On friendship. Aristotelian themes and political associations I am delighted to be able to speak among pupils and friends honoring the memory of Prof. Jacques Phytilis. Although, much to my chagrin, I did not have the opportunity of becoming either a pupil or a friend, I had the pleasure of meeting him on some occasions. I still vividly recall his generous offer to serve as my guide at the Louvre, a museum he felt very much at home. Unfortunately, I could not visit Paris while he was there. But let us suppose we did in fact meet at the Louvre and did in fact stand in front of Medusa's raft (and so many other great paintings) and did discover ideas and sensitivities we shared in common and took a liking in each other. Could we have ever been or become friends? Theoretically yes, and Professor Phytillis certainly had all these enviable qualities and gifts of character and mind that made him such an attractive and generous personality. This is, of course, a speculative question and I will not attempt to answer it here. Instead I would like to take this opportunity for raising some more general questions. What does it take for somebody to become a friend of another person? When are we friends, why are we friends and what is the value of friendship? Of course, being friends does not necessarily coincide with the usage of the word. When the end of a love affair is announced with the rhetorical exhoration "let us remain friends", we can rest assured that in most cases this means "I don't want to be with you any more" and it is not an invitation to a new edition of an old relationship. Similarly, when two arch-enemies shake hands and address each other as friends this should not be taken at its face value. It may well mark the end of a period of belligerence and the beginning of peace, but not really friendship. Talk of friendship is usually empty and friends certainly do not talk too much about friendship unless their friendship is in a crisis. I think that we would all agree that a life without friends would be an impoverished kind of life. But why should we say this, why do we need friends and what kind of friendships enrich our lives? Many intersting questions come up here. When exactly is a friendship one of the enriching kind, can we perhaps live well without friends and maybe, further, when we enter into a relationship with others as friends should we care for those excluded? Leaning on Aristotle (and borrowing heavily from him) I would like to sketch some answers to these questions and then try to see what kind of importance friendship may or many not have for political life. What is friendship? Aristotle gives a general characterization of friendhip that seems very plausible and intuitively appealing. It is a relation of mutual liking between two persons of a non-egoistic or instrumental kind. We care for our friend and wish him or her good for her own sake, not our own. Indeed putting on a good face in order to feign intimacy and maximize one's profits or pleasure or entertaining superficial relations that help us carry the day in professional or social dealings can hardly be acknowledged as instances of friendship. We all know that. Aristotle who employs, interestingly enough, a much broader conception of friendship than we do - he included relations of kinship as instances of friendship and regarded friendship as relevant in the polis - distinguishes further among three types (τριών 1 όντων δι' α φιλούσιν, δια το ηδύ, δια το χρήσιμον, δια την αρετήν, 1155b27) of friendship depending on the essential motive for bonding. What do we seek by forming friendships? We have friendships that are based on pleasure (we do not have to take pleasure in its most extreme form or literal sense), friendships of advantage and friendships that are based on the recognition of moral goodness. It only the latter form is actually friendship per se, τελεία φιλία. Why is it perfect? The idea behind it is that it expresses the very essense of friendship in its most ideal form because friendship in its most ideal form is to be mutually inclined to mean good and to do good to another person for its own sake and not for one's own as we just saw (There is a very clear statement to this effect in Rhetoric 2.4). At the face of it this seems again correct. But of course, this requirement might be too strict to capture real friendship among real people. Friendship between saints and moral heroes may be the purest expression of the idea and we deeply admire those who can reach a level of self-negating and self-sacrificing love for the other. But I would tend to believe that these are extreme cases not only in terms of the scarsity of really virtuous people but also in terms of the rarity of the occasions that justify such a behavior. Saintly and heroic response is asked in extraordinary situations but we are in need for friendship in situations of human normality. So as it goes we should ask if friendship is possible among people who cannot be good and virtuous absolutely and exclusively, whose motivational framework is mixed, who are capable of doing good to others but are also prone to seek their own narrow or broader self-interest. Can these people be friends and have friends? Perfect friendship involves a relation of love (στέργειν), trust and mutual acknowledgement of each other's excellence of character. Really virtuous people who have morally and intellectually mastered their own life feel attracted to tokens of equal excellence and tend to form permanent relations when they encounter individuals that share the same capacity and urge for excellence. This highly admirable ideal can only be shared by individuals that are equals in excellence of character. But this is a rare phenomenon for various reasons. Most commonly, friendship