Problematizing Organ Sales GABRIEL PLEASANTS Abstract—This paper critically explores the global sale of organs from two perspectives. The first belongs to those who argue that the phenomenon is beneficial to both the rich and the poor; it is a “life for life” transaction. The second is the medical human rights position that argues against organ sales because they exploit and destroy the health of the poor. It is found that the latter view is much stronger because it is based on rigorous ethnographies that demonstrate that organ sales in fact only benefit the economically privileged. It is suggested that the sale of organs is merely one symptom of larger global ills. The discourse surrounding the international movement of organs to sick bodies can be illuminated by looking at the words used to describe the phenomenon: “trade” and “traffic.” Those who argue for sales of organs refer to the “organ trade,” a term that calls to mind a legitimate market. They argue from a philosophical/rational perspective that reveres individual autonomy and holds aloft the right of the poor to sell bodily tissue in order to secure a better economic future. They argue that it is doubly beneficial because that bodily tissue also secures the health of the buyer. Proponents of an organ trade argue on the grounds of “life for life” (Radcliffe-Richards et. al. 1950-1952, Cherry 20). The school that opposes the sale of organs describes it as “organ trafficking,” which calls to mind the “human trafficking” of the slave trade. This camp argues from a medical human rights perspective based on years of fieldwork examining organ trafficking among the vulnerable (Scheper-Hughes 1645-1648, Cohen 135-165). The biopolitical discourse is focused on the opposition of the perspective of individual autonomy versus that of medical human rights. Yet the discourse is situated within a cosmology that leaves the foundation of those arguing for an organ trade unquestioned. The ethical argument assumes that the body parts of the poor are assets in a world of globalized capitalism; it also assumes that the poor are autonomous in the same way as those who are not economically constrained. This essay will critically examine the unquestioned foundation of those advocating an organ trade by looking at the devastating repercussions that such a perspective has on the health of the poor as cataloged by those who resist organ trafficking. To undercut the foundation of the argument for organ sales, it is necessary to first examine the structure that has been built upon it. “The Case for Allowing Kidney Sales,” by Janet Radcliffe-Richards and coauthors takes the standpoint of a philosopher, soundly rational and ethical (supposedly). The article is an attempt to rationally overcome the “feelings of outrage and disgust that led to an outright ban on kidney sales” (Radcliffe-Richards et. al. 1950). The argument of the article, very briefly outlined is this: There is a shortage of kidneys for transplantation throughout the world that is leading to the “suffering and death” of many. Living vendors are available to meet this need, to the benefit of those who are sick and dying. It is objected that the living vendors are poor and are being exploited by the rich; however, the economic privilege of the buyers can be used to compensate the sellers, who will also come out with a positive result (“life for life”). Those who argue against the exploitation of the poor are in fact harming the poor through paternalism; the poor are “anxious to sell.” The poor are autonomous individuals with a valuable asset that they should be allowed to sell; they can be protected from exploitation through regulation. The argument for organ sales is based on “FINANCIAL AID to supplement altruistic sacrifice” (Frati 2433-2435). It puts faith in the strength of a regulated market: “People would be free to negotiate a bargain in which both parties win: on the one side a life is saved, on the other a family is lifted from poverty” (Cherry 20). Yet the “life for life” argument is essentially founded on the premise that the parts of the body can be commoditized and capitalized and that they fit within a global capitalist system. Furthermore, the argument assumes the perfection and naturalness of that system in using institutions like the state to regulate the “trade.” The medical human rights perspective that fights the trafficking of human organs implicitly resists the foundation of the “life for life” argument, which I will refer to as a global capitalist cosmology. Nancy Scheper-Hughes explains that, “the kidney as a commodity has emerged as the gold standard in the new body trade, representing the poor person’s ultimate collateral against hunger, debt, and penury” (1645). Scheper-Hughes’s perspective is grounded in years of work gathering ethnographic accounts of “the global traffic in human organs,” rather than in a theoretical perspective. It has led her to equate the “circulation of kidneys” with “established routes of capital from South to North, from East to West, from poorer to more affluent bodies, from black and brown bodies to white ones, and from female to male or from poor, low status men to more affluent men” (Ibid 1645). Rather than a positive, “life for life” choice, ScheperHughes and her colleague, Lawrence Cohen, have found that instead of raising organ sellers up out of their conditions of poverty and marginalization, the sale of their organs was in fact a nonchoice produced by those conditions; it almost always marginalized them further. Cohen’s interviews with women who sold their kidneys in India at first reveal what the “life for life” camp expects: “Yes, I would do it again if I had another to give.” But it is their next words that capture the reality of the organ “trade”: “I would have to” (Cohen 138). Both Scheper-Hughes and Cohen explain how the primary transaction is certainly not beneficial to the organ seller: “Bioethical arguments about the right to buy or sell an organ or other body part are based on Euro-American notions of contract and individual choice. But these create the semblance of ethical choice in an intrinsically unethical context” (148). Unlike those who argue from the rational perspective, those who argue for medical human rights take their argument against organ “trafficking” further, beyond the primary transaction. “The problem with an ethical argument of this sort is the unrelenting presumption that ethics can be reduced to a primary transaction” (148). By examining the “second-order phenomena” that result when a poor, marginalized person sells an organ to one of the world’s affluent minority, the reality of organ transactions on the ground crushes the theoretical argument of ethics and philosophy. Scheper-Hughes and Cohen again provide the soundest foundation because they have compiled years of ethnographic research in a way that few others have. Both anthropologists found that the crucial factors when investigating organ sales were well beyond the limited scope of the primary transaction. In India, Cohen explains that debt plays an instrumental role in kidney sales before and after the primary transaction. In “kidney belts,” moneylenders push more aggressively for debts to be paid knowing that the extremely poor there have at least one asset. The kidney takes a straight path from the poor seller to the affluent buyer, but the other side of the “life for life” equation, the money meant to pull the seller out of poverty, is usually diverted to PAY OFF DEBTS already accrued. South Africa’s Sunday Times tells the story of what happened to Alberty Da Silva’s money: Then, Da Silva’s cash evaporated. His two former girlfriends, the mothers of his children, made off with a large chunk of it and, with what remained, Da Silva bought a USED CAR to look for work. When he couldn’t meet the monthly payments, he downgraded to an old jalopy. When the jalopy broke down almost immediately, he traded it for a second-hand bicycle. The bicycle and a pair of running shoes are all he has left to show for the sale of his kidney—that, and a huge, disfiguring, sabre-like scar across his midsection (8). The experiences of “sellers” before and after they sell an organ demonstrate that it is not simply the first-order phenomenon of the financial transaction, the most important part of the equation for global capitalism (goods for money), that must be considered. Nancy Scheper-Hughes worked with a group of Moldovan kidney sellers and documented the ostracism and stigmatization of that group. One young seller in his late twenties said: “They call us prostitutes….Actually, we are worse than prostitutes because we have sold something we can never get back. We are a disgrace to our families and to our country” (Scheper-Hughes 1647). Lawrence Cohen’s poignant evidence of the consequences for the poor of selling an organ cannot be ignored, either. He tells of a woman who sold her kidney and was beaten by her husband on her scar when she no longer had any of the money that was supposed to get her out of poverty; Cohen calls it, “a postoperative complication of a painful scar that began to hurt when the money ran out” (Cohen 162). The distressing examples of stigma provided by Scheper-Hughes and Cohen have no place in the rational/philosophical argument for kidney sales; that line of argument is only interested in the first-order phenomenon of the financial transaction. It is not surprising, though, because actual ethnographic evidence from organ sellers had no place in it either. When confronted with the second-order phenomena, the ethical argument dodged it by advocating regulation: “The best way to address such problems would be by regulation and perhaps a central purchasing system, to provide screening, counselling, reliable payment, insurance, and Besides ignoring that global capitalism has created the need for the poor to sell their “organ of last resort,” the “life for life” argument presumes that mechanisms, such as regulation by states and other institutional bodies, will be able to resolve the devastating second-order phenomena that result from the extraordinarily harsh conditions that those at the bottom of the world economic system live in. This faith in global capitalism is a result of being enveloped by the dominant paradigm and not being able to see oneself within an unnatural frame. Proponents of a philosophical/rational/ethical argument for organ sales treat their Western epistemology as the only epistemology, and inherently natural. So, too, do they regard global capitalism as the only economic system and biomedicine and its advances as moving toward what it is to be human. Organ transplantation reveals the resistance of the world’s poor and marginalized to the global capitalism of the West, which has been presumed legitimate and natural when it is actually unnatural. We are left with no easy answers like the neat and rational arguments for the sale of