The Concept of the Inertial Mass in Macroscopic Physics and in Quantum Field Theory R. Faber Private Center for Fundamental Research 90491 Nuernberg, Germany and M. Dillig Institute for Theoretical Physics III University Erlangen-Nuernberg, 91058 Erlangen, Germany Abstract We reflect on the concept of the mass in physics. We argue that in macroscopic physics the only relevant mass is the inertial mass, which we call dynamic, opposite the gravitational (static) mass: all experimental measurements are only sensitive to the inertial mass (the gravitational mass is at best realized in the asymptotic limit with the interaction time t ). Our reasoning is strongly supported from quantum field theory: here the presence of the fluctating vacuum inevitably allows only for a dynamical, i.e. inertial mass. 1 The concept of the mass is of fundamental importance in physics, as it plays a crucial role on the very large and the very small scales, i. e. in macroscopic and microscopic physics. However, inspite of their outstanding role and their long historical tradition, the dynamical origin of the mass is presently only vaguely understood. The basic idea of mass generation is the concept of spontaneous symmetry breaking (such as in the context of gauge or chiral theories), where the mass originates from the nonperturbative breaking of the symmetry of the vaccum: the generation of mass reflects the appearance of new vacuum as the true ground state of the field theory (1). Though microscopic details of such mechanisms (their dynamical origin) are presently only anticipated, it is obvious that the generation of mass is intimately connected with the presence of the nontrivial physical vacuum: in spontaneous broken field theories the mass of a particle it proportinal to the vacuum expectation value of bilinear timeordered products of field operators (or condensates), schematically (2) (With respect to the discussion presented below we use as a neutral symbol for mass, without explicitly specifying further its nature). Leaving the framework of microscopic field theories, we face different conecpts for the mass on the macroscopic level: the inertial mass, denoted in the following by the symbol m, and the gravitational mass, denoted hereafter as m*. The historical origin of this differentiation is not fully clear, but dates back to the 18th century (3): though Newton in his formulation of the Newtonian classical mechanics used only the concept of the inertial mass as part of his dynamical equations (4), a subsequent formulation of the equations of motion in the framework of the Hamilton or, equivalently, the Lagrange formalism, led to an extension of the 2 conecpt of mass to a graviational mass, entering in static formulations, such as based on the static gravitational potential. From its first origins this concept became rooted deeply in classical mechanics as a standard of common modern textbooks. A link between these a priori two fundamentally different concepts for the mass was established in the formulation of the Theory of General Relativity by Albert Einstein (5) who introduced the (both local and global) principle of the strict quantitative equivalence between the inertial and the graviational mass to formulate the strict equivalence of an appropriate accelerated system without gravitational force and an appropriate system in rest with the presence of a gravitational force. Soon after the discrimination between an inertial and a gravitational mass appeared in the literature, intuition and experimental experience lead to the conjecture of the equvialence of these two a priori different forms of the mass. Pionieering and accurate experiments have been performed already towards the end of the 18. century by Eötvös (6) and other groups. However, as Einstein introduced the strict equivalence of inertial and gravitational mass in an axiomatic way, various (and ongoing) experimental attempts have been and are performed to prove the strict equivalence of m and m* with increasing accuracy; current NASA initiated projects aim at an accuracy of (7) ( m – m* )/m < 10 ; furtheron, even more accurate experiments are planned. Even though their outcome has to be awaited for, hitherto all findings point strictly to an identity of the inertial and the graviational mass, i. e. to a unique conecpt of mass with m = m*. Guided by this experimental trends and worried by conceptional difficulties in the discrimination beetween the inertial and the graviational mass, it is tempting to formulate the underlying question: does enforce nature a priori the introduction a gravitational mass in addition to the inertial mass öand the 3 discrimination between these two kinds of masses, or, alternatively, has