Finite State Approach to Modern Portfolio Theory Introduction Underlying all of modern finance is the idea of diversification. Holding a diversified collection of assets permits an investor to better control risk and, for a given level of risk, achieve better investment performance. But what, in theory and in practice, is diversification? How does one diversify and how does measure the amount of diversification in a portfolio of assets? In order to more clearly see the meaning of diversification, we will treat the possible outcomes of the investment process as being finite in number. The usual Capital Asset Pricing Model (CAPM) formulation assumes an uncountably infinite number of possible outcomes, any one of which is impossible to identify or describe. This means it is not possibly to speak meaningfully about good or bad or mediocre economic environments – only rates of return and their probability distributions survive in the usual CAPM treatment. For many purposes, it may be easier to think of the future as containing, at most, a finite number of possible outcomes. In this way, one can discern different economic environments and assign prices to securities with known performance characteristics in each of the possible economic environments. The No-Arbitrage Principle The most important principle in modern finance theory is the “no-arbitrage principle.” This principle has supplanted the notion of market equilibrium in finance since the 1970s. The idea of a “market equilibrium” has always been problematic in finance, because it is difficult to imagine a real world market equilibrium. Much of the interest in finance centers around change and activity – not around steady states or equilbria, concepts that dominate much of economic theory. What is the “no-arbitrage principle?” The No-Arbitrage Principle: Given a set of prices, there is no investment strategy that produces a certain return with net investment of zero (or that produces an infinite return from a finite investment). It is very important to note that arbitrage might be possible with one set of prices but not possible with another set of prices. The definition of the “no-arbitrage” principal is contingent upon a given set of asset prices – one for each asset. A market that is in equilibrium automatically satisfies the noarbitration principle, but a market may be in disequilibrium and nevertheless satisfy the no-arbitrage principle. The no-arbitrage principle implies that if there is an investment strategy that does not involve risk then that strategy will earn the ‘risk-free rate of return.’ There is no requirement that financial markets be in equilibrium. Indeed, the main significance of the no-arbitrage principle is that markets can be active, even chaotic, and still be consistent with the no-arbitrage principle. As long as there is no “free lunch” in the market place, the no-arbitrage principle will be satisfied. As we will discover in what follows, most important conclusions of finance theory follow from an application of the no-arbitrage principle. The principle of efficient markets follows directly from this principle and the Capital Asset Pricing Model and its descendent theories can, with some additional assumptions, be established by using this simple principle. In this chapter, we will introduce some of the elementary concepts of modern finance – states, securities, state prices and market efficiency – in a very primitive context. States of the World A state of the world is a description of the environment. For example, if weather is our main interest, we could define two states of the world: (i) it is raining; (ii) it is not raining. Obviously, there are more than two states regarding the weather. But, how many states we identify will depend upon the problem that we are working on. If we are trying to decide whether to put on rain gear when leaving the house, then the only states that we need consider might just be the two identified in this paragraph. If you own a bond, there might be only two states that interest you. The first state might be the state in which the bond pays you the interest payments that it promises. The second state might be the state in which the bond defaults. If you own shares of a company’s common stock, you might envision a state in the next period in which the company’s earnings grow versus a different state in which the company’s earnings don’t grow. The states of the world that are needed are the states that are most useful to the problem that you are considering. Whether finance is our interest or the day’s weather is our main concernpa, we are generally free to pick the states any way we like. The strength of our analysis will often hinge on how well we pick the states that make up our analysis. Let’s suppose that we identify three states that might prevail in the future: State 1: s1 -- the good state – this will be the state where most