is a relation that may be inchoate or incomplete. We often get carried away by first impressions, we are sometimes overwhelmed by what we think we see in the other, it oftens happens that a relation does not fulfill its initial promise. This does not need to be lethal for the relation. We accept imperfection and we focus on what is good and rewarding. Friends with great minds and weak characters, generosity and inconsistency, we take them as they are and negotiate some improvements perhaps. So in a sense, Aristotle cannot restrict the case of frienship of virtue and good character only to the perfect and complete kind. But there is also a further reason. People are unequal in kind (at least according to Aristotle) and sometimes the fuel of attraction has it source in some kind of disparity of status. We look up to superior knowledge or wisdom or judgement and we suppose that at least the benevolently inclined among those who possess this kind of excellence will feel attracted to share it with persons they love. What should we say about the imperfect and inferior types of friendship that feed on pleasure and advantage? Can friendship be based on such accidental and contigent faculties? Isn't real friendship supposed to be resting on essential and not accidental qualities and is it not that we become excellent by achieving these qualities? This is 2 perfectly true but there is an addendum we should not underestimate here. On the one hand, Aristotle certainly allows pure friendship to be also pleasureable and advantageous for the parties. Greek ethics are more far-sighted in this respect than their modern successors. It is, of course, obvious that Aristotle would not consider business relationships, professional affiliations and fleeting encounters of any kind as per se a foundation of friendship. On the other hand pleasure and advantage are constants of human life and any conception of friendship would be justified in taking them seriously. Any kind of human activity that relies on human interaction and cooperation may be in need of some more permanent and stable underpinning than "mere rational self-interest" based on strict reciprocity. Friendship allows a mutuality that is more relaxed, more human, more beautiful: a mutuality that cultivates awareness of common interests beyond short-term profit making or immediate gratification. Even the more instrumentalized world of profession, economy, social and political interaction is in deep need of the pleasures, the benefits and the value of friendship. A businessman looks after his clients because he wants them to be pleased and come back. This is no friendship but good business acumen. But with time he learns to know his clients better and he wishes them well not only because they are essential to his business but because through their special relation of mutual advantage a special concern for the other has grown out of it. This special concern is causally triggered by the pre-established business relationship of advantage and profit but it is not based on it. It is more personal and human and can thus be represented as a form of friendly care for the other on its own term. As one of the first commentators on Aristotelian friendship has observed, "(h)ere then one has a complex and subtle mixture of selfseeking and unself-interested well-wishing and well-doing. The overriding concern of the advantage-friend is for his own profit. But this does not mean that every action and wish of his is ultimately aimed at the realization of something profitable to himself."1 To be sure, most economic transactions and interactions of business nature are nowadays faceless and impersonal. No doubt, the friendships of advantage Aristotle had in mind, do not seem very likely in the spheres of globalized economy. Still, reflecting on the value and the prospects of more authentic, less alienated relations of interest and the admittedly inferior type of friendship that emanates from them may be a ground of restrained optimism. If others are important for us, we have a very compelling reason to learn to care for them for their own sake, not our own. But there is a nagging question here. If what we have just described are the plausible kinds of friendship, what is the value of φιλία for our life, what reasons do we have to entertain and develop intimate relations of love and care with close friends? If we care for the good of our friend for his own sake only, why is that so important for our life? Aristotle intimates in many ways that having friendships of the superior kind, friendships in goodness and excellence contributes to human flourishing. This is a deeply moving assumption but it is not self-evident. For instance, people of excellence who seek absolute goodness, what need do they really have of friendship? Can't they seek and attain goodness on their own? But the Aristotelian thesis seems to be that goodness is knowledge of oneself and this is something that can be reached 1 John M. Cooper, p. 314. 