and fragmented information recognising that competing traders, with their own flawed cognition, do the same. A constantly revised, revolving, set of heuristics enable an organic order to emerge but equally allow for it to dissemble until a new transient order prevails. Even skills acquired by continuous interaction with others, with all its punishments and rewards, are often wrongly rationalised as deriving from our individual skill or talent (Smith, 2008, p 8). If heuristics/frames can truly aid decision-making the question arises as to when and why do some heuristics perform well for investors while others prove misleading or even harmful? The evolution of a bounded rationality, selected for fitness of purpose in some particular market context, is a focus of this paper. A conceptual framework is developed that incorporates internal and external bounds upon rational choice, building upon the key characteristics of bounded rationality. Three key characteristics are taken into account in modelling bounded rationality. These are (a) the evolution of heuristics and mental-frames by adaptive decision-making, (b) the impact of investor heterogeneity, and, finally, (c) the concept of investor satisficing implied by bounded rationality. We show bounded rationality provides a promising perspective for refining the foundations of the AMH in an age when theory and practice have so wildly diverged and finance theory is deemed unhelpful for evaluating policy reform. Financial markets are subject to uncertainty, risk and ever changing events; these aspects make such markets a particularly interesting field to examine market participants’ behaviour and decision-making processes. Financial innovation has often increased such uncertainty in financial markets. The multiple triggers for recapitalisation of Special Purpose Entities (SPE’s), which housed securitised debt, or its division into tranches, illustrate this trend. Price/quantity choices are made by investors within a trading environment itself in a 15 constant state of flux. A theory of expectation formation is a crucial part of any theory of investment and asset pricing. Most theories in finance rely on the assumption that investors form rational expectations. Professors Christopher Sims and Thomas Sargent were awarded the Nobel Prize in 2011 for contributions to this work. In this area rationality is usually held to imply an evaluation of risky outcomes in conformity with the von Neumann-Morgenstern axioms. These axioms imply agents consistently rank alternative risk outcomes/gambles based on an accurate projection of probability weighted future cash-flows. These axioms are themselves largely a normative theory of how decisions should be made in uncertain environments rather than providing a positive theory of how they are made. To quote Vernon Smith, the 2002 Nobel Prize winner (2008, p. xv) “Practitioners are into problem solving and do not relate naturally to discussions driven by economic theory...but they can appreciate working models when they see and experience them.” As discussed above, despite the clear behavioural biases of investors standard finance commonly invokes perfect “rationality” in the sense described by the von NeumannMorgenstern axioms. 3. The AMH as an alternative framework to perfect rationality, and its implementation This section reviews a recent alternative to the EMH’s assumption of perfect individual rationality and the role of bounded rationality in the development of this theory and its implementation. Behavioural finance attempts to provide evidence that the market is not efficient and that market participants are not rational. Many empirical findings indeed jar with standard Finance theory. Investors tend to overreact to private information signals and under-react to public information signals, such as earnings announcements (Bernard and Thomas, 1990). Stock market overreaction and consequent longer-run mean-reversion are foundational findings for the behavioural perspective on investment. Further, the equity premium puzzle, of equity's relatively high return as an asset class, remains puzzling even after the on going financial crisis has partially dented its edge (Mehra and Prescott, 2008). 16 To date, however, no integrated theory of investment behaviour to rival standard theory has yet emerged. As critics state behavioural finance can often seem a rag bag of ad hoc models to explain individual anomalies with no overarching structure (see, for example, Fama, 1998). One attempt to develop such an integrating framework is the AMH (Lo, 2004). While such models are currently in their infancy, they provide hope of salvaging the best of the efficient markets theorem while excising some of that theory’s worst follies. AMH explains loss aversion, overreaction and other behavioural biases by the fact that investors react to a changing market environment by invoking new heuristics/mental frames. The processes of learning, heuristics management and adaptive decision-making are central to AMH. Accordingly individual agents are regarded as not perfectly, but rather boundedly, rational or “satisficers”. Hence a rational decision is always evolving, in construction and contention as mental schemata are invoked, adapted for purpose, and discarded as market conditions change. Hence we cannot understand market outcomes through the eyes of one representative investor. Rather it is the very exchange, rejection and promulgation of mental frames upon valuation that evolves the market condition we observe at any given point (Lo, 2004, p. 21). Investors satisfy, as opposed to optimise, by truncating search at varying points, trading and observing the consequences. Great, or perhaps just lucky, traders choose good truncation points and come to dominate the market, poor traders truncate their search too early or too late and are eased out of the market. But this difference can only be observed after the event with successful traders’ confidence being fuelled by the downfall of their peers. Trading strategies, high-frequency, contrarian, etc. can be thought of as mutating species within an overall market ecology. The growing weight of money flowing towards the favoured mental frame earns a declining rate of return restarting the cycle of mental frame selection, via the search for yield in a Darwinian selection process in which trading species grow, mutate and thrive or face extinction. In this process there are no fixed valuation rules, but rather an array of constantly recycled and sometimes outdated market plays of temporary opportunistic use. Market plays are here neither rational nor irrational, but rather adapted or maladapted to the context within which they are deployed. So trading profits guide the evolving chain of market strategies, “By viewing economic profits as the ultimate food source on which 17 market participants depend for their survival, the dynamics of market interactions and financial innovation can be readily derived.”(Lo, 2004, p. 23). This “survival of the richest” rather than the fittest allows for substantial noise to surround the signals about asset value conveyed by prices. Further successful actions speak louder than disastrous omissions, as one feted movie executive put it “If I had said yes to all the projects I turned down and no to all the other ones I took, it would of worked out much the same” (Molodinow, 2009, p 12). Availability bias means few traders learn from even their most damaging omissions. So learning is very history dependent with little inference being made from unused, but potentially profitable, alternative trading strategies. Scholars of psychology and behavioural finance are aware that beyond a certain level of complexity human cognition is limited, the question is how bounded rationality can be more realistically modelled in finance. There are two main approaches to modelling bounded rationality (a) optimising agents who face constraints-with the focus placed upon external bounds, and (b) satisficing decision-making agents- which focus upon internal bounds to cognition. Heuristics work by using small, but highly relevant, sets of information to resolve immediate problems quickly. Investors apply heuristics to adapt to new information, for example as market conditions change. New opportunities arise from the old heuristics. Think of the “weightless economy” of the late 90's that made reported losses almost seem virtuous as internet players struggled to “dominate the space” at all costs (Brynjolfsson and Kahn, 2000). Since market conditions are subject to continuous and abrupt changes, investors will continue to adjust and adapt, as the evolutionary ebb and flow of markets progresses (Lo, 2004). According to the AMH arbitrage opportunities appear and disappear as a result of adaptive responses to changing economic conditions; as they do so investors adapt new heuristics to match new challenges. The most basic requirement of any trading strategy is its survival value, its profitability and risk reduction value come after this most fundamental market test. Strategies that “blow up” their adopters are unlikely to live long enough to 18 appropriately adapt to the market environment in which they are deployed. So where do new market strategies or ways of seeing the market come from? De Bondt (2004) interviewed over 500 European investors with between Euro 100,000 and Euro 1 million to invest and concluded “individual clusters of attitudes and belief, often associated with national character, gender, age