KANTIAN ETHICS RKUD 2020 ISLAMIC ETHICS SEM 1 2018/2019 DR. FADZILAH BT DIN SECTION 3 No. Name Matric Number 1 AINI SYUHAIDA BT AZMI 1612886 2 NUR ALYAA BT HASHIM 1729224 3 NUR AIN AFIQAH BT HAMIDON 1622426 4 NUR SYAHIRAH BT MOHAMED SHUKOR NURSHAMIMI NATASHA BINTI SHAMSUDIN NURUL SYAZANA BT KHAIRUL ANUAR 1722152 5 6 1711542 1719784 TABLE OF CONTENT NO CONTENT PAGE NUMBER 1 Introduction Biography Of Immanuel Kant 2 2 Kant on Moral Worth 2-4 3 Moral and Imperative 5-8 4 Kant Theory of Punishment Methods of Punishment 8-9 5 Comparison Between Kantianism And Utilitarianism 10-11 6 References 12 1 1.0 INTRODUCTION 1.1 BIOGRAPHY OF IMMANUEL KANT Immanuel Kant was known well among the modern western philosophy that being influenced by his theory. Without leaving the region of his hometown in, the philosopher changed the course of ethics, moral philosophy, metaphