Selcer 1 Small, Smooth, and Soulless Woman: Wollstonecraft’s Vindication and Burke’s Beautiful When Mary Wollstonecraft published A Vindication on the Rights of Woman in 1792, she was living in a period of social insurrection. The American Revolution had ended in 1783, the French Republic formed in 1792 and brought with it the equity-minded Declaration of the Rights of Man and of the Citizen, and the Reign of Terror had not yet begun. She was impassioned with the defense of equality for women, and employed a sound critique of 18th century gender roles exemplified in Edmund Burke’s 1757 work entitled A Philosophical Enquiry in to the Origin of our Ideas of the sublime and Beautiful. At the center of Burke’s argument was the belief that “the beauty of women is considerably owing to their weakness, or delicacy, and is even enhanced by their timidity, a quality of mind analogous to it” (106). Wollstonecraft, fighting this construction of feminine subordination as desirable, believed that “men have increased that inferiority till women are almost sunk below the standard of rational creatures” (54). Appealing with a doctrine of sensibility dictating that morality must stem from the exercise of one’s own reason, Wollstonecraft argued that women’s constant subordination (a necessary quality in Burke’s characterization of the beautiful) led them to become immoral and ignorant creatures not capable of sustaining the virtue that would be necessary for their immortal souls. Each author’s perception of the female sex is intricately related to their definition of love. Burke states that “the object…of this mixed passion which we call love, is the beauty of the sex” (Burke 39). His definition of love is simply an appreciation for beauty and a desire for to the “possession of certain objects” (Burke 83). Wollstonecraft argues against this simplistic notion, noting that one must show their beloved “that the heart, rather than the senses, is moved” (126). When one merely has a love for the beauty of another, she believes that “love becomes a selfish personal gratification that soon degrades the character” (Wollstonecraft 126). Wollstonecraft’s stance as a Romantic insists that there be some modicum of respect between a man and a woman because “love and esteem are very distinct things” Selcer 2 (84). When women are denied ‘esteem’ by their husbands, they are made ignorant and subservient: “tyrants and sensualists are in the right when they endeavor to keep women in the dark, because the former only want slaves, and the latter a play-thing” (Wollstonecraft 42). In order for women to exist as more than a ‘play-thing’, respect for their status as humans is necessary in addition to love. Burke seems to agree that love and esteem are not the same, and so he assigns ‘love’ to the feminine beauty and ‘admiration’ (or esteem) to the masculine sublime: “there is a wide difference between admiration and love…we submit to what we admire, but we love what submits to us” (Burke 103). Burke’s distinction requires that women cannot be admired because they do not have the power to force submission. Instead, they must admire the men who can force their submission and happily accept a problematic power dynamic labelled as ‘love.’ Wollstonecraft points out that if women only need to be beautiful to excite love, then they become nothing beyond unwitting objects for men to control at their leisure: Women are told from their infancy, and taught by the example of their mothers, that a little knowledge of human weakness, justly termed cunning, softness of temper, outward obedience, and a scrupulous attention to a puerile kind of propriety, will obtain for them the protection of man; and should they be beautiful, every thing else is needless, for, at least, twenty years of their lives. (36) Wollstonecraft is highly interested in the social construction of what ‘natural’ femininity means, and so she invokes the idea that women are raised from “infancy” to believe in these gender roles in a way that doesn’t allow them to see the world any differently from what the man constructs it to be. The “human weakness” she references can be directly linked to one of Burke’s descriptions of what is perfect: “this quality, where it is highest in the female sex, almost always carries with it an idea of weakness and imperfection…beauty in distress is much the most affecting beauty” (100). This portrayal Selcer 3 of ‘distressed beauty’ being the most desirable kind lends credibility to Wollstonecraft’s nearly-satirical use of the word “cunning” to describe a woman’s ability to manipulate by pretending weakness. Wollstonecraft next lists “softness of temper” as a feminine quality, reflected in Burke’s statement that “those which engage our hearts… are the softer virtues; easiness of temper, compassion, kindness and liberality; though certainly those latter are of less immediate and momentous concern to society, and of less dignity. But it is for that reason that they are so amiable” (Burke 100). His description of a soft temper is extremely diminutive, suggesting that women must necessarily be less important and less dignified in order to be beautiful. This is a huge problem for Wollstonecraft in her crusade for female equality because it presents a cultural standard practice of subordination. Wollstonecraft goes on to italicize in the phrase “outward obedience” to emphasize the alarmingly-standard practice of females falsely portraying themselves in order to please men. Finally, she cites a “puerile kind of propriety”, selecting the word ‘puerile’ to show how childish she believes the constant female attention to decorum to be. Burke addresses this ‘puerile propriety’ as necessary, for beauty is a “social quality” in his mind