and religion influence portfolio choice. [Hence] Culture matters.” As Polyani pointed out (1944) financial markets are embedded within a broader social and political settlement whose transformation (in a revolutionary episode) can breach the control of such heuristic tools control. So mental frames influence investment strategies and are shared and communally formed. Such cognitive schema are inherited, adapted and eventually abandoned, cannibalised or recycled in the face of new realities. Crucially our financial and personal lives are integrated and mutually enforcing and not sealed off purely economic calculations But how does this happen? What do we know about the evolution of the behavioural norms we all share? One norm we all rely on is some, perhaps minimal, degree of co-operation from others. One setting in which this collaboration is sorely needed is within the context of a prisoner's dilemma where a failure to co-operate induces losses for all. Axelrod (1984) reports the results of a competition to devise a computer program capable of optimally solving the prisoner's dilemma problem. The winning program always initially uses a cooperative strategy until the opposing player defects and then retaliates until the opponent co-operates again. This ‘tit-for-tat’ strategy turns out to be optimal almost whatever the opponent does. If my opponent is continually uncooperative he gets one period of grace before my retaliation kicks in. If my opponent always cooperates so will I. Interestingly the strategy that performed worst is the most seemingly “sophisticated” invoking learning and probability distributions to constantly update behaviour. Within financial markets the problem of counter-party risk, so vividly displayed during the recent sub-prime debt crisis reflects such a choice (Khanani and Lo, 2007 and Lo, 2009). Heiner (1983, p563) notes a rather similar pattern of development in the evolution of blackjack play amongst professional players. Card counting techniques, requiring immense memory skills, have given way to very simple structured response strategies. It appears simple structured strategies dominate more explicit “maximisation” strategies in many competitive environments. 19 The evolving order of the AMH contrasts with the EMH for which efficiency is seen as a static concept. It is important, however, to consider how the two hypotheses can be tested empirically. Direct tests of the AMH are quite easy to conceptualise using the ‘top-down’ approach. A large number of tests have been designed over the years to test for the EMH and usually these involve some sort of quantification of efficiency. In broad terms the AMH can be tested by investigating whether the level of efficiency in a market varies significantly over time. An increasing number of papers report results consistent with the AMH. Neely et al (2009) report regularity in appearing and disappearing profit opportunities in the foreign exchange market in the 1970's through early 1990's. Lo (2004) and Kim et al (2011) report fluctuating levels of market efficiency over very long historical periods. In addition, quite a number of studies report fluctuations and even reversals in well known stock market anomalies (see, for example, Brusa et al 2005; Chong et al, 2005; Marquering et al, 2006 and Moller and Zilca, 2008). Yet the AMH must presently be regarded more as a way of seeing, rather than a fully specified alternative model to the EMH. In Section 5 we adopt that way of seeing to re-evaluate some classic problems in Finance. The following section of the paper outlines conceptual frameworks incorporating both internal and external bounds. It reviews the inclusion of internal and external bounds separately in the modelling of bounded rationality, highlighting the importance of taking the two sets of constraints upon effective decision-making into account when modelling the limitations upon rationality. These conceptual frameworks allow direct testing of the AMH using ‘bottom-up’ approaches. 4. A more systematic and theoretically grounded basis for behavioural finance and its links to AMH In this section we examine how a more systematic and theoretically grounded basis for behavioural finance can be developed. The internal and external bounds on financial decision-making are examined in sub-section 4.1. Heuristics and adaptive behaviour are examined in sub-section 4.2, followed by discussions of satisficing and investor heterogeneity in sub-section 4.3. We show how each section implies testable hypotheses allowing us to distinguish the predictive power of the AMH from the EMH using ‘bottom-up’ methods which is discussed in sub-section 4.4. 20 4.1. Internal and external bounds upon investment decisions Both environmental context and cognitive boundaries are crucial factors when modelling decision-making under uncertainty. There are two types of model of bounded rationality. One type of model focuses on the external bounds on the investor. These models are based upon investor optimisation under externally imposed constraints (Lee, 2011, p 514). Here investors are assumed to be rational in terms of maximising some objective, whereas satisficing is interpreted as non-optimal and simply accepting some, at least tolerable, outcome given the external constraints. Following this external constraint approach, some studies use an optimal search model framework, where investors do not possess full information about the choices set they face. But Weitzman's (1979) allows investors to invoke heuristics in deciding when to stop their search. Asymmetric information is often invoked as investors are often not equally informed about the distribution and location of the prices on offer. The second type of model of investor satisficing is based on internal cognitive limitations which tend to induce errors in the judgements of boundedly rational agents (Salop and Stiglitz, 1977, Bekiros, 2010). The focus of this type of model is therefore on the internal cognitive bounds upon the investor. Following this approach, such models imbue consumers/investors with heterogeneous response functions recognising that, for example, investor's cognition may be reduced through habitual behaviour such as dividing price quotes into, high, medium and low bands. In this example, traders with low cognitive ability can only form a small number of partitions (for example the single partition into low and high prices), whereas the more cognitively gifted traders are able to form a greater number of partitions (say low, medium and high) and are thus able to more astutely assess the price distribution. Heiner (1983) portrays the origins of predictable investor behaviour as deriving from the need of investors to assess the reliability of information before it is acted upon. Actions in this view are only undertaken if they cross a threshold for the reliability of the information eliciting the possible action. More frequently deployed actions are by their nature more reliable, if only because their effect has been played out more. The reliability of information is a function of both an investor’s perception and environment. For a given environment less 21 perceptive investors will be able to assess the reliability of a smaller range of actions, because of their inability to recall them being used. This makes sense when we compare the variety of behaviour we observe in humans compared to animals, or cats compared to baboons. The more developed the mind the less repetitive and predictable the agent’s behaviour. So in Heiner’s (1983) framework task uncertainty reduces the scope of actions adopted by challenging investors’ to assess the reliability of possible actions. It is this very contraction of the feasible action set, induced by the need to select a reliable action, that produces predictability in observed investor behaviour. So when reliability of actions is an issue uncertainty may be a boon for the social scientist/researcher, by rendering investor behaviour predictable. The above two models of bounded rationality present an incomplete picture of the notion of bounded rationality since they only apply one type of bound. In a more complete version of bounded rationality, both internal and external bounds intertwine in determining the agents’ decision-making. When only one set of bounds is taken into account, bounded rationality is seen as a barrier to an optimal solution whereas if the two sets of bounds are taken into account, as Simon’s scissors metaphor shows, a richer concept of rational action is born. This fit between internal and external bounds highlights the evolving nature of limits upon investor rationality. According to this holistic view of decision-making our environment contains both potential problems and solutions. This is because environments are constructed by decision-makers’ behaviour and the emerging structure of our environment interacts with the heuristics each trader adopts in order to manage and remould that environment. Therefore, the structure of the environment maps onto and is redrawn by to the structure of individuals' cognition. This implies the following hypothesis: Hypothesis 1: The structures for both internal cognition and the external environment within which it arises define rationality for investors within an evolving market order. The inclusion of both sorts of bounds allows an evolved form of rationality to emerge amongst investors. Successful investors respond to their changing external environment adaptively and appropriately. This matching process of environment to its cognition is 22 undertaken by the construction and adaption of heuristics/mental-frames aimed at limiting cognitive errors without incurring unacceptably high costs in the struggle. 