the concept – as we argue – of the gravitational mass to be abandoned completely and to be replaced by the unique concept of the inertial mass m? To formulate this question on a truely fundamental level we feel, that presently indispensable elements for a substantial answer are missing: we foresee that answering this question on the deepest level requires a basic understanding both of the conept of mass generation and the unifcation of very small (microscopic) and very large scales in nature unifying all known forces on or beyond the Planck scale (8). As presently here only fragmentary attempts have been undertaken, we have to divide our discussion of the concept of mass up into the two scales mentioned above and focus separately on macroscopic and microscopic aspects. On the microscopic level – referring to the Newtonian concept of mechanics, which is sufficient for our considerations – the starting point is the unification of dynamical and a static equation in Newton’s law for a two body system m* r = - V with V = - m * M* / r (with the gravitational constant and the heavy masses m and M of the gravitating bodies); in its linearized form and extended to angular momentum conservation the corresponding law also holds for the comparison of two masses in a weigthing process. In the equation above we have to critically examine the concecpt of a static situation. As a closed, isloted two-body system never exists 4 in natureretation the equation of motion above never describes – except in a limiting process sketched below – rigorously a static problem. With the fluctuating nonequiblibrium background generated the dynamical coupling to all the (infinite number of) background masses, a static equilibrium is never strictly realized. As a direct consequence, the conept of a static graviational mass never enters into a dynamical macroscopic equation: we are exclusively confronted in macroscopic nature with dynamical problems. Taking the gravitational force it is clear that the static conecpt is just an extreme simplfication of a truely dynamcial situation: the (quasi) static result just reflects the approximation to an (infinite) sum of dynamically coupled many-body contributions. This argument does not rest on the question of a static or an expanding (or contracting) universe: even within a formally static universe any dynamical equation reflects a truely nonstatic underlying physics. In continuing this argument, we feel that the concept of a graviational mass may be only realized in extreme limit m = lim (r) m* i.e. in isolating the mass under consideration strictly from the residual system of interacting masses. Though such a limiting process is hypothetically possible, it indicates by its very nature that for the existing universe both in space and time the existence of a static heavy mass is never realized (note that the limiting process above in space implies on the same level a limiting transition in time with t , where t is the time of the interacting mass relative to the residual system. Again this reasoning is not invalitated by the even more complex and controversial question of an indiviual „Eigenzeit“ for each body in an interacting system, as arising naturally in various covariant field theoretical approaches (9)). It is crucial to stress that we arrive at exactly the same conclusion in comparing the inertial and the graviational mass directly by a 5 weighting process. In a relative comparison of two masses one measures the accelerating (graviational) force of one body acting on the second body, which is from the principle actio = reactio inversely accelerated with respect to the first reference mass. A priori, such a comparision is a truely dynamical situation. The static limit – i.e. a strict static balance between the two bodies compared – is only achieved the limit of an asymptotically vanishing mutual acceleration of the two masses, i. e. for lim r 0. Again it is clear, that such a limit in nature at finite times is never realized, in other words, the concept of a gravitational, static mass strictly never enters in any macroscopic physical law of nature. One might argue, that there is a caveat in the argumentation above: in principle it might be possible that during a finite time interval there exists a phase transition of the second kind (such as realized macroscopically and microscopically in many phenomena in physics, for example, in superdconductivity, magnetization, chiral phase transitions or colour superconductivity (10)), giving rise to a nonvanishing energy gap and converting the inert mass into a distinctly different state of a gravitational mass. We feel that from our present understanding, such a reasoning cannot be reconciled with