November 20, 2012 Questions for Week 13 Is there anything one might be able to say with objective modal language that wouldn't be able to say in the subjective, normative modal language? That is, it sounds, for all that has been said, that one could express everything one says with "It is impossible for X to be Y" with "In saying that something is X, one is thereby committed to its not being Y", and I see no reason that, in principle, one couldn't continue to do so with embeddings, etc. If this is right it, it seems like you take the discourses to be so similar that the only real distinction will be one of emphasis. What do each forms of discourse allow us to do or say that we simply could not do in the other, if anything? -Billy Eck In chapter 6 of Between Saying and Doing, Brandom claims that “A single object [sic: subject] just is what ought not to have incompatible commitments...it is an essential individuating feature of the metaphysical categorical sortal metaconcept subject that subjects have the metaproperty of normatively repelling incompatibilities” (192). Here Brandom suggests that repelling incompatibilities is both necessary and sufficient for being a subject. It seems convincing that this is a necessary condition (given that we take material inference to normatively govern the laws of thought) but is it also sufficient? Is there nothing more to being a subject than the normative requirement of having compatible commitments? Laura Davis [Cf. Aristotle on objects being distinguished from properties by not having opposites.] Brandom claims that an essential part of having a commitment is taking responsibility for weeding out incompatibilities between that commitment and other commitments. One is normatively obliged to repair incompatibilities. I wonder if that obligation is defeasible. As Harman has pointed out, it may be best for one to knowingly hold incompatible beliefs, while leaving the incompatibility relatively isolated, because an agent might not see a way to modify her beliefs, may not have time, etc. In such cases, it is argued, the agent ought to admit incompatible beliefs into her belief set. Is the obligation to repair incompatibilities non-defeasible? -- Shivam Patel I have a question inspired by Kripke’s “bizarre skeptic” from his *Wittgenstein on Rule Following and Private Language*. My intention in asking it is to use that skeptic’s line of thought to drive at a clarification of how the practice of “discursive updating”, “rectifying commitments”, or “shouldering the responsibility of repair…of incompatible commitments” (*BSD *, 187, 193, 194) establishes the meaning or representational purport of what said or believed. My intuition is that whatever meaning does get established is a fairly different sense of ‘meaning’ than the one that most philosophers and common folk have in mind. But I’m not clear about this yet. Kripke gives the novel concept *quus*: *x *quus *y *= *x *+ *y*, if *x*, *y *< 57 =5 otherwise (*WRPL*, 9). If it happens that I have never computed an addition problem where either of the numbers added are 57 or greater, appeal to all of my computations will still be insufficient to show that I preformed (i.e., followed the rule of) addition rather than (the rule of) *quaddition*. Kripke’s introduction of the term *quus* is waged as a challenge against the idea that in producing particular performances a person, or even a whole community, follows one rule, or understands or means one thing rather than another by some term. To rule out my performing *quaddition *(or an infinity of other appropriately gerrymandered activities), Kripke says, “there must be some fact...that can be cited to refute” those interpretations of what I have done (*WRPL*, 9). Kripke thinks that there is no such fact: no facts about my past history—nothing that was ever in my mind, or in my external behavior—establishes that I meant plus rather than quus” (13). The result, Kripke says, is “a new form of philosophical skepticism”: “There can be no such thing as meaning anything by any word” because “no *fact *about me constituted my meaning” one thing rather than another by it (7, 55, 21). This “new form of philosophical skepticism” dramatizes a more general form of the worry that begins Ch. 6 of *BSD*: Brandom recognizes that his “talk of ‘vocabularies’ and the practices of deploying them can make it look as if *all *that is in play is words and their use. If the * world* is left out of the story, what justification could there be for saying that *meaning* has not been?” (*BSD*, 177). He explains how some “* friction* between the world and the deployment of a vocabulary” (185) can be acquired with his toy model of repairing incompatibility with respect to the term ‘acid*’: Because the practitioner tastes something sour that turns phenolphthalein red, she is obliged to revise her concept ‘acid*’—which previously had inferential connections to ‘turns phenolphthalein blue’—in some way that makes it compatible with her new observations (either that or reject her observations). She sees that she ought to revise her concept ‘acid*’ because she sees that committing herself to the liquid’s being acid* (pre-revision) would commit her to two incompatible states of affairs (its turning phenolphthalein blue and its turning it red). For Brandom, the harmony between the *normative *incompatibility—the practitioner’s feeling that she ought to revise her commitments—and the * modal* incompatibility—that the liquid cannot have conflicting properties—is what gives the practitioner’s commitment(s) representational purport, i.e., makes them meaningfully represent properties of objects (*cf*. 193). Models like this one show how Brandom’s account can provide some “friction” between word and world. The representation purport of terms and claims in a language derives from a constraint of compatibility within a speaker’s web of material inferences and incompatibilities, and this web must be compatible with the observational data. But is this enough “friction”? Kripke’s bizarre skeptic draws our attention to the fact that the observational data supports many putative meanings: Perhaps no fact about what anyone in the linguistic community has seen or done rules out their meaning *quus* by ‘plus’ or *grue* by ‘blue’. Of course, we can rule out some of these gerrymandered meanings by, e.g., asking each other questions about when a term or claim is correctly used, but it will always be possible to think up more candidate meanings to show that an infinity of them can never be ruled out. The practice of “rectifying commitments”, which for Brandom gives terms or claims their representational purport or meaning, looks then to be no more than a necessary condition for such purport or meaning in general. What seems to be a lacking is a sufficient condition on some term or claim’s having its particular meaning. It seems to me that there are two ways Brandom could respond. One is the appeal to some fact that really does rule out someone’s meaning, e.g., anything but plus by ‘plus’. But another route seems to me more promising, and perhaps more in Brandomian spirit, which would be to reject the way that Kripke conceives of meaning in presenting his