4.2 Heuristic and adaptive behaviour The use of decision-making heuristics and the construction of mental frames is perhaps the most influential departure from standard expected utility theory, it plays an important function in prospect theory (Kahnneman and Tversky, 1979, 1992), the theory of mental accounting Thaler (1985, 1999) and asset pricing Bernartzi and Thaler (1995). Early studies of heuristics were associated with error-prone intuitions or apparent irrationality (Kehneman and Tversky (1992). In the literature, heuristics are also viewed positively as a natural feature of decision choice requiring a combination of learning and adaptation (Gigerenzer and Brighton, 2009). Heuristics that are not rational if cognitive processing was limitless may be understood as a form of constrained rationality given our true mental abilities. Recent studies attempt to model heuristics using an adaptive tool box built on three decision blocks of (a) searching, (b) stopping rules and (c) final decision criterion. These studies show that employing specific heuristics in an adaptive way helps to make accurate, fast and frugal decisions. The frugality derives from adapting least cost filters to screen out clearly inferior options and settle upon good enough outcomes. In this view, heuristics are the internal mechanisms that guide search and determine when it should end. Using heuristics in this adaptive way means that the two sources of bounds upon rationality, from internal and external sources, nest neatly. So Gigerenzer et al (1999, p 13) state “A heuristic is ecologically rational to the degree that it is adapted to the structure of the environment.” Here “'ecological' is just another word for the occurrence of a rule-governed, self-organized order” (Smith 2008, p. 6). Decision-makers can make good decisions, by using their mind to best infer future value given by trading in their environment. If external bounds are fairly immutable from the investors’ standpoint, then internal bounds can be evolved to take advantage of the structure of the external environment. A relatively stable environment combined with a constantly adapting investor understanding of that environment makes for better decision-making. 23 Heuristic search involves identifying a search procedure requiring limited computational capacity to render complex decisions solvable. This involves an “editing” of decisions to leave a feasible choice set capable of fairly simple, rule-based, evaluation. So, for example, we sort stocks into value or glamour, small or big, bins prior to final selection. Heuristic rules/mental frames are used to manage the consequences of cognitive limitations and especially so in situations where there are constraints in time, cost and skills or when information is limited or ambiguous. There are two reasons for rationality to break down: firstly, beyond a certain level of complexity our logic fails us. Secondly, in the cut and thrust of market trading investors cannot rely on the rationality of other agents, so they are forced to make guesses regarding the behaviour of others. Consider the game of chess. On the first move each player can move any of their 8 pawns or either of their 2 Knights. This implies 40 moves are available to play in total at the opening move. This fact implies at the end of first move 400 board configurations are possible. On the second move this expands to 71,582 possible board configurations (Shenk, 2006, p. 69). So good Chess players, like great traders, must make fast and frugal decisions focussing directly on likely evolutionary paths of play and resulting threats and opportunities. Similarly Rubic’s cube has 43 trillion possible initial starting points (Heiner, 1983, p 563). So recalling the best way to unscramble the cube from each of them is impossible. So good players simply sequentially adopt a few basic unscrambling strategies pursuing them until they prove fruitless. While this involves far more manipulations of the cube than a perfect/optimal strategy, for any given starting point, it is hugely superior to any random search strategy. This results in subjective beliefs and the assumption of managed risks. Given the possible outcomes of play are so numerous co-ordinating the editing of possible outcomes, prior to decision-making, becomes impossible even if players/traders were to attempt it. Hence investors are almost certain to adopt very different mental frames for trading purposes and it is only the evolutionary process of trading itself that can remove the most unhelpful frames and promote the power of the most successful frames. In this way each investor “promote(s) an end which is no part of his intentions.” (Smith, 1776, p. 421). This is achieved by unconsciously sifting and perfecting new, more appropriate, mental schemata thrown into prominence by changing market conditions. 24 Adaptive agents use specific heuristics that seem appropriate to the changing environment. In this context adaptive decision-making is rational. Successful heuristics rotate over time, with no fool-proof trading rule being on offer. As Lo (2004) points out rationality in the context of EMH and irrationality in the context of behavioural finance are two sides of the same coin i.e. agents adjust and adapt to new information. This is why Lo favours replacing the polarities of rationality and irrationality with a more nuanced concept of adaptive behaviour in complex, evolving, markets. This is consistent with a definition of an evolved rationality, where investors try out, adapt and reject heuristics as they assess new market opportunities and withdraw from past loss-making positions. From the above the following hypothesis is derived: Hypothesis 2: Adaptive decision-making enhances alignment between the structures of internal cognition and the external environment. Here the reliability of a strategy, and hence its practical use, depends on both the decision-makers environment and their perception of it. Heiner (1983) reminds us that the most sophisticated agent’s may seek to change their environment as well as improve their ability to perceive it. Of course such possibilities are limited, which may explain the extinction of many animals with poorer perceptual abilities than humans. More appropriate/adaptive responses to the trading environment enhances the match between internal and external bounds. This hypothesis accords with the fact that cognitive limits are not necessarily a curse, but may rather be a blessing in guiding investors to fast, frugal, yet profitable, trading decisions in a world where time is money and the sources of money change rapidly. 4.3. Satisficing and heterogeneity Satisficing, as opposed to optimising, might be thought of as the first fruit of bounded rationality. Satisficing embeds the art of the possible in a constrained environment with sparse information and tight deadlines on decision-making. Satisficing fulfils feasible aspirations while accepting money will always be left on the table. Often we must choose the least bad option. But investors’ ability to conceive of and rank options will differ. For some investors a tech stock is a tech stock, but some prescient investors, like John Doerr of 25 Kleiner Peabody Caulfield Byers realise Amazon, Netscape and Google are just that little bit special. It is from such refined mental processes that fortunes are made. Satisfaction of investors’ desires is limited by their cognitive abilities and powers of selfcontrol and these will differ across investors. Investors differ in their psychological makeup and cognitive brain function, as well as their risk-profiles and investment horizons. From the above, the following hypothesis is derived: Hypothesis 3: Optimising agents who utilise their best internal capacity to adapt to their observed environmental structure are satisficers. Investors optimise their investment portfolios subject to their personal cognitive bounds and ability to match their cognition to objective market conditions. Putting this interpretation of satisficing into a financial context implies that investors differ in their trading strategies in addition to setting different goals according to their skills and knowledge. From the above discussion we identify four main features of bounded rationality for incorporation into a successful modelling framework for investment. These features, listed below, will be discussed within this section and applied in Section 6. 1) Investors’ cognitions are bounded in different ways and to different degrees. 2) The goal of a satisficer is to achieve an acceptable solution by using their current cognition, taking the heterogeneity of other agents into account. 3) Through adapting appropriate heuristics, the investor's own cognitive bounds and the bounds set by their trading environment are matched. 