securities do well State 2: s2 – the bad state – this will be the state here most securities perform poorly State 3: s3 – the ‘neutral’ state – this will be the state where mediocrity reigns Many finance issues can be discussed with this simple description of states. The importance of states is that the payoff of securities will depend upon which state occurs. We can think of these states as future states – tomorrow, for example. But, today we don’t know for certain which state is going to occur. We have to decide today which securities to own without knowing for certain which state we will be in tomorrow. Securities and Payoffs Now that we have states defined, we can proceed to talk about securities. A security will be completely defined by identifying the payoff that the security provides for each state that may occur. We will use capitals to identify securities: Security 1: X1 – pays off in the good state; pays a little in the neutral state, goes bust in the bad state Security 2: X2 – pays moderately in the good state and the neutral state and goes bust in the bad state Security 3: X3 – pays less than S1 in the good state but loses less in the bad state We still have not yet defined a security. We need to get more specific about what the payoffs are in each state to get a complete definition of each security. We will use the Greek symbol, p, to represent payoffs. Each security has a specific payoff in each state. This means that p will have two subscripts – one that identifies the security and the second will indicate in which state the payoff is intended. For example: p1,2 is the payoff to security S1 in state s2. If there are three states and three securities, we will have nine payoffs: p1,1 p1,2 p1,3 --the payoffs to security one p2,1 p2,2 p2,3 --the payoffs to security two p3,1 p3,2 p3,3 --the payoffs to security three The No-Arbitrage Principle Now that we have defined the states and the securities we can give a more formal definition of the noarbitrage principle. We need the concept of an investment portfolio. An investment portfolio, in this simple situation, will be defined by three numbers: φ1, φ2, φ3. Each φ indicates the amount of that security contained in the portfolio. The prices1 of the three securities are P1, P2, P3. An investment portfolio, then is defined as: { φ1, φ2, φ3} -- a portfolio With a cost of: 1 All prices used in this text will be assumed to always be non-negative without explicitly saying so. P 1 φ1 + P 2 φ2 + P 3 φ3 The payoff to the portfolio in state one will be: φ1 p1,1 + φ2 p2,1 + φ3 p3,1 The payoffs to the portfolio in states two and three are given by: φ1 p1,2 + φ2 p2,2 + φ3 p3,2 φ1 p1,3 + φ2 p2,3 + φ3 p3,3 Following Stephen Ross’s treatment in his Princeton Lectures2 with slight changes, we give the following definition of the no-arbitrage principle: Definition: An arbitrage opportunity is a portfolio with no negative payoffs and a positive payoff in some state, where the cost of the portfolio is not positive. Formally P 1 φ1 + P 2 φ2 + P 3 φ3 ≤ 0 and φ1 p1,1 + φ2 p2,1 + φ3 p3,1 ≥ 0 φ1 p1,2 + φ2 p2,2 + φ3 p3,2 ≥ 0 φ1 p1,3 + φ2 p2,3 + φ3 p3,3 ≥ 0 where at least one of the last three inequalities is strict (meaning > 0), otherwise the budget constraint equation (the first equation in the definition) is strict (meaning < 0). In words, an arbitrage opportunity is situation where a costless portfolio can produce a positive return or a negative cost portfolio fails to provide a negative return. Logically this takes case of the situation where a finite cost portfolio would yield an infinite return because you could achieve the infinite return by taking an arbitrarily large position in the portfolio. The no-arbitrage principle is the idea that there is no arbitrage portfolio, given the payoffs and the security prices. We can state that formally as: Definition: The No-Arbitrage Principle: Given security prices and the security payoffs for each state of the world, there does not exist an arbitrage opportunity as defined above. The relationship between competitive equilibrium and the no-arbitrage principle 2 Stephen A. Ross, NeoClassical Finance, Princeton University Press. See Chapter One. Clearly, if markets are in equilibrium, the no-arbitrage principle must be satisfied. Otherwise participants will be attempting to take advantage of the available arbitrage opportunities and the markets will not remain in equilibrium. But, is it possible for markets to be out of equilibrium, yet satisfy the no-arbitrage principle? The answer to that question is yes. There is no requirement that markets be in equilibrium. Markets can be quite chaotic and yet there could be an absence of arbitrage opportunities. This means that the no-arbitrage principle is a weaker assumption that the usual markets-in-equilibrium assumption that dominates most of economic theory. In finance, you don’t really need markets to be in equilibrium to