the fundamental laws of nature. As the crucial point, we realize that all second order phase transitions in nature arise on a genuinely microscopic level, macroscopic consequences of such phase transitions only reflect the dynamical collectivity of the underlying micrcoscopy. This immediately raises the principal question: is there a microscopic transition from a dynamcial to static situation possible at all. Here – even without knowing the true origin of the generation of mass – on the microscopic level a static limit is completely excluded by the presence of the dynamical vacuum 6 itself (11) – or equivalently – the existence of Heisenberg’s uncertainty relation (12). From the basic concepts of quantum mechanics it is clear, that there exists no static vaccum: the vacuum is always fluctuating due to the presence of the Dirac sea. In other words, the isolation of a particle in the spirit of a truely single particle problem in never realized in nature: nature always involves an infinite many-bdoy problem and thus exclusively dynamcial masses of the interacting particles. Thus the nature of the vacuum itself excludes a phase transition to a static limit even hypothetically (To avoid a misunderstanding: our argument does not contradict the current definition of static or rest mass for example for an elementary particle: we argue that this seemingly static concept just reflects the necessary approximate „semi-static“ experimental situation and accuracy: in experiments a genuine static system is never strictly realized). Summarizing, we end up with our main conclusion, that from a critical examination of the equations of motion of nature as an infinite fluctuating manybody system – which even violates particle number conservation – we conclude, that nature never reaches a static limit in the rigorous sense. Thus, in discriminating between the concept of an inert and a heavy (static) mass, only and exclusively the inert mass is realized in nature. In this sense we believe that the introduction of the concept of a heavy mass is completely redundant. In addition, in our opinion the Theory of General Realtivitiy does not require the equivalence principle for the interial and the graviational mass: it is sufficient to realize that the action of a graviational field is equivalent to the acceleration of a system by external force. Above all, this reasoning is also supported by the guiding principle of all fundamental laws in nature, i. e. the principle of maximal simplicity: the inroduction of two different mass quite evidently contradicts this basic concept in an unncessary way. In formulation our main conclusions we, of course, realize that we are unable to provide a rigorous formulation of the microscopic generation of the mass, beyond that it is not clear from our present 7 understanding, if the macroscopic and microscopic concept of the mass can be unified consistently; here for a deeper understanding of the fundamental questions significant progress in the ongoing attempts of the unification of quantum field theory and quantum gravity (13) is indespensable. However, as all our arguments have their basis in the microscopic nature of the dynamical vacuum, we are convinced that the notion of a satic graviational mass is properly replaced and incorporated in the unique state of mass in nature, i. e. in the concept of the interial mass. References (1) J. Goldstone, A. Salam and S. Weinberg: Phys. Rev. 127 (1962) 965; P. W. Higgs: phys. Lett. 12 (1964) 132; T. W. B. Kibble: Phys. Rev. 155 (1967) 1554; (2) F. J. Yindurian: The Theory of the Quark and Gluon Interactions (1993) (Springer Verlag, Berlin), (3) J. L. Lagrange: Analytische Mechanik (1887) (Ed. H. Servus; Springer Verlag, Berlin); (4) I. A. Newton: Philosophiae Naturalis Mathematica Principia (1729) (Ed. A. Motte, London); (5) A. Einstein: Sitzungsber. Preuss. Akad. Wiss. (1915) 778; (6) R. Eötvös: Annalen Physik 68 (1922) 1; 8 (7) NASA-ESA: Test Equiv. Principle (STEP) (2004); (8) J. C. Pati and A. Salam: Phys. Rev. Lett. 31 (1973) 275; H. Georgi and S. L. Glashow: Phys. Rev. Lett. 32 (1974) 438; (9) E. E. Salpeter and H. A. Bethe: Phys. Rev. 84 (1951) 1232; (10) P. G: de Gennes: Supercondicutivity in Metals and Alloys (1989) (Perseus Books, Publ., Mass.); K. Rajagobal and F. Wilzek: Nucl. Phys. B 399 (1993) 395, hep-ph/9210253; M Alford: hep-ph/0110150; (11) M. Kaku: Quantum Field Theory (1993) (Oxford University Press, New York); G. `t Hooft: Phys. Rev. Lett. 37 (1976) 8; Phys. Rep. 142 (1986) 357; (12) E. Schrödinger: Sitzungsber. Preuss. Akad. Wiss. Berlin (Mathe. Phys.) 19 (1930) 296; quant-ph/9903100; (13) Th. Kaluza: Sitzungsber. Preuss. Akad. Wiss. K1 (1921) 966; O. Klein: Z. Phys. 37 (1926) 895 9