4) Agents’ satisfy their goals through adaptive behaviour and the adoption, recasting and rejection of decision heuristics. The interaction between investors as decision-makers within financial markets is illustrated in Figure 1. Here markets are in the short run “voting machines” not weighing machines as the famous value investor Benjamin Graham pointed out (Graham and Dodd, 1934, p 23). What matters is not what a trader believes but what traders think others believe. The market reflects the instability of Keynes' “beauty contest” which yields an unstable equilibrium in investors' expectations. Expectations and decisions by investors shape market 26 outcomes, the resulting structure of the market order is then reflected in individual investor’s assessments of the effectiveness of their chosen trading strategy. This drives iterative rounds of adoption, adjustment and rejection of mental frames by investors. This adaptive process can be both costly and slow as a new order tentatively emerges. Figure 1 about here 4.4. Implementation of Artificial Intelligent Agents This sub-section outlines how artificial Intelligence models can be constructed in order to test the hypotheses of the prior subsections. In response to the highly centralised, top-down and deductive approach that characterises the mainstream neoclassical economic approach, agent-based modelling using artificial intelligent agents is decentralised, bottom-up, and inductive, within dynamic environments Agent-based modelling was developed in the early 1980s and is now a rapidly growing approach to modelling economic behaviour (Duffy, 2006). While looking at the advantages and disadvantages of this computational approach to economic behaviour Duffy (2006), shows that these models often provide a better fit to experimental data and he suggests the possibility of combining an agent-based methodology productively with human subjects/experimental research methods. Agent-based models have the considerable advantage that controlled experiments can be run with the attributes of both the population of agents and market being capable of being adjusted to see the effects on the resulting market dynamics (see, for example, Cincotti et al., 2003; Yeh and Yang, 2010; Tseng et al., 2010)). Thus it is possible to directly test hypotheses such as those developed in the three subsections above. An interesting sub set of this work is that looking at ‘zero-intelligence’ agents who have no trading skill at all to see how they fare in markets sometime in interactions with more skilled or faster learning agents (see, Yeh, 2008). In these exercises the roles of skill and chance can be explicitly investigated in a way that is very difficult in the traditional paradigm. 27 Machine learning refers to systems capable of independent learning; that is integrating and acquiring knowledge. Researchers in artificial intelligence are actively engaged in developing learning algorithms applicable in a real world complex system context. Modelling a financial market is an ideal application for this field because financial markets are huge and complex. Investors’ behaviour is complex and conflicting and so far standard linear asset pricing models have struggled to describe it adequately. Therefore, the methodology and modelling that allows agents to learn and adapt may become a crucial part of modelling financial market behaviour. Reinforcement Learning is a sub-field of machine learning and now commonly used in artificial intelligence originated from psychology. Investor behaviour is heuristically determined and depends on agents’ cognitive ability to learn and adapt, therefore RL methodology appears to provide an ideal approach to model agents’ learning, experience, intuition, knowledge and beliefs. RL provides a formal framework for defining the interactions between goal-directed learning agents within a dynamic environment in terms of states, actions and reward (Sutton and Barto, 1998). Sutton and Barto (1998, p.3) describe RL as learning how to map actions into the environment in order to maximise reward. They continue their definition as follow: “The learner is not told which action to take, as in most forms of machine learning, but instead must discover which actions yield the most reward by trying them out. In the most interesting and challenging cases, actions may affect not only the immediate reward faced but also the next situation encountered and, through that, all subsequent rewards. These two characteristics-trial and error search and delayed reward- are the most important distinguishing features of RL”. Moreover, the dynamics of RL can be reduced to four main elements: a policy, a reward function, a value function, and a model of the environment. An agent searches for an optimal policy which maximises total reward. The agent is continuously analysing the consequences of their actions through trial and error interactions with the environment. In more recent RL frameworks agents simultaneously learn by trial and error a model of the environment and, the use of that model for planning (Sutton and Barto, 1998). 28 RL consists of a set of environmental states, S, a set of agent actions, A, and a scalar reward/reinforcement function, R, mapping environments and actions into pay-offs. The environment is typically modelled as a finite-state Markov decision process (MDP), this make RL algorithms highly related to dynamic programming techniques. Greif and Laitlin (2004) show reinforced learning within institutions can make the difference between continued survival and collapse. Comparing the dominant post-war socialist parties in Italy and Sweden and the medieval cities of Genoa and Venice they trace how an inability to learn to adapt to a radically changing environment lead to the demise of the Italian left and the Genoese podesteria. These authors show how reinforcement learning can be built into a simple repeated-game structure. They conclude, after considering a variety of casestudies of institutional reform, that while initially institutions reinforce their structure over time exogenous shocks tend to undermine this trend by posing an existential threat to the increasingly atrophied institution. According to a survey done by Kaelbling et al. (1996) RL has been successfully applied to complex problem-solving and decision making. RL can be applied for the purpose of getting an optimal policy that resolves control problems as well as prediction problem. Different versions of RL have been used in the context of financial markets. For example, Lee (2001) adopts a RL algorithm which learns only from past data for stock market prediction using the Korean stock market. He finds RL provides a more useful indicator than conventional indicators of stock trading and he recommends extending this approach by applying other RL algorithms where the definition of reward on offer is slightly different from that in his paper. An adaptive fuzzy RL approach, which combines the adaptive action selection policy of RL and fuzzy logic, is employed by Bekiros (2010). In this approach agents beliefs are represented by fuzzy inference rules to advance the literature on heterogeneous agents based market. He finds that the predictive ability of the adaptive fuzzy RL is significantly higher than other competing models. 5. EMH or AMH? - Some applications. 29 In this section we try to illustrate how a shift to viewing financial markets through the lens of the AMH, as opposed to the traditional EMH, might aid our understanding and improve research methods in finance. The greatest effect of such a shift would be to broaden the type of questions that can legitimately be asked in finance, a prospect we discuss in our conclusion. However, an AMH focus would illuminate many existing issues and the specific ways they are conceptualised and addressed. To illustrate the AMH approach we discuss three specific and important issues out of many in the existing literature that can be illuminated by the AMH approach. We revisit these standard research questions through the lens of our three proposed research hypotheses developed above. We ask how those hypotheses might be used to enhance current model building and financial decision-making. We later show the AMH helps us to understand State intervention in financial markets not as a constraint on the operation of those markets but as part of the evolution of financial institutions’ market power into full expression in the political arena. 5.1 Three examples of applying the AMH The first example we deal with concerns the random walk. Perhaps the most basic implication of the EMH is that market prices follow a random walk. Tomorrow’s price will only differ from today’s price in random unpredictable ways. As stated above, an array of empirical studies have rejected this claim in favour of under-reaction/momentum at relatively short intervals of a year or so and longer-term correction/reversals implying earlier market overreaction. Such refutations have emerged as a set of “anomalies” which form much of the grist to the current mill of behavioural finance studies. i) Momentum Recently Barberis, Sheifer and Vishny (1998) have advanced a theoretical model in which earnings (and hence stock values) always follow a random-walk, as the EMH implies, but investors perceive them to either revert to trend or exhibit momentum with some predetermined probability. The transition between an investor focus upon momentum and reversion regimes with a corresponding effect on prices, in clear denial of the random-walk property of observed prices, is an obvious anomaly/irrationality within the EMH framework. 