establish most of the main conclusions of the theory. The Existence of State Prices Definition: A state price is a price of security whose payoff is exactly one unit for that state and zero for all other states. If there were state prices for each state, these could be used to price the securities in the following manner: P1 = q1p1,1 + q2p1,2 + q3p1,3 P2 = q1p2,1 + q2p2,2 + q3p2,3 P3 = q1p3,1 + q2p3,2 + q3p3,3 The price of security one, P1, for example, should be the total payoff in each state(pi,j, where I represents the security and j represents the state) times the state price for that state. Similarly, P2 and P3 are calculated in the same manner. (The qi’s are the state prices in the equations above). Imagine a security that paid exactly one unit in one of the three states, but absolutely nothing in the other states. The security that paid one unit in s1 would have price q1. Similarly for states 2 and 3. A portfolio that consists of these three securities would pay exactly one unit regardless of which state occurs. We call that portfolio a security – the risk-free security in fact, since it’s payoff is always the same no matter what the future holds. The Fundamental Theorem of Finance: The No-Arbitrage Principle is Equivalent to the Existence of State Prices Restating the ‘Fundamental Theorem,’ if we can calculate the state prices given the security prices, then the no-arbitrage principle must hold and if we know that the no-arbitrage principle holds, then we can calculate state prices from knowledge of security prices. Presumably the state prices are not identical for each state. Different states will generally have different state prices. This has profound implications. This means the value of a unit of account is worth more in one state than in another when determining the price of a security. So far, we have said nothing about the likelihood of any state occurring. Surprisingly, our Fundamental Theorem is independent of the likelihood of any particular state’s occurrence. But, for the moment suppose we know the probabilities associated with the occurrence of each of our three states. Then, we can define the “expected return” to be the sum of the returns weighted by their respective probabilities, where pij is the return in state j of security i: Expected Return of security i ≡ prob(1) pi1 + prob(2) pi2 + prob(3) pi3 If you have two different securities that have identical expected returns, but one has all of its return in the good state and the other has all of its return in the bad state, then the latter will have a higher security price. This makes portfolio diversification much easier to visualize. Diversifying assets are those that produce returns in states for which most of your assets aren’t doing very well. In the extreme, insurance is an example where the good state and bad state might be mirror images of one another. Let’s suppose we have the three state prices: q1, q2, and q3. If no one security can be created by a linear combination of the other two, then there will always be some portfolio that, for each state, provides one unit in that state and zero units in the other states. The price of that portfolio would equal the q for that state. If there is a (hypothetical) security that provides one unit in each state, the price of that security would be equal to q1 + q2 + q3. The return for this security is one and the cost is the sum of the q’s: r = Return of security that pays one unit in each state = 1 (𝑞1 + 𝑞2 + 𝑞3 ) This security is known as the risk free security and its return will be the risk free rate, r. Notice that r is uniquely defined by q1, q2, and q3. If we know that we can solve for : q1, q2, and q3, then the no-arbitrage principle must be true. This is very simple to show mathematically. The converse proposition is more difficult: that the no-arbitrage principle implies the existence of state prices. The proof relies on a separation theorem between two non-overlapping convex sets. Risk-Adjusted Probabilities Are the relevant probabilities of each state known? We assume they are not. But, it turns out, we can calculate risk adjusted probabilities and use them to price assets in a manner similar to using state prices to price assets. These risk-adjusted probabilities are easily calculated, if you know the values of the state prices. Set Q equal to the sum of the q’s. Then the risk-adjusted probabilities are simply: π1 = q1/Q π2 = q2/Q π3 = q3/Q Because of the way that we defined Q, these risk-adjusted probabilities must sum to 1 and therefore behave just as normal probabilities – they are non-negative and sum to one. These risk-adjusted probabilities are so named because if {z1, z2, z3} Represents the returns to a security in each of the three states, then its price, P, is given by: P = π1 z1 + π2 z2 + π3 z3 which is nothing more than the expected value of the returns from holding the security where the expected value