ARE THE CONCEPTS OF REALISM AND EXPRESSIONISM CONTRADICTORY IN RELATION TO THE PHOTOGRAPHIC MOVING IMAGE? (2000) The invention of photography in the 19th century was a significant turning point for art’s function and conceptualisation. For the first time, a man had the oppurtunity to create an absolute copy of an image of the physical world. This realisation brought western painting—which until then was mainly concerned with “imitating” nature-- to an awkward position: if photography was to cover the role of the imitation, what would painting’s contribution to art would be? At this moment, the concept of imitation as art’s primal purpose was abandoned and notions as realism and expressionism were introduced in art theory. These ideas did not limit themselves to painting criticism but were applied to the whole of the art world. With the invention of the cinema at the beginning of our century, the question whether natural representation contradicts artistic expression became a major one, since cinema was more “real” than anything else the art establishment has seen then. Posing an exact definition of the concept of “realism” is not posssible. First of all, realism is based on a series of concepts which are problematic themselves, such as “reality” “represantation”, “perception” and others. At the same time, the idea of realism has been used in very different ways and sub-divisions of realism (between which there were major differences) have imerged: naturalism, social realism, expressive realism and others. However, if we want to give a rough definition of the concept of “realism”, it is “the represantation of things as they are and not in some imagined perception”, as William Gaunt suggests. For realism, therefore, imitation becomes a key-concept. The value of a piece of art is mainly (if not totally) dependent on its relation (“lookalike-ness”) with the image of the real world it is supposed to represent. In this sence, the role of the artist is limited to that of the artisan, a perfect craftsman who has practically learned how to copy nature with its paint. Strictly realistic creation becomes an almost mechanical process where the space for personal expression is very limitied. In cinema (the moving photographic image), realism takes a slightly different turn, since the imitation of the world as such is allready covered by what Maya Deren calls the “ “Closed-Circuit of the Photographic Process”, the fact that there is no human intervention betweenthe actual object and its copy and on light sensitive material, an exclusion of the human factor which is “responsibleboth for the absolute fidelity of the photographic process and for the widespread convinction that a photographic medium cannot be itself, a creative form”. Therefore, in the cinema, realism is something deeper than mere imitation of appearances, it is what Roberto Rossellini calls “the artistic form of the truth”. Of course this is one of the ways cinematic realism can be viewed for others, as for the french “Cinema-Veritè” movement, film should be reduced to absolute naturalism, where artistic intervation is kept to a minimum. It is important to keep in mind, though, that realism is strongly connected to the earliest definitions and that “the guiding myth[…] a recreation of the world in its own image, an image unberdened by the freedom of interpretation of the artist”, as A.Bazin puts it. The more cinema progressed as an art form though the more this definition was abandoned. Expressionism, on the other hand, is a much more esoteric way of expression/recreation. Stemming from a reaction to the impressionists’ preoccupation with light and appearances, “expressionism was[…] a term applied to the work of those artists who believed that there was much more to the world than simply what their eyes saw”. Again this definition is quite problematic, since “all art, as Tudor argues, involves some form of ‘distortion’, some form of subjectivity, and therefore all art can be concidered more or less “expressionist”. From the very point that systems of human perception and therefor consciousness are used, subjectivity enters. As Lawson argues, “Vision is a psychological as well as mechanical process” and the psyche carries information, which unavoidably interferes. No image can have an objective substance; it only exists when a light receiver (a retina, a lens) exists as well. Therfore all art is by the human nature more or less subjective. However that fact alone does not make it necessarily what is known as “expressionist”. How can expessionism manifest itself in the field of the moving image? As in pictirial expressionism, abstraction can be a means of self-expression (as supposed to outside impression). The difference, however, between pictorial and cinematic expression is that in the latter time plays an important role: not only the images themselves, but also their placing within a specific context or their development in time can create abstract effect. In the history of cinema, the main reference to expressionism usually takes place in the analysis of the 20’s German silent film. In the case of Weimar cinema, the idea of expressionism was mainly applied to ways of acting and set design, it was, in other words, a theatrical expressionism. This is not the case in modern film and video, where expressionism should be traced in the filming and editing of the sequences themselves, for the art of cinema is not primarily the art of staging a concept, but rather of representing a concept through the lens. “The things themselves, without ceasing to be what they