30 These agents fail to comply with the requirement of Hypothesis 3 above in matching their perceptions of value creation to the observed environment; thus they fail the test hypothesis 3 poses for boundededly rational agents. The distinction here, as in Hypothesis 1 above, is between the investment strategy and its cognitive and external context, as opposed to a proposed statistical property, which is conjectured to prevail regardless of context or cognition. The AMH cautions us that it is not primarily value characteristics themselves that drive price movements but rather the mental frames and heuristics through which value is perceived. Hence the irrationality of investors, as suggested by the EMH, in the Barberis et al (1998) framework is simply their adaptability, or evolving rationality, to those adopting the AMH lens on the same phenomena. The success of momentum based trading strategies is known to be a function of the extent of informational asymmetry prevailing in the financial market (Easley et al, 2002), suggesting the need to adapt trading strategies according to the environment into which they are deployed. Neither momentum nor reversion/correction based strategies are dominant universally but rather are revealed to be so by deployment into a favourable trading environment. So either the transition probability, underpinning the markov- switching process between regimes in the Barberis Shleifer and Vishy model tracks changes in the regime probabilities (as investors flip between momentum/reversion “routines”) or the choices made by competing autonomous agents are allowed to aggregate to determine overall market asset demand and supply schedules. Seru et al (2010) show market learning consists of two types of correction. Firstly investors discover their true market ability in the process of trading. Secondly those who realise they have little aptitude for trading, having been punished with losses, exit the market in order to passively hold a diversified portfolio. Those who so exit may be largely individual investors whom Hur et al (2010) identify as being particularly associated with the presence of profits to following momentum based strategies. ii) The disposition effect It is now well established that investors seem to sell winners (stock that have had recent rises in price) too quickly and hold losers (stocks with recent price declines) too long. In any market with transaction costs longer trades are, on average, more profitable trades. The costs of trading opens up a range of prices between which arbitraging differences in prices 31 of assets of equivalent value makes no sense (Constantinides, 1983). In their seminal study Schlarbaum et al (1978) document this fact. Returns to short holding periods are highest amongst their sample of individual investors, although surprisingly good more generally. So why do the returns of individual investors decline in the holding period over which they trade? Shrefrin and Statman (1985) argue that this occurs because such investors have a disposition to sell winning stocks, whose price has just risen, too quickly and hold on to losing stocks, whose price has just fallen, too slowly. They do this to avoid the “regret” of realising paper losses or missing out on easily envisaged gains. This pattern of trading is all the more difficult to understand given tax incentives to sell stocks whose value has fallen to enable the realised loss to be used as a tax shelterv (Constantinides, 1984) . This is because the tax rate levy/relief on capital gains/losses are equal so it makes sense to realise losses in order to help harvest longer-term post-tax returns on your winning stocks. It appears individual investors at least do not seem to trade to maximize risk-adjusted returns, leaving tax subsidies from the government on the table. In contradiction of hypothesis 3 they fail to match their cognitive frame to the tax environment they find themselves in, suggesting they are not rational in this bounded sense. What about more sophisticated traders, such as hedge funds and investment banks? Hur et al (2010) confirm that the presence of both momentum and the disposition effect is directly proportional to the percentage of individual traders present in each market segment. As with momentum strategies the intensity of a heuristic and its explanatory power varies with the environment into which it is deployed. While institutional investor dominated markets offer little scope for arbitraging the disposition effect more “noisy” markets, in which individual investors have a greater share of trades, offer greater opportunities for counterdisposition effect arbitrage profits to be reaped. Hence the disposition effect flourishes in individual investor dominated markets but is arbitraged away elsewhere. Yet it is not only the traders’ characteristics that determine the intensity of the observed disposition effect. Kumar (2009) shows firstly that the intensity of the disposition effect is strongly related to various proxies for the uncertainty involved in valuing the stock and that there is also evidence informed traders recognize such pockets of “hard to value” stocks and that they proactively trade to arbitrage out such mispricing. Using standard metrics of the intensity of informed tradingvi Kumar (2009) reports evidence that informed traders actively 32 predate upon the relatively uniformed who misguidedly trade in hard to value stocks. This evidence brings us closer to direct observation of the elimination of noise-traders in a process of Darwinian competition to implement profitable investment strategies. iii) corporate governance and organisational form. A tragic example of this process of a mismatch of cognition within a changing environment is the way in which British Petroleum’s “upstream” exploration and extraction unit, BPX, was focussed, by its then Head John Browne, on identifying very large hydrocarbon deposits of oil and natural gas; so called “elephants” in the industry (Roberts, 2007). In the 90’s BP had lost ground to smaller, niche player, independent explorers/extractors. So Browne cut competing “asset managers” loose within BPX to compete as they saw fit. This replaced centralised control with information-sharing amongst “peer group” autonomous asset managers within BPX (Roberts, 2007, p 25-27). The Deepwater Horizon rig explosion (in the Gulf of Mexico on April 20th 2010) and the subsequent inability of BP to cap the underground well until mid September that year exposed the dangers of such intense internal rivalry. Safety thresholds were pushed to breaking point under such intense pressure. Following the spill survival required hyper-vigilence with regard to rig safety as politicians made clear their willingness, if not eagerness, to react to public fury. Hence corporate history matters, especially in times of economic crisis by determining the nature and scope of corporate routines available to enable survival. This “path dependence”, deriving from the effect of history of the array of corporate routines is most starkly illustrated by the claim that shareholder rights are better protected in common law jurisdictions (largely the UK and its former colonies, US, India, Malaysia, etc) than in civil law ones (France, Germany or their former colonies) (La Porta, et al, 1998, 2000). Yet, as other others have pointed out in critiquing the “path dependency” story of national shareholder protection arrangements, the civil law retains much of the plasticity the common law offers by differential enforcement of a unified set of codified company laws (Pistor et al, 2002, Pistor and Xu, 2003). The AMH allows us to understand both the “path dependency” of governance arrangements and how legal enforcement of shareholder’s rights operates as an evolutionary selection strategy within seemingly divergent governance paths. 33 The examples given above have been drawn directly from the existing finance and accounting literature and the insights gained can be fitted reasonably easily into the standard methodological approach of creating analytically tractable models. However, the traditional analytical methods are very limited in their scope to model interactions between large numbers of heterogeneous agents when decision systems evolve though time. In so far as papers in the literature deal with these issues, most either use either single representative agent models with non-constant belief systems (see, for example, Barberis and Huang, 2008) or models with two types of agent, one rational and the other nonrational (see the literature on noise trader models, for example, De Long et al , 1990). Models with much more complexity than this quickly become intractable analytically. It is possible, however, to use computer simulations to directly model the interactions of large numbers of heterogeneous agents with varying degrees of intelligence. This use of intelligent agent models is a very fast growing field (see, the special issue of the Journal of Economic Surveys in 2011 devoted to this and closely related topics) but is currently largely disconnected from mainstream academic finance. Work of this nature is often done by computer scientists, mathematicians and physicists and receives very little coverage in the most prestigious mainstream finance journals. Given that the assumptions adopted in this field are evidently a much closer depiction of reality this field of research looks very promising and its dismissal by the mainstream all the more troubling. 