1 Virginia Commonwealth University August 14, 2012 One of the things every writing teacher knows is that students—whether they’re aware of it or not—are composition theorists. They work from a set of presumptions, assumptions, and preconceptions about how to get school writing done, and these guide their writing behaviors. For instance, I’ve heard students say “I need a deadline if I’m going to do my best work. I need to feel the pressure.” This theory works from the premise that there’s a relationship between the scarcity of time to write and a writer’s level of performance—the less time the better. Another theory that I frequently hear is that it’s a bad idea to begin writing before you have anything to say. Now, this proposition, like any, certainly has some truth to it in certain situations. When writing an essay exam, for example, it is helpful to know what you’re going to say before you say it. But as a broadly applied concept, the theory is problematic. To always know what you’re going to say before you say it closes off sustained inquiry into a topic. It commits the writer to a particular point of view, and rigs the process so that there is a predetermined outcome. This theory is often manifested in students’ attitude towards the thesis statement. When asked about their research routines, nearly sixty percent of the students in a recent study said that they thought they need “to know their thesis early on.” It’s possible that these students meant tentative thesis but I’m pretty certain they meant the final claim or proposition around which they plan to build their papers. I’ve taken to calling this the “thug thesis” or the “bully thesis” because it strong-arms the process, muscling information into obedience with preconceived ideas. Where does this leave discovery, which is at the heart of academic inquiry? It essentially eliminates it because discovery is inconvenient. Don’t mess with the plan! This is particularly problematic in writing programs that 2 emphasize inquiry, like yours (and mine), not only because it short-circuits discovery but because it signals that suspending judgment—something essential in exploring a question—is a thing to be avoided at all costs. Surfacing these theories in the classroom—making them a part of the conversation in a nonjudgmental way—is one of the things that should be a part of the metacognitive instruction we do in a writing class. That way, we might encourage the “unlearning” of theories that don’t serve student writers well. This also encourages transfer of knowledge, so that students can more clearly see how to apply what they’ve learned in novel writing situations. Writing teachers have theories, too, about why we’re teaching what we teach, what we hope students will learn, and how they might apply what they’ve learned when they leave us. Many of us are sufficiently wedded to these theories that they form a kind of ideology to which we’re deeply committed. I know I feel that way. We can look at our ideologies in all sorts of ways. For example, how do we construct our students, as people in need of correction (the deficit model) or as people with linguistic resources that can be harnessed and built on (the surplus model). Scholarship in composition studies also provides us with taxonomies to describe our methods. For example, teachers who invite personal writing are “expressivists” and those who emphasize product at the expense of process are “current-traditionalists.” But I’d like to simplify this in a way that I hope is helpful. I’m going to argue that there are two ideological positions that make the most difference in how we teach writing. They are our stance towards invention, and our cognitive theories about learning. The cognitive scientist John Bruer nicely lays out the four cognitive theories each of us might subscribe to and he begins with a story. He asks us to imagine that a tiny country is being attacked by a larger one. Outgunned and outnumbered, the country does have one asset: the current world chess champion. Working from the assumption that the chess champion might apply his superior strategic 3 knowledge and wit to battling the invading nation, the small country’s prime minister asks the chess champ for help. This tale, of course, highlights theories about knowledge transfer. The prime minister figures that chess and military strategy share certain characteristics. But is she right? Can the chess expert save the country? Well, that depends on your theory of intelligence. Bruer proposes four: 1. The mind is a muscle. The first is rather old fashioned, and I suspect the least relevant. This theory proposes that the mind is like a muscle, and learning comes from exercising it. This is the pedagogy of the 18th and 19th centuries that had students memorize Latin, perform grammatical or logic exercises. There’s no empirical support for this theory, so while the chess champion may have a limber mind that alone probably won’t make her a better military strategist. 2. General reasoning and thinking strategies. This theory is embraced by those of us—and this always included me—who believe that in a writing class we are teaching students how to think critically, and these thinking skills should come in handy in any situation in which thinking is required. The evidence suggests that general reasoning and thinking strategies don’t typically transfer, so the logical superiority of the chess champion may be little help in defending the nation. Composition scholar David Russell’s metaphor about teaching “ball-handling skills” is apt here: can anyone be taught ball-handling skills that apply to both tennis and basketball? 