organs, however. By finding what isn’t, we are left with the question, What is? Kidneys for Sale: A Reconsideration By Miriam Schulm The Commodification of Human Life Even if legalizing organ sales might inspire more donations, many ethicists reject this approach because they fear where it may lead: to the commodification of human life. Cynthia Cohen from the Kennedy Institute of Ethics at Georgetown writes, "Human beings…are of incomparable ethical worth and admit of no equivalent. Each has a value that is beyond the contingencies of supply and demand or of any other relative estimation. They are priceless. Consequently, to sell an integral human body PART is to corrupt the very meaning of human dignity." Despite these concerns, the black market itself has put a value on human organs—about $5,000 according to most reports. Peter Minowitz, professor of political science at SCU, suggests, "The actuality is there's a thriving market for organs, even crossing global boundaries. So even though the sale of organs may, in itself, violate human dignity, that dignity is being violated now on a fairly large scale, especially among the most desperate. Maybe it would be better for them if we legalized the sale and imposed certain standards on it. It's a very complicated series of considerations, mixing moral judgment with what's going on in the real world." Do No Harm Undoubtedly, increasing the supply of living donors would be good for organ recipients. According to the Organ Procurement and Transplantation Network, about 90 percent of people who receive a livingdonor kidney and 82 percent of those who received a deceased-donor kidney were alive five years after the transplant. But what happens to the donors? "Usually, IN MEDICAL ethics, we are looking at harm and good respective to a single patient," says McLean. "Here we are looking at harm and good for two patients where good is going to accrue to one and potential harm to the other." Generally, kidney donation from a living donor is seen as a relatively safe procedure, as the human body functions adequately with only one kidney. The mortality rate for the removal of a kidney (nephrectomy) is between 0.02 and 0.03 percent, major complications affect 1.5 percent of patients, and minor complications affect 8.5 percent. The University of Maryland Transplant Center states: The risks of donation are similar to those involved with any major surgery, such as bleeding and infection. Death resulting from kidney donation is extremely rare. Current research indicates that kidney donation does not change life expectancy or increase a person’s risks of developing kidney disease or other health problems. While this picture may accurately reflect the experience of donors in first world countries, those in the developing world report less benign outcomes. Madhav Goyal, Ravindra Mehta, Lawrence Schneiderman, and Ashwini Sehgal studied 305 residents of Chennai, India, who had sold their organs. Participants were asked to rate their health status before and after the operation. Eighty-nine percent of the respondents reported at least some decline in their health. "Fifty percent complained of persistent pain at the nephrectomy site and 33 percent complained of long-term back pain." McLean points out that society also incurs risks when someone donates a kidney. "Who pays if the donor is harmed or develops renal failure of unrelated etiology 15 years later and needs a transplant?" she asks. In bioethics, where the first rule is "Do no harm," can the sale of kidneys be judged to conform to this basic principle? Are there better ways to protect donors so that no disproportional harm comes to them? The Problem of Exploitation and Informed Consent The Indian experience points to another of the key objections that have been raised against the sale of organs: the danger that poor people will be exploited in the transaction. Nicky Santos, S.J., visiting scholar at the Ethics Center and an expert on marketing strategy for impoverished market segments, argues strongly that desperation "drives the poor to make choices which are not really in their best interests." Such lopsided transactions may exacerbate already existing inequities, where the rich have access to excellent HEALTH CARE and the poor do not. That was the conclusion of the BELLAGIO Task Force Report to the International Red Cross on "Transplantation, Bodily Integrity, and the International Traffic in Organs": Existing social and political inequities are such that commercialization would put powerless and deprived people at still graver risk. The physical well-being of disadvantaged populations, especially in developing countries, is already placed in jeopardy by a variety of causes, including the hazards of inadequate nutrition, substandard housing, unclean water, and PARASITIC infection. In these circumstances, adding organ sale to this roster would be to subject an already vulnerable group to yet another threat to its physical health and bodily integrity. On the other hand, some view this attitude as paternalistic. "You could raise the question," says Michael McFarland, S.J., "Are the rich or those in power in a position to tell the poor they are not capable of making a decision? Doesn't that violate their human dignity? It seems to me that a person in desperate circumstances could be making a perfectly rational decision that the sale of a kidney is in his or her best interests." McFarland, a Center visiting scholar and the