5.2 The AMH and financial reform The AMH allows us to see the relationship between the markets and the State in a new, perhaps more helpful, way. A keystone of the EMH is the belief that markets know best and the State can at best only re-allocate wealth produced by the gains from the trade that characterise free-markets. The recent financial crisis makes a mockery of such claims. In reality the primary role of the TARP, UK bailout of RBS, EU bailout of Dexia, Bankia, etc, has been to recapitalise bankrupt private sector institutions at the tax-payers expense, in a “socialism for the rich” parody of the welfare state. In reality two parallel, and often complementary, markets explain these facts. The market for votes is itself as much central to effective financial hegemony as any financial market exchange. Increasingly political and financial power has been fused in a way that makes the prudential role of banking 34 authorities much in doubt (Johnson and Kwak, 2010). The central figures in the management of the financial crisis, Hank Paulson, Timothy Geithner and Larry Summers all had previous lives in investment banking or headed straight to such an institution slightly after their tenure in office. The close integration between the State and financial power suggests a symbiotic, and perhaps even mutually parasitic, existence. The AMH recognises the need of investment institutions to adapt to pressures from vote markets within democratic polities. Political preferment is thus just another survival/advancement strategy of those using vote markets to buttress their position within allegedly “efficient” financial markets. State intervention is not necessarily a constraint on market forces but rather one further manifestation of market forces power. 5.3 The AMH and nature of Darwinian economic competition. The AMH with its acknowledgement of evolutionary behaviour makes clear some of the problems of equating competition with automatic improvements in social welfare. Much economic competition is truly Darwinian in that it is being ranked first as an individual, not increasing the overall social product, that counts. Frank (2011, page 7) states the problem thus “Charles Darwin was one of the first to perceive the problem clearly. One of his central insights was that natural selection favours traits and behaviours primarily according to their effect on individual organisms not larger groups.” A tension arises between the interest of individuals and the broader social group because natural selection implies traits which confer individual fitness thrive regardless of their consequence for the broader species. Frank (2011, p12) gives the example of drug cheats in the world of professional sports. All cyclists may agree that a “clean” race is the only race that counts. But each may feel forced to use drugs in a World where “everyone is doing it”. The need to stretch to reach the highest possible rank means we may achieve the worst of all possible worlds, with no worthy Champions to hail, rather than the best. The proposed financial transaction/Tobin tax (FTT) 0.1% tax on all bond and equity transactions now adopted by ten EU member states might be seen as a helpful attempt to bring about a community-wide benefit in the face of individual nation states incentives to act as a home to “flight capital”. While access to such capital clearly benefits whichever State in which it chooses to domicile the need to appease it may serve to reduce community-wide 35 wealth and social cohesion. Such a “public good” might be seen as sufficient justification for State intervention to dampen speculative trades. Indeed the costs of an individual State adopting a FTT is already well known from Swedish experiments in the 1990’s. So it is clear any benefits from the FTT can only be reaped by transnational co-operation rather than competition. An evolutionary perspective helps us understand that the problem is not that financial markets are insufficiently competitive, but rather that the intensity of competition we observe is damaging to broader social objectives of stability. Hence the State has a legitimate role in constraining individual competitive effort which damages broader social policy This symbiotic relationship between the State and the market has been known at least since Karl Polyani, explained how the “laissez-faire” system of free-market capitalism was planned by England’s political ruling elite. In a similar way today intense and resource intensive “rent seeking” is deployed by the wealthy to divert resources from the middleclass to themselves (Stiglitz, 2010). The predatory lending practices and credit card services marketing of financial institutions are examples of legal, but clearly immoral, transfers from the poor to the wealthy. But in this the banks follow a well recognised path in procurement, privatisation and regulatory practice which facilitates State mandated transfers from the middle–class to a wealthy elite. The impact of such transfers is already very clear in the data. In 2007, just before the Crisis hit America, the top 0.1% of American households had an income 220 times higher than the average for the remaining 90% of American households (Stiglitz, 2012, p 2) More recently Rajan (2010) has traced the roots of the sub-prime crisis to the increasing impoverishment of the uneducated and unskilled, often black, citizenry in the US. From 2001 onwards economic recovery, even when it came, often was of the jobless recovery form, where new jobs went to the young, better educated, more flexible elements of the workforce leaving behind a surplus to requirement residue. The absence of any longterm social welfare provision in the US means such victims of past restructuring enter a lower paid, more transient, workforce more exposed to the vagaries of the market. The obvious way of alleviating the most pressing needs of the swollen ranks of the working poor, short of State provision, was easier access to credit. While this stoked up problems for the future it did at least ameliorate the anxiety of current poverty. Rajan (2010, p 35) finds no shortage of evidence that US government policy promoted the indebtedness 36 of the working poor. For example the Federal Housing Enterprise and Housing Enterprise Safety and Soundness Act of 1992 instructed the Department of Housing and Urban Development (HUD) to develop affordable housing goals specifically targeting ethic minorities and those living in zip/post code areas rarely attracting mortgages. This initial encouragement to the development of the sub-prime lending market was reinforced later by President George W. Bush as part of his vision of expanding the American dream via a homeowners’ democracy. Recently Ferguson (2012) has diagnosed Western capitalism as entering an era of a “great degeneration” as market participants are driven to use rent-seeking to derive benefits from the State over claims to a constant, or even declining, national product. This descent into “stationary state” allows the rule of law to be replaced by the rule of lawyers as distributional conflicts dominate attempts to create a more efficient, productive, society. Within the modern “beehive” of financial networks extreme complexity allows small perturbations within the system to swiftly gather pace with disastrous consequences. While such network externalities are now being addressed by finance theorists (Easley and Kleinberg, 2010) and implemented tentatively by regulatory authorities (Gai et al, 2011) they remain irreconcilable with the standard finance theory of price-taking trades amongst anonymous atomistic agents. Financial institutions are the embodiment of the “rules of the game” of financial markets (Heiner, 1983) and it is these very rules which have now clearly broken down. So much of the post crisis challenge lies in appropriate post-crisis institutional reform. While many commentators portray almost any institutional reform as an attempt to traduce market allocations this ignores the role of financial institutions in maintaining the integrity of financial markets and hence securing gains from trade. A competitive strategy which gives an individual an edge ahead may nudge the society he lives in backwards. If free-market order takes much planning, as Polansky suggests (1944), it is financial institutions which must both bring a free market into existence and maintain its integrity once it exists. As Greif and Laitlin (2004) show such institutions are limited in their capabilities of internal renewal and so likely to being overwhelmed by historical events and hence collapse. This seems to have been the fate of many of the existing regulatory authorities discredited by the crisis (the UK’s FSA being perhaps the most obvious victim). Such bodies are unable to survive the 37 competitive process due to an inability to adapt to the greatly intensified rent-seeking behaviour the financial crisis brought. 