3. Thinking is domain-specific. The premise here is that each discipline deploys different reasoning strategies, and that these are always tied to particular context. This seems particularly true in domains that require considerable factual knowledge. If true, and there is evidence that it is, then writing classes in the disciplines would be more effective than a general 4 first year writing class. It also implies that being good a chess may have nothing to do with being good at military strategy. 4. Intelligent novice. Left with the previous three theories of intelligence, first-year writing teachers seem to be wasting everyone’s time. But Bruer describes a “new synthesis” of these theories--the intelligent novice—that provides a foundation for not as much what we teach but how we teach. The intelligent novice is someone who, while lacking expertise, is able to apply some general thinking skills, especially metacognition, to solve problems in an unfamiliar domain. The intelligent novice learns to see the similarities between different contexts and knows what general strategies might be relevant. This theory suggests that if our chess master is good at thinking about his thinking, then she might indeed help save her country. I find in Bruer’s intelligent novice a theory that strongly supports much of what we do in first year writing, if we not only teach composing and rhetorical strategies but we also when they’re useful. Where we stand on rhetorical invention is the other key element of our ideology as writing teachers, and I think it’s particularly relevant to those of us who emphasize inquiry-based learning. Recall that the term invention comes from classical rhetoric, and was specifically used to describe how a speaker might choose the appropriate propositions that could be argued in a particular context and for a particular purpose: advocating a policy, celebrating an achievement, or debating a legal issue. Note that these propositions were typically existing arguments the speaker might choose from. In contemporary writing instruction, invention has assumed a different meaning. As Richard Larson pointed out many years ago, the challenge for student writers these days is discovering whether they have anything to say at all about something: “[T]he task is to help students see what is of interest and value in their experiences, to enable them to recognize when something they see or read or feel warrants a response from them” (127). The classical version of invention isn’t irrelevant, Larson notes, when students already “have 5 convictions to express.” I’m thinking, in particular, of the thug thesis I mentioned earlier. But nearly every first-year writing class incorporates invention in the modern sense, teaching students to freewrite, cluster, brainstorm, generate questions, list, and any number of other methods that help them use language to think. Few of us are against this kind of invention. Writing to learn was, after all, one of the significant gifts of the writing process movement in the sixties and seventies. But often we teach these invention strategies as an obligation or an exercise with little connection to a range of writing situations beyond the personal essay. The ideological divide, then, is between instructors who see writing to learn as fundamental to a range of writing tasks and those who see it as secondary to the other big concern in writing instruction: the logical arrangement of information. My position is that the best teachers of inquiry-based writing instruction are ideologues of the first proposition. The diagram below might help clarify this. 6 Imagine dividing the universe of writing tasks into two broad categories: those in which writers’ initial motive is to find out something and those in which writers attempt to prove what they already know. We’ll call the first “open” writing, and borrowing from Peter Elbow, we’ll call the other “direct” writing. Since the purpose of open writing is discovery, then invention—at least in the modern sense— is primary. In an inquiry-based class, invention is focused on exploring the investigator’s questions. This may lead ultimately to a conventional argumentative essay after writers discover their thesis but it might also lead to more exploratory genres like the Montaigian essay with its delayed thesis. On the other hand, instruction that emphasizes direct writing is much more likely to encourage students to arrive at a clear purpose for their projects as soon as possible so that they can focus on organizing their presentation. Invention is largely irrelevant in this scheme except in the classical sense of teaching the importance of finding an existing proposition that fits the facts. There may be discovery in a classroom focusing on direct writing but it is much less likely. I want to emphasize that one method of instruction is no “better” than the other. There are, for instance, plenty of writing situations in which the strategies that direct writing most encourages— moving quickly to clarify a purpose and organizing material around it—are very powerful. I’m also arguing here that we don’t necessarily teach one method in exclusion to the other; in fact, as the diagram suggests, the two can be combined. However, I am suggesting that in an inquiry-based writing class, open writing—and the importance of modern invention—combine with the theory of the intelligent novice to create learning environments where first-year students are most likely to experience what the Boyer Commission called “a culture of inquiry,” one in which students “share an adventure of discovery.“ 7