are, become a sign or a symbol” , by the very way they are filmed or placed within a particular context. “The great artists […] have always been able to combine the two tendencies [realism and expressionism]. They have allotted to each its proper place in the hierarchy of things, holding reality at their command and molding it at will into the fabric of their art” , Bazin argues. It was soon realised that imitation of nature by itself is not sufficient for appreciating the value of art. Artists attempted to find a way to idealise nature and thus, through making it look more beautiful, express their personal aesthetical and conceptual concerns. “All efforts necessarily came down to choosing the best parts of Nature, in order to form an exquisite whole that was more perfect than Nature itself, without for all that ceasing to be natural” , as Tzvetan Todorov argues. A cinematic example of this idea of the idealisation of nature is the case of the expressionist director Fritz Lang, who “found it more convenient to recreate nature in the studio or in similar circumstances”, as Mitry suggests. Although his sets were very similar to natural settings and his stories were supposed to take place in natural contexts, his need for personal expression demanded that he could manipulate his environment as much it was necessary. In this sense, realism moves to a point where it is actually much more mediated without ever being removed from its representational purpose, a mediation based on the artist himself, his very own experiences and purpose. Thus the distinction between what is objective and what is subjective is blurred: “The artist has not created something ‘unreal’, but he has used the camera to expose new aspects of the external world, communicating his attitude towards it” . For such an approach, Parker Tyler uses the terms “illusionist realism” and “realist illusion”, which in cinematic mean to use the camera as an instrument of rediscovering the world around us. The concept of abstraction is of great importance here. For it is the way in which the artist’s lens blurs the image that his personal expression comes through. As Lawson argues: “The concept is abstracted from ordinary observation; it is a product of the mind. It is not necessarily irrational: abstract thought can be extremely logical, but aesthetic abstraction asserts the primacy of inner experience” . Of course such a definition of realism is extremely broad and poses problems to distinguishing realism from expressionism. One of the most influential figures in the history of film theory, who wrote on the creative use of reality is Maya Deren, an underground American film director. In fact, Deren believed that this is exactly the purpose and essence of cinema: to start from a representational image, but manipulate it as to arrive to very abstract conclusions. “Photography, being itself the reality or the equivalent therof, can use its own reality as a metaphor for ideas and abstractions” , as she suggests. Editing plays here a major role, as “it establishes a context, a form which transfigures them [the shots] without distorting their aspect, diminishing their reality and authority, or impoverishing that variety of potential functions which is the characteristic dimension of reality” . Shots are used in a functional way in order to serve a purpose within a self-ruled context. Here we enter the field of structuralism, in which the content of a particle is not important as such, but is necessarily dependent on the whole. This approach retains the spatial characteristics of realism, but alters its time structure as a means of personal expression. We have seen so far that the concepts of “realism” and “expressionism” are not necessarily contradictory and that the ideas that are connected to them can coincide and apply to both of them. Therefore, it is useful to establish a term that combines that two concepts. This terms is “expressive realism”, an idea that emerged in the previous century, but which can probably be applied to art even today. Catherine Belsey quotes: “The aristotelean concept of art as mimesis, the imitation of reality, was currect throughout the Renaissance and particularly during the eighteenth century. Expressive realism was the product of the fusion of this concept with the new Romantic conviction that poetry, as the ‘spontaneous overflow of powerful feelings’” . The most impressive and historically important cinematic representative of expressive realism is the Russian avant-garde film-maker Dziga Vertov. Vertov developed the theory of the “kino-eye”, according to which the purpose of cinema is to record “life-as-itis”, but recontextualise in the post-production phase in order to appreciate images not only for their meaning but also expressive formal qualities. As Hans Richter argues, “Vertov located the expressiveness of the object photographed in the expressiveness of movement. Faces, trees, clouds, a falling drop of blood became in the rhythm of Vertov’s series of images, a metrical language of the document – became film poetry” . Vertov believed in the power of the camera to represent to us a world we have not been aware of, which still consists of elements that are around us in our everyday experiences. “The secret may be in an angle, or an arrangement of light, or an arrangement of movement” , as John Grierson suggests in order to get an image whose expressionism depends on its very representational formal qualities. In other words, a realist image has got not only meaning, but also expressive value based on the possibilities of its form.