former president of College of the Holy Cross, goes on, "You could see the sale of organs as a way for the poor to derive some benefit from donating an organ, which they wouldn't otherwise get. For example, if a poor person was willing to donate a kidney but couldn't afford to take the time off, wouldn't it be reasonable to allow him or her to be compensated for that time?" More people might be persuaded by this argument if, in fact, kidney sales really did help the poor financially. But in India, donors often did not receive the benefit they expected from the sale of their organs. Ninety-six percent of the people in the study had agreed to the donation to pay off a debt, but six years after the operation, 74 percent of those studied still owed money. Most of the benefit from organ sales goes to middlemen. Havocscope, which monitors black markets, found last May that the average reported amount paid to kidney donors was $5,000, while the average price paid by recipients was $150,000. "The real injustice to the poor is they are getting so little, while those who are involved in these illegal sales are getting all the money," says Rev. Brendan McGuire, vicar general of the Diocese of San Jose. Santos believes that the poor cannot really make free decisions to sell their organs because they are so driven by their dire circumstances. McFarland agrees that the issue of consent is the real sticking point for creating a market for organs. "I think what stops us is the concern about being able to count on a genuine free consent on the part of the donor." But he does not believe any moral absolute makes the sale of kidneys unacceptable. "It comes back to the issue of truly informed consent. Do people understand the risks they are taking on? Are those acceptable risks? Are people capable of making free decisions about whether to take those risks?" Altruism or Justice Informed consent is, of course, as crucial for organ donation as it would be for organ sale. But donation frames the process as a wholly altruistic act. "For a living donor," says McLean, "it may be a chance to help a family member or friend or even a stranger." For a person signing on to donate organs after death, it may be seen as a way to give back or not to die in vain. And for the family of a deceased donor, it's "a way to have a little bit of someone alive in the world," she CONTINUES. Many people value this altruistic aspect of the current system and do not want to see organ donation reduced to a business transaction. But, McFarland asks, "Is it the wisest and most moral policy to run a social system like kidney donation entirely on altruism?" That may be the ideal, he agrees, but since it has not been very effective at meeting the need for organs, it may be better to "strive for justice and not depend totally on altruism." The idea of justice encompasses concern about the exploitation of the poor, but it raises even broader concerns about fairness. These might be summed up in another email we received at the Ethics Center: So what? Is the sale of one's kidney lawful? Morality or ethics has nothing to do with it when you're down and out. Why doesn't someone ask the same of doctors and hospitals when they sell the transplant operation? Why is it when John Q. Public sees a way into the open markets, that he gets hit with the morality/ethical questions? Is it fair that everyone involved in organ transplantation—doctors, hospital, nurses, recipient—gets something out of the process except the donor or the donor’s family? Also, donors on the black market are rarely paid anything approaching what the kidney is worth. Justice might be better served if donors were paid more. In the Indian study, the average price of an organ in 2001 was $1,410. Nobel Laureate in Economics Gary Becker and his colleague Julio Elias have calculated $45,000 as a fair price. Fairer, still say some ethicists, would be a system that pays the donor a figure closer to the actual cost of maintaining a patient on the waiting list for organs, including the cost of dialysis over many years. Arthur Matas and Mark Schnitzler have calculated that a transplant from a living unrelated donor would save at least $94,579. Alternatively, the donor wouldn't necessarily need to be paid to be compensated. McLean reviews some other proposals to give something back to donors: "One suggestion has been to at least offer to pay FUNERAL EXPENSES for a deceased donor because for many people that's a stumbling block. For live donors—and this could be hugely attractive in the current environment —we might offer to cover their health care for the rest of their lives in exchange for doing this good. " Another cut at fairness has recently been adopted by Israel and is advocated in the United States by the private organization Life Sharers. Top priority on Israel's waiting list goes to candidates who have themselves agreed to be donors. Those who don't sign up as donors get a transplant only if there is an excess of organs. All proposals to allow the sale of organs raise ethical as well as medical risks. However, as E.A. Friedman and A.L. Friedman argue in Kidney International, Journal of the International Society of Nephrology: At least debating the controlled initiation and study of potential regimens that may increase donor kidney supply in the future in a scientifically and ethically responsible manner, is better than doing nothing more productive than complaining about the current system's failure.