skeptical conclusion, perhaps in favor of pragmatic analysis of meaning. I would like to know how this could be done. Chuck Goldhaber I have a tangential question regarding BSD chapter 5: causation is often thought to be a modal notion, expressible via modal vocabulary (e.g. talk of "causal necessity/necessitation") What kind of consequences (if any) do you think your incompatibility semantics for modal vocabulary has for how we understand causal vocabulary? For instance, should we take causal conditionals as endorsements of inferences based on incompatibility-entailments? Sam Gavin I'm still sort of wrangling with a good way of placing understanding in terms of commitments, collateral commitments, and the attribution/acknowledgement between interlocutors. It would seem that, from the TOTE/discursive obligation towards deontic status updating, one might be granted understanding as given until 'proven otherwise' -- that one is 'understanding' someone until it becomes aware to him that the concepts both are using split in terms of the commitments they involve. But I'm thinking backwards of a case where two people share all the same commitments a concept entails/shares the same space in all inferences to and from it, but refer to the concept in different ways -- say 'scallion' or 'spring onion' -- perhaps provoked by one of those guessing games where one begins, "I'm thinking of a vegetable...". If two people were having a conversation, they could sort this out, but if it were just a game of "Is it a...", "Does it have..." there would seem to be no resolution. Again I guess I'm wondering about the ways two people can nail down what they're both talking about. And I continue to be bothered by the question of, when someone enters a claim into the discourse, whether it is understandable only to the degree it can be used, and if so, according to whose set of commitments? If it comes to the end in its practical use and material incompatibilities -- what of 'relatively immaterial' concepts, like a sortal? One breaks the rules with them according to whom? Also, much earlier in the class I asked something along the lines of whether material incompatibility were a requisite to being able to say anything at all; in class, you responded affirmatively. If we take understanding as being given until proven otherwise, and any concept beginning with an entailment of its being not 'whatever it is not', it seems in terms of a word's semantic meaning that any concept originally gives itself as a very rudimentary picture of "It's all this" or "It's all that". And it is as though mistakes in use were what allows one's idea of a concept to evolve, in a sense as though through a negative ontology of the original material incompatibility dualism, finding the most that something /cannot/ be, and the least that something /must/ be. I'm not sure this bit is even a question, but I find it interesting to think of this and wondering how it can start off: 'It is red', 'It is not red' -'not red is what?' Where evaluating 'not red' requires these other concepts... each again being another dualism. Also, this example is only with something directly observable and not a sortal concept. There might be room for an analysis of what kind of commitment/entitlement/entailment structure allows for the sortal concepts 'to grow', as it were, off the ground. Jacquet Kehm BSD, chap. 6: As the final step of his pragmatically mediated semantic analysis of discursive practices, in this chapter, Brandom focuses on the issue how those discursive practices establish intentional relation between words and the world, or, how the words used in those practices come to represent the world (i.e., be not merely syntactic but also semantic). Following the traditional pragmatist order of explanation, Brandom starts with a special kind of “thick” TOTE feedback process, and proceeds to explain what the subject and the object are and what the representational relation between them consists in in terms of that process. More specifically, Brandom claims that the representational relation is established in the discursive updating process that essentially involves rational rectification of incompatible commitments in the following two-step way: (1) First, taking two commitments to be incompatible (along with taking one to inferentially entail from the other) is to take them to refer to the same object. (pp. 187-8) (2) More generally, taking two commitments to be incompatible in the normative sense that undertaking both of them undercuts the entitlement for each is taking their contents to be incompatible in the modal sense that they cannot be true simultaneously. Therefore, shouldering the responsibility to rectify these normatively incompatible commitments is granting something independent of those commitments authority over the correctness of those commitments, that is, taking those commitments to represent a state of affairs obtaining in the objective world. (pp. 1934) Having said this, let me ask two interrelated questions concerning this analysis of semantic, representational relation resulted from the analytic pragmatist program of BSD. (a) Is it possible that a solitary subject engages in a discursive TOTE feedback cycle involving the essential element of rational rectification? The first question aims to compare the analysis at issue with that of representational dimension of propositional content as developed in MIE chap. 8. As I understand it, MIE claimed that one’s practical understanding of the representational dimension of content consists in her ability to draw several de re attributions from the de dicto attribution of the commitment to that content. This claim seems to imply that in order for one to (practically) understand the representational dimension, she needs at least a second subject to whom she can make some de re attributions, since the distinction between de dicto and de re will lose its point if there is nobody else but herself. On the other hand, at least apparently, even a solitary subject seems to be able to engage in the discursive TOTE cycle, which is claimed by BSD to be the essential factor to establish the representational relation. Then, is it fair to say that BSD suggest a weaker sufficient condition to establish and (practically) understand representational relation than MIE? (b) Is it possible for a discursive TOTE process to involve no non-inferential, causal route of gaining a new commitment? We can imagine such a discursive updating practice that contains no non-inferential, causal move but still involves the essential element of rational rectification. For example, imagine an ancient mathematician who believes that all numbers must be rational. In engaging in a mathematical practice, he can come to find that it is self-incompatible to claim that a square root of 2 is rational. Is this kind of rational rectification is sufficient for his mathematical practice to count as a discursive TOTE cycle, and thereby to establish a genuine semantic relation between his mathematical claims and the mathematical “facts” that those claims “represent”? Or are causal interactions between the subject and the object essential for the discursive TOTE cycle? Shuhei Shimamura