3 not just through socratic elenchos but rather through some pattern of comparative learning integrated as a parameter of our own life. A friend is thus a kind of second self (1213a10 MM: "τοιούτος οίος έτερος είναι εγώ") in which one's own self is mirrored. However, one should not assume that the mere availability of comparison of strengths and weakness makes the trick. We don't need friends to see and compare. We see people everywhere on the street, in the marketplace, in the theater, in one's professional space, in social gatherings. But we can never check ourselves adequately against all these personae. We can never really know what is true and what is false, what is objective and what is subjective because looking at others from a perspective has a distorting effect. Afterall, goodness in practical matters is not just a matter of verification, but rather a challenge of active achievement based on self-knowledge. As it is easy to fool oneself either by blindly admiring whatever shines or ignoring what remains hidden in the dark, so it is equally easy to overestimate one's own capacities and qualities and fall victim of self-deception. Here enters friendship. The gist of the argument lies in the fact that a friend exemplifies qualities that are common or purport to be common. Real friendship of the excellent kind is a truthful and well-intended mirror of oneself, we can trust and learn from. This is the context that enables constructive comparison as a foundation for common flourishing among friends. Friendship is not only an invaluable support for the project of excellence through selfknowledge. Friendship is also a pleasurable good that keeps as alive and active by helping us remain in the game and keep the ball rolling. Through friendship we participate in far more complex projects of experience that we would ever have been capable of carrying out on our own. No doubt, there are many important activities and responsibilities that can only be borne individually, we think and feel on our own and we literaly live and die on our own. It is one's own life that we have to lead and be responsible for. We are indeed individuals but there is hardly any activity that is not based and also enhanced through the intermediation of others. Of course, we think and feel on our own but thinking and feeling with others is far more than a metaphor. It might be dabatable to what extent we are rational choosers, but what we do choose most of all is life with others and thus we form part of more complex and intensive web of life. As Aristotle himself poignantly puts it, "people think that the happy must live pleasantly: well, for an isolated person life is difficult, for being continuously active is not easy by oneself, but it is easier in the company of people different from oneself, and in relation to others. Consequently his activity will be more continuous, being pleasant in itself, which is a necessary condition of blessedness; for the good man, in so far as he is good, delights in actions in accordance with excellence and is disgusted by those, flowing from badness, just as a musical expert takes pleasure in fine melodies and is distressed at worthless ones. Living in company of good people may also provide a training of excellence, as Theognis says." (1117a10-15) It is not astonishing that contemporary research carried out in many fields seems somehow to corroborate the truth of the Aristotelian insights. Loneliness is certainly unhealthy for the physical and mental balance of human beings and people lacking the capacity to form strong emotional connections and a meaningful relationship are prone to all sorts of illness and decay. Still, Aristotle's point does not form part of a compendium for good health, it is a philosophy of good life. Although he does not deny that there may be people capable 4 of leading good and successful lives based exclusively on their own, he urges us to take the more natural path of common love and support. Imperfect creatures as we are, we cannot face the adversity and complexity - perhaps even the brevity - of life on our own. His ideas and fragmented arguments on friendship present an admirable insight into a good of life that transcends its individual significance and acquires a social and political dimension. The question of why and how we should live becomes a question of with whom we should live. We should learn to value and understand the point of living in full awareness with others we care for. This means, of course, that we should learn to assume responsibility for others, importantly associated as they are with our lives. This means further that we should live consciously with an attitude of love and concern for those we chose as companions, but it also means conversely that we do not owe that much to those who are not and cannot be our friends. Friendship then seems to be releasing us from two kinds of shackles, those of an egoistic self living only a life of one's own and those of a super altruistic and impartial self belonging to humanity as such. If we understand ourselves as part of everybody else, we abolish the sense of a self. If on the other hand we think only of the self, we abolish the cognitive and ethical potential that lies in recognizing and bonding with the other. Aristotle always recognized a political relevance for his understanding of friendship. Living with others in the polis is indeed a form of friendship and this is something we tend to forget or rather underplay in our reading of democracy only as conflict. Democracy is among other things a framework institutionally accommodating difference and disagreement and it is good so. But contemporary rule of law democracies tend to loose their effectiveness in promoting their legitimate values when they become forgetful of the common good and, most of all, the common bond that unites citizens. The idea of political friendship is not meant as an ideological mechanism of control and manipulation enforcing a kind of pseudo-consensus. It should rather be understood as an opportunity that empowers citizenship by involving everyone in each other's good. As it goes, friendship among citizens will also ask us to take an active stance towards non-citizens, whether they are peoples under oppressive regimes, or μέτοικοι, in search of a better future in our own polis. Friendship after all is a common and mutual endeavour for the good, not an exclusive club for the promotion of one's interest to the detriment of others. Athens, 3. 6. 2013 Konstantinos Papageorgiou, University of Athens 5