Judt: The Past is Another Country Three arguments: (1) “the special character of the wartime experience in continental Europe, and the ways in which the memory of that experience was distorted, sublimated, and appropriated, bequeathed to the postwar era an identity that was fundamentally false, dependent upon the erection of an unnatural and unsustainable frontier between past and present in European public memory. (2) “the ways in which the official versions of the war and postwar era have unraveled in recent years are indicative of unresolved problems which lie at the center of the present continental crisis”, (3) there are new “myths and mis-memories” at play post 1990. The reality: “most of occupied Europe either collaborated with the occupying forces (a minority) or accepted with resignation and equanimity the presence and activities of the German forces (a majority)” (85). The myth: “The first [myth] was the universally-acknowledged claim that responsibility for the war, its sufferings and its crimes, lay with the Germans” (87). “The presence of concentration camps in Poland, Czechoslovakia, and even France could thus readily be forgotten, or simply ascribed to the occupying power, with attention diverted from the fact that many of these camps were staffed by nonGermans and…had been established and in operation before the German occupation began” (87). He also makes the point that the Nuremburg trials limited the scope of guilt for the war to a select group of Nazis, thus helping those like the Soviets, who “wished to avoid any discussion of broader moral and judicial questions which might draw attention to the Soviet Union’s own practices before and during the war” (ibid) He also mentions that in 1948 over half a million former Nazis received amnesty in Austria, “a process that would have been all but unthinkable in 1948” (88). Ethnic expulsion: At the end of page 88 and beginning of 89, he discusses post-war forced relocations/expulsions of Germans. “Beyond its significance for postwar German domestic politics (which were considerable), this process had a marked impact upon the states whence these Germans came. Poland and Hungary (as well as Western Germany itself) now become ethnically homogenous states as never before. Others felt free to indulge in further exercises in ethnic purification”. But Europe did not have misgivings about this. “On the contrary: a clear and quick distinction was made between the sorts of collective violence and punishment visited on these lands by German war criminals, and the mass, racially motivated purges represented by these expulsions and undertaken by freely-elected or newlyliberated national authorities” (89). Two memories: “that of things done to ‘us’ by Germans in the war, and the rather different recollection of things (however similar) done by ‘us’ to ‘others’ after the war…Two moral vocabularies, two sorts of reasoning, two different parts. In this circumstance, the uncomfortably confusing recollection of things done by us to others during the war (i.e. under German auspices) got conveniently lost” (89). Resistance Myth: “to be innocent a nation had to have resisted, and to have done so in its overwhelming majority, a claim that was perforce made and pedagogically enforced all over Europe” (89-90). He asks why genuine resisters acquiesced in the myth. Two reasons. “In the first case, it was necessary somehow to restore a minimal level of cohesion to civil society and to reestablish the authority and legitimacy of the state” (90). Secondly, he says the communists “could hope to capitalize on their war record by claiming to have spoken for the nation in its time of trial” (91).They also took advantage of the idea of their being a few traitors in order to purge their opponents (91). Punishment: He says most of the retributive attacks (antifascist executions, etc.) took place before the axis countries were liberated, and so unofficially. Officially, the process was “half-hearted”. “In Austria, 130,000 persons were investigated for war crimes; of these 23,000 were tried, 13,600 found guilty, 43 sentenced to death….and 30 actually executed” (93). “In both France and Austria…the emphasis was clearly placed upon the need to reduce to the minimum the number of convictable and convicted persons, reserve for this select few a sort of symbolic and representative function as criminals and traitors, and leave the rest of the social fabric untouched” (ibid). 1948 Myths: He argues that because there were no post war peace treaties officially ending and framing the war, memories became confused when it transitioned in 4849 to concern over the division of Germany and the shaping of the Cold War order (95). He then turns to talk about the “foundation myths” of “Europe” and the project of Europe, which began from 1948. HE discusses the country-specific myths of the new Europe to the middle of page 97. To page 108 he gives a variety of examples of problematic national memories / myths. Then he turns to modern myths. Social Function of Taboo: “In return for the myth of an ethically-respectable past and an impeccably untainted identification with a reborn Europe, we have been spared the sorts of language and attitudes which so polluted and degraded the public realm between the wars” – an argument in favor of taboos. The problem: “These constraints are now loosened” (108). And “[a]t a time when Euro-chat has turned to the happy topic of disappearing customs borders, the frontiers of memory remain solidly in place” (112). Note: There are a lot of specific examples in the paper, which I have not listed here. It is always good to know examples, since they illustrate the point, and since you can include them in arguments you make in your papers, depending on the topic.