is calculated using the risk-adjusted probabilities, as opposed to the true (unknown) probabilities. The risk-adjusted probabilities are often described as martingale probabilities, or simply, the martingale measure. For many problems in finance, it is much simpler to work with the martingale measure than with the state prices from which the martingale measure is derived.3 The Martingale Property A random variable satisfies the martingale property if the expected future value of the variable is identical to its current value, regardless of the future date that is considered: E[Vt+s] + V for all t and for s > 0 Suppose your wealth at time t is $ 100, i.e., Wt = $ 100. Imagine the following process determines your future wealth: each period you flip a fair coin and gain $ 1 if heads and lose $ 1 if tails. What is the expected value of your future wealth at some date t+s in the future (where s> 0)? The answer is $ 100 since you expect to gain $ 1 half the time and lose $ 1 the other half of the time. Your wealth, using the process, is a martingale. Stock prices clearly do not satisfy the martingale property. If they did, no one would ever invest in stocks. But, if you use an adjusted stock price series where the adjusted stock price at any time is the discounted future value of the stock price using the risk free rates as discounts, the adjusted stock price 3 The martingale measure is obviously related to the martingale property that the best estimate of a future value of something is its current value. Adjusting prices with the martingale measure gets one to the martingale property of security prices. This is the correct formalization of the random walk concept in finance. measure does satisfy the martingale property: Stock Price E[P1 P1 P0 to t1 time In the above diagram, one period elapses between t0 and t1. The slope of the line from P0 to E[P1] is (1 + r). It is clear that the expected future price is not equal to the current price. So prices, by themselves, do not satisfy the martingale property. But, if we slight modify our variables, we can get to the martingale property. Define a new variable R, by de-trending the price series, in the following way: R0 = P0 Rt+1 = Pt+1 - rPt If we extend our single period model, the variable Rt, as defined above, will satisfy the martingale property, since Rt = E[Rt+s] where s is any positive integer. The martingale property, in this setting, applies to the de-trended price series. (De-trending the stock price series is equivalent to creating a new random variable that in time t is the expected current value of the price at time t discounted back to the present). Actual future stock prices will, it may be supposed, bounce around the trend line as described in the diagram below: Stock Price E[P1] time The dots, describing possible actual prices, will not necessarily fall along the trend line, but should track it with some variation. This is the meaning of ‘random walk’ in stock price series. It does not mean that the stock price distribution is unknown. Quite the contrary. It means that next period’s price, or any future price, is unpredictable, even though we may be fully confident about its expected future price. Think of a coin flip, once again. You have no idea exactly how many of the next ten coin flips will turn out to be heads. But, your expectation is five. What actually happens is random and will constitute, in repeated trials a random walk around a mean of five. If Stock Prices (Adjusted) is a Martingale Process, So What? There are some strong information assumptions embedded in our treatment thus far. The two most important embedded assumptions are: 1. The states of the world and their payoffs are known with certainty 2. All market participants agree on what the states are and what the payoffs are If you combine these assumptions with the idea that martingale probabilities exist (in another words, state prices exist or, equivalently, the no-arbitrage condition is satisfied), then you can almost taste the idea of market efficiency. It is not possible to define market efficiency without directly addressing the preferences of investors, something we don’t intend to do here. But once we are able to define investor preferences, these assumptions will be enough to guarantee the kind of market efficiency that says that no investor’s welfare (utility) can be improved without a decrease in the welfare of some other investor. This is the classic allocative efficiency that is known in general equilibrium theory as a Pareto optimum. It means that resources aren’t wasted. It doesn’t meant that allocations are ‘fair’ or ‘just’ or anything like that. It just means there is no ‘free lunch’ left out there could be captured and given to someone. The existence of state prices and martingale probabilities throw considerable light on other important issues in finance – diversification, risk management, for example.