6. Conclusion In the light of recent events which have exposed the shortcomings of the current financial paradigm this paper discusses the implications of moving to an approach based on the AMH. The AMH is much less theoretically restrictive than the existing paradigm as it does not assume that market participants uniformly act in accordance with the rationality axioms of neo-classical economics. Instead more realistic notions of bounded rationality are totally consistent with the AMH approach. We present the main features of bounded rationality suggesting three testable hypotheses to determine the degree to which observed trading behaviour conforms to the tenets of bounded rationality. This reflects an evolutionary concept of bounded rationality that seems more psychologically plausible than that commonly invoked by Finance researchers in its EMH form. As we have seen in the previous section the move to this approach would enable many specific issues in the discipline to be addressed in a more constructive and meaningful way. Many empirically established facts would cease to be troublesome anomalies to be ignored or marginalised but phenomena to be integrated into the mainstream of the subject. Yet it is in forming policy regarding financial markets that the transition from an EMH to an AMH paradigm may yet have it biggest impact. Possibly the greatest effect might be at a conceptual level by making acceptable discussion about and research into issues that would previously have been regarded as resolved. It is clear that more questioning of this nature might well have helped to avoid or alleviate the present crisis. The AMH is still a tentative and untested competitor to its EMH rival. But we have shown some reasons to be excited about its sphere of application both in theory testing and policy discussion. The evolving financial crisis may provide the context for such alternatives to the prevailing orthodoxy to at last be taken seriously. 38 References: Akerlof, G, Shiller, R.Animal Spirits: How human psychology drives the economy and why it matters for global capitalism:Princeton University Press New Jersey, USA: 2009. Armstrong, M, Vickers, J Zhou, J. Prominence and Consumer Search. RAND Journal of Economics2009:209-233. Arrow, K.J. Rationality of Self and Others in an Economic System. The Journal of Business. 1986: Vol. 59, No. 4: 385-399. Arthur, W. Inductive Reasoning and Bounded Rationality. The American Economic Review, 1994 No. 2 (Papers and Proceedings of the Hundred and Sixth Annual Meeting of the American Economic Association 1994:(May) 406-411. Axelrod, R.The evolution of cooperation: Basic Books Cambridge, Massachussetts, USA: 1984. Barberis, N, Shleifer, A,Vishny, R.A Model of Investor sentiment, Journal of Financial Economics 1998: 49(December) 307-343. Basov, S. Bounded rationality: static versus dynamic approaches. Economic Theory 2005:25(4), 871-886. Available at: http://works.bepress.com/suren_basov/3. Bekiros, S. Heterogeneous trading strategies with adaptive fuzzy Actor-Critic reinforcement learning: A behavioral approach. Journal of Economic Dynamics and Control2010:34(6) 1153-1170. Benartzi, S, Thaler, R.Myopic loss aversion and the equity premium puzzle. The Quarterly Journal of Economics1995: 110, 73-92. Bernard, V. and Thomas, J. Evidence that stock prices do not fully reflect the implications of current earnings for future earnings. Journal of Accounting and Economics:1990 13: 305340. British Academy, Open letter to Her Majesty the Queen. 2009: http://www.britac.ac.uk/events/archive/forum-economy.cfm Brock, W,Hommes, C.A rational route to randomness. Econometrica: Journal of the Econometric Society1997:651059-1095. Brown, A, Chua, Z,Camerer, C. Learning and visceral temptation in dynamic saving experiments.Quarterly Journal of Economics2009: 124(1) 197-232. Brusa, J, Pu, L, Schulman, C. Weekend Effect, ‘Reverse’ Weekend Effect, and Investor Trading Activities.Journal of Business Finance &Accounting2005: 32(7/8) 1495-1517. 39 Chang, E, Lewellen, W.Market Timing and Mutual Fund Performance. Journal of Business1984: 57 57-72. Cincotti, S. ,Focardi S. M., Marchesi M., Raberto M., Who wins? Study of long-run trader survival in an artificial stock market. Physica A 2003: 324 1–2 227–233. Chong, R, Hudson, R, Keasey, K, Littler, K.Pre-Holiday Effects: International Evidence on the Decline and Reversal of a Stock Market Anomaly. Journal of International Money and Finance 2005: 24 1226-1236. Clarkeson, R. Actuarial insights into the global banking catastrophe. Journal of Financial Regulation and Compliance 2009:17(4) 381-397. Cootner, P. (Ed) The Random Character of Stock Market Prices. Cambridge MA: MIT Press, 1964, 297-337.Critical Perspectives on International Business, Special Issue on the Financial Crisis 2009: 5(1/2). Critical Perspectives on International Business, Special Issue on the Financial Crisis 2009: 5(1/2). Daniel, K, Hirshleifer, D,Teoh, S. Investor psychology in capital markets: Evidence and policy implications, Journal of Monetary Economics2002: 49(1) 139-209. Daniel, K, Hirshleifer, D, Subrahmanyam, A. Investor psychology and security market underand overreactions. Journal of Finance1998: 53(6) 1839-1885. De Bondt, W, Thaler, R. Does the stock market overreact? Journal of Finance1985:40(3) 793-805. De Bondt, W,Thaler, R. Further evidence on investor overreaction and stock market seasonality. Journal of Finance1987:42(3), 557-581. De Bondt, W. A portrait of the individual Investor, European Economic Review 1998:42 831844. De Bondt, W. The value and beliefs of European investors. In Knorr Cetina, K, Preda A., eds. The Sociology of Financial Markets, Oxford University Press: 2005. De Long, B., Shleifer, A. Summers L. Waldman R. Noise trader risk in financial markets. Journal of Political Economy, 1990: 98(4): 703-738. Easley, D., S. Hvidkjaer, O’Hara, M. Is information risk a determinant of asset returns? Journal of Finance 2002:57(5): 2185-2221. Easley, D. and J. Kleinberg. Networks, Crowds and Markets: Reasoning about a highly connected world. New York, USA, Cambridge University Press. 2012 40 Fama, E. Random Walks in Stock Market Prices. Financial Analysts Journal. Sept-Oct 1965. 55-59.Fama, E. Efficient Capital Markets: A Review of Theory and Empirical Work. Journal of Finance, 1970:25(2) 383–417. Fama, E.Market efficiency, long term returns and behavioral finance. The Journal of Financial Economics 1998:49 283-306. Ferguson, N. The Great Degeneration: How institutions decay and economies die. London, England, Allen Lane. 2012. Findlay, M, Williams, E. A Post Keynesian View of Modern Financial Economics: In Search of Alternative Paradigms, Journal of Business Finance and Accounting1985:12(1) Spring. Fox, J.The Myth of the Rational Market:Harriman House. Petersfield, UK: 2010. Frank, R., The Darwin Economy: Liberty competition and the public good. Princeton, Princeton University Press. New Jersey, USA, 2011 Gai, P., Haldane, A. Kapedia, S. Complexity, concentration and contagion. Journal of Monetary Economics 58:July 453-470. 2011 Gabaix, X,Laibson, D. A boundedly rational decision algorithm. The American Economic Review2000:90(2) 433-438. Gigerenzer, G, Brighton, H. Homo heuristicus: Why biased minds make better inferences. Topics in Cognitive Science2009:1(1) 107-143. Gigerenzer, G, Gaissmaier, W. Heuristic Decision Making. Annual Review of Psychology, 2011:62 451–482. Gigerenzer, G, Goldstein, D. Reasoning the fast and frugal way: models of bounded rationality. Psychological Review 1996:103(4), pp. 650-669. Gigerenzer, G, Selten, R. Bounded Rationality: The Adaptive Toolbox: MA MIT PressCambridge : 2001. Gigerenzer, G, Todd, P, Group, A. Simple Heuristics That Make Us Smart: Evolution and Cognition Series Oxford University Press: 1999. Graham, B, Dodd, D. Security Analysis: McGraw-Hill New York, USA: 1937. Greenspan, A. Testimony to House of Representatives Committee on Government Oversight and Reform Oct 23: 2008. Greif, A. and D. Laitlin, A Theory of Endogenous political change. American Political Science Review 2004:98(4): 633-652. 41 Heiner, R. The Origins of predictable behavior. American Economic Review 73(4): 560-595. 1983. Hao, S, Jin, Q, Zhang, G. Investment Growth and the relation between equity value, earnings and equity book value. Accounting Review2011:86(2) 605-635. Hommes, C. Financial markets as nonlinear adaptive evolutionary systems. Quantitative Finance2001:1(1) 149-167. Hudson, R,Keasey, K, Littler, K, Dempsey, D. Time diversification: an essay on the need to revisit finance theory. Critical Perspectives on Accounting 1999: 10501–19. Hudson, R, Maioli, S. A response to a ‘Reflections on a global financial crisis’. Critical Perspectives on International Business 2010:6, 1 53-71. Hulbert, M.Timing and selection within the bond market: A look at the record, American Association of Individual Investors(AAII) Journal, 1996:(November). Hur, J., M. Pritamani, et al. Momentum and the disposition effect: The role of individual investors. Financial Management 2010:39(3): 1155-1175. Journal of Economic Surveys, Special Issue on Nonlinearity, Randomness and Complexity, 2011:25(3). Journal of Financial Regulation and Compliance, 2009, Special Issue on the Financial Crisis, Vol 17, Issue 4. Johnson, S, Kwak, J.13 Bankers: The Wall Street takeover and the next financial meltdown: Pantheon Books, New York, USA: 2010. Kahneman, D, Slovic, P,Tversky, A. Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases:Cambridge University Press: 1982. Kahneman, D, Tversky, A. Prospect theory: An analysis of decision under risk. Econometrica1979:47 263–291. Kay, J. Review of UK equity markets and long-term decision-making. London, England, Department of Business Innovation and Science. 2012. Keasey, K, Hudson, R. Finance theory a house without windows. Critical Perspectives on Accounting2007:18 932-951. Kendall, M. The Analysis of Economic Time Series – Part I: Prices. Journal of the Royal Statistical Society, Series A (General) 116, no. 1 11-34. 42 Kim, J,Shamsuddin, A, Lim K. Stock return predictability and the adaptive markets hypothesis: Evidence from century-long U.S. data. Journal of Empirical Finance 2011: forthcoming. Khandani, A, Lo, A. What happened to the quants in August 2007? Journal of Investment Management2007:5 5-54. Krugman, P.How Did Economists Get It So Wrong? The New York Times, September 2nd, 2009: http://www.nytimes.com/2009/09/06/magazine/06Economict.html?pagewanted=1&_r=2. Kuhn, T. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. 1st. ed., Chicago: Univ. of Chicago Press: 1962. Kumar, A. Hard to value stocks, behavioural biases and informed trading. Journal of Financial and Quantitative Analysis 2009:44(6): 1375-1401. Lee, C. Bounded Rationality and The Emergence of Simplicity Amidst Complexity. Journal of Economic Surveys2011: 25507-526. Lo, A. The Adaptive Markets Hypothesis: Market Efficiency from an Evolutionary Perspective. Journal of Portfolio Management,2004: 30th Anniversary Issue 15-29. Lo, A. Reconciling efficient markets with behavioural finance: the adaptive markets hypothesis. Journal of Investment Consulting2005: 7 (2) 21-44. Lo, A. Regulatory reform in the wake of the financial crisis of 2007-2008. Journal of Financial Economic Policy2009:1(1) 4-43. Lo, A, Hasanhodzic, J. The evolution of technical analysis: financial prediction from Babylonian tablets to Bloomberg terminals: Bloomberg Press, Hoboken, New Jersey, USA: 2010. Lo, A, Fear, Greed and financial crises: A cognitive neurosciences perspective, MIT Working Paper, https://mitsloan.mit.edu/finance/pdf/Lo-20120109d.pdf, 2011. Mandeville, B. The Fable of the Bees: Or private vices and public virtues. London, England, Penquin Books. 1714/1970. Mandelbrot, B. The Variation of Certain Speculative Prices. The Journal of Business 1963 36 (4) 394-419 Mallard, G. Modelling cognitively bounded rationality: an evaluative taxonomy. Journal of Economic Surveys,2011: forthcoming. 43 Marquering, W, Nisser, J, Valla, T. Disappearing anomalies: a dynamic analysis of the persistence of anomalies, Applied Financial Economics 2006: 16(4) 291-302. McLean, B, Nocera, J. All the devils are here: The hidden history of the financial crisis: Portfolio-Penguin, London, England: 2010. Mehra, R, Prescott, E. The equity premium: A puzzle. Journal of Monetary Economics1985:15(2), 145-161. Mehra, R, Prescott, E. The equity premium: ABC’s. Handbook of the Equity RiskPremium:North Holland, Elsevier, Amsterdam, The Netherlands: 2008. Merton, R. On Market Timing and Investment Performance, I. An Equilibrium Theory of the Value for Market Forecasts. Journal of Business1981:54 263-290. Minsky, H. Stabilising an unstable economy: McGraw Hill Professional New York USA: 1986. Mlodinow, L. The drunkard's walk: How randomness rules our lives: First Vintage Books New York, USA:, 2009 Moller, N, Zilca, S. The evolution of the January effect. Journal of Banking & Finance2008:32 (3), 447-457. Neely, C, Weller, P, Ulrich, J. The Adaptive Markets Hypothesis: Evidence from the Foreign Exchange Market. Journal of Financial and Quantitative Analysis2009:44 467-488. Newell, A,Simon, H. Human Problem Solving: Englewood Cliffs, NJ: PrenticeHall: 1972. Polyani, K. The great transformation: The political and economic origins of our time Beacon Press. Boston Massachusetts, USA 1944. Rajan, R., Fault lines: How Hidden fractures still threaten the world economy. Princeton, New Jersey, USA. Princeton University Press. 2010 Rogers, R,Sahakian, B, Hodges, J, Polkey, C, Kennard C, Robbins,T. Dissociating executive mechanisms of tasks control following frontal lobe damage and Parkinson's disease. Brain.1998:121 815-842. Rubinstein, A.On Price Recognition and Computational Complexity in a Monopolistic. Journal of Political Economy1993:39 83-96. Rubinstein, A.On price recognition and computational complexity in a monopolistic model.Journal of Political Economy, 1993:101(3) 473-484. Salop, S, Stiglitz, J.Bargains and Ripoffs: A Model of Monopolistically Competitive Price Dispersion. The Review of Economic Studies1977:44 493-510. 44 Samuelson, P. Economics. 1948. New York. McGraw-Hill. Samuelson, P. Proof that Properly Anticipated Prices Fluctuate Randomly. Industrial Management Review 1965 6:2 41-49.Sapra, S, Zak, P.Neurofinance: Bridging Psychology, Neurology, and Investor Behavior. 2008:Working Paper Series, Issue Available at SSRN: http://ssrn.com/abstract=1323051. Shenk, D.The immortal game:Anchor Books, New York, USA: 2006. Seru, A., T. Shumway, Stoffman N. Learning by Trading. Review of Financial Studies 2010:(23): 705-739. Shiller, R.Do Stock Prices Move Too Much to be Justified by Subsequent Changes in Dividends?American Economic Review 1981: 71(3): 421–436. Shiller, R.Stock Prices and Social Dynamics.Brookings Papers on Economic Activity, 1984:(2) 457-510. Shiller, R.Irrational Exuberance.2nd Edition: Princeton University Press, New Jersey, USA: 2000. Shleifer, A, and Summers, L.The Noise Trader Approach to Finance.Journal of Economic Perspectives 1990:4(2) 19-33. Simon, H.A behavioral model of rational choice.The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 1955:1 99-118. Simon, H. Studying human intelligence by creating artificial intelligence.American Scientist1981:69(3) 300-309. Simon, H.A mechanism for social selection and successful altruism.Science, 1990:250 16651668. Simon, H.Invariants of human behavior. Annual Review of Psychology, 1990:41(1), 1-20. Sorkin, R.Too big to fail:Penguin, London, England: 2009. Smets, F, Wouters, R. An estimated dynamic stochastic general equilibrium model of the euro area.Journal of the European Economic Association2003:1(5), 1123-1175. Smith, V. Rationality in Economics: Constructivist and Ecological forms. Cambridge University Press, New York, USA: 2008. Stiglitz, J., The Price of Inequality. London, England, Allen Lane, 2012. Taleb, N., Antifragile: How to live in a world we don't understand. London, England, Allen Lane. 2012. 45 Thaler, R. Mental Accounting and Customer Choice. Marketing Science1985:4(3), 199-21. Thaler, R,Mental Accounting Matters.Journal of Behavioral Decision Making.1999: 12(3) 183206. Todd, P.Fast and frugal heuristics for environmentally bounded minds. In: G. Gigerenzer & R. Selten, eds. Bounded rationality: The adaptive toolbox (Dahlem Workshop Report):Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 51-70: 2001. Todd, P,Gigerenzer, G. Bounding rationality to the world. Journal of Economic Psychology2003:24(2) 143-165. Trichet, J.-C. Reflections on the nature of monetary policy non-standard measures and finance theory., European Central Bank Press Release. http://www.ecb.int/press/key/date/2010/html/sp101118.en.html, 2010 Tseng, J., Lin C., Lin C., Wang S., Li S., Statistical properties of agent-based models in markets with continuous double auction mechanism. Physica A 2010: 389 8 1699–1707. Tseng, K.Behavioral finance, bounded rationality, neuro-finance, and traditional finance. Investment Management and Financial Innovations, 3(4) 7-18. Tversky, A, Kahneman, D.Advances in prospect theory: Cumulative representation of uncertainty. Journal of Risk and uncertainty1992:5(4) 297-323. Turner, A.The Turner Review: A regulatory response to the global banking crisis: Financial Services Authority: 2009. Veit, E, Cheney, J.Are mutual funds market timers? Journal of Portfolio Management, 1982:8(Winter) 35-42. Von Neumann, J., and Morgenstern, O. Theory of Games and Economic Behavior, Princeton, NJ, Princeton University Press, second ed. 1947. Weitzman, M.Optimal Search for the Best Alternative.Econometrica1979: 47, 641-654. Whitley, R.The transformation of business finance into financial economics: the roles of academic expansion and changes in U.S. capital markets. Accounting, Organisations and Society 1986: 11 171–92. Yeh, C. The Effects of Intelligence on Price Discovery and Market Efficiency. Journal of Economic Behaviour & Organization, 2008: 68.613-625. Yeh, C. and Yang, C. Examining the Effectiveness of Price Limits in an Artificial Stock Market. Journal of Economic Dynamics and Control, 2010: 34.pp.2089-2108. 46 Zhang, G.Accounting information, capital investment decisions and equity valuation: Theory and empirical implications, Journal of Accounting Research 2000:Vol 38 271-295. 47 Figure 1 48 Figure 2 49 Figure 3 i A good example of this is Rajan, 2005. This paper was delivered in August 2005 to a gathering of top economists at Jackson Hole which that year was honouring the retirement of Alan Greenspan as Chairman of the Federal Reserve. In hindsight this paper seems remarkably prescient but it was attacked quite violently at the time. Lawrence Summers, for example, told the audience he found "the basic, slightly lead-eyed premise of (Rajan's) paper to be misguided." (Wall Street Journal, 2009). A paper by Bezemer, 2011 outlines a number of research studies that did forecast a crisis and concludes that they commonly adopted accounting or flow-of-funds models rather than neo-classical equilibrium models. ii Books by McLean and Nocera, 2010 and Sorkin, 2009, are popular examples of the genre. One of the better high level overviews is a letter to the Queen seeking to answer her question written by members of the British Academy (British Academy, 2009). For diverse collections of academic papers on the crisis see special issues of the Journal of Financial Regulation and Compliance, 2009 and Critical Perspectives on International Business, 2009 iii Rationality is a rather ill-defined and potentially loaded concept as we discuss later in the paper. iv Very similar axioms of rationality were set out by von-Neumann and Morgenstern in their work on the theory of games and economic behaviour.(von-Neumann and Morgenstern, 1947). vRepurchasing after 30 days if the asset is expected to rally, to avoid the sale being classified as a “wash sale” and discarded for tax purposes. vi The PIN metric of Easley et al (2002). 50