and must require constant attention to one’s manners (39). He says that “the manners give a certain determination to the countenance, which being observed to correspond pretty regularly with them, is capable of joining the effect of certain agreeable qualities of the mind to those of the body” (107). But Wollstonecraft cannot accept the idea that women should constantly cater to their appearance and manners because she believes it retracts from their ability to think and deal with more serious issues. She states that women “acquire manners before morals, and a knowledge of life before they have, from reflection, any acquaintance with the grand ideal outline of human nature” (41). In Wollstonecraft’s mind, women’s education constantly focuses on the corporeal and the senses, and fails to teach them any ability to reason or think for themselves: “the passions thus pampered, whilst the Selcer 4 judgment is left unformed, what can be expected to ensue?—Undoubtedly, a mixture of madness and folly” (83). The disordered and incomplete education of women naturally proceeds into “madness and folly” for Wollstonecraft, a state in which women are not only obedient, but also ignorant and frivolous. Women’s lack of rational education is a huge problem for Wollstonecraft, who believes that emotions exist so “that man by struggling with them might attain a degree of knowledge denied to the brutes” and that “consequently the perfection of our nature and capability of happiness must be estimated by the degree of reason, virtue, and knowledge, that distinguish the individual” (28). But Burke finds these exact intellectual qualities to detract from the beauty of women, saying that “those virtues which cause admiration, and are of the sublime kind, produce terror rather than love. Such as fortitude, justice, wisdom, and the like. Never was any man amiable by force of these qualities” (100). Wollstonecraft is livid at this, unhappy that “the behavior of the whole sex should be modulated to please fools, or men” (124). In the demand that women be beautiful and follow empty-headed conventions of propriety and coquettishness, Wollstonecraft believes that the humanity of women is sacrificed: “I discern not a trace of the human character, neither reason nor passion in this domestic drudge, whose being is absorbed in that of a tyrant’s” (122). All of Wollstonecraft’s arguments against social conventions that rob women of intellectual challenge and rationality come down to one statement: “without knowledge there can be no morality!” (85). Because men like Burke desire that women be attractive, easily-controlled objects, women’s immortal souls and capacity to act ethically are put at risk. Wollstonecraft sums this up with a religious reference to sin: “if men eat of the tree of knowledge, women will come in for a taste; but, from the imperfect cultivation which their understandings now receive, they only attain a knowledge of evil” (37). In light of women’s trained inability to distinguish good from evil, Wollstonecraft is forced to ask whether or not women can truly be humans with souls: “what childish expressions, and how Selcer 5 insignificant is the being—can it be an immortal one?” (36). She believes, that under these conditions, women must be essentially reduced to animals or children. And Burke confirms this suspicion when he speaks of loving women and loving animals as essentially the same thing: “when other animals give us a sense of joy and pleasure in beholding them, (and there are many that do so) they inspire us with sentiments of tenderness and affection towards their persons” (39). The only distinguishing factor between a love for women and animals is the lust that men may experience for women. Wollstonecraft gives a stinging summary of what this means for women: Women are every where in this deplorable state; for, in order to preserve their innocence, as ignorance is courteously termed, truth is hidden from them, and they are made to assume an artificial character before their faculties have acquired any strength. Taught from their infancy that beauty is a woman’s scepter, the mind shapes itself to the body, and roaming round its gilt cage, only seeks to adorn its prison. (64) Wollstonecraft likens women to slaves, or perhaps birds, inside of cages. They exist only to be gazed upon and to be amiable companions when desired. Women are raised to be unintelligent and are manipulated by men to gain false characters that will be pleasing for men to interact with. Left with little besides their vanity and desire to please, women must simply ‘adorn’ their metaphorical prisons and never know what lies beyond the cage. Burke states that “those persons who creep into the hearts of most people…are never persons of shining qualities, nor strong virtues. It is rather the soft green of the soul on which we rest our eyes, that are fatigued with beholding more glaring objects” (101). He, and many of the men of the 18th century, are almost wholly concerned with training women to be submissive and pleasing. This expectation includes a demand that women are small, smooth, delicate, weak, and have a non-angular ‘variety in the Selcer 6 direction of the parts’ (107). Wollstonecraft responds to these diminutive traits of desirability by encouraging women to exercise their minds and bodies into robustness, and asking that female education be reformed so that women’s immortal souls are not at risk or wallowing in evil. The implication that women must give up their humanness to be desirable is incredibly problematic for Wollstonecraft, and so she takes advantage of her historical moment of ideological revolution in order to introduce important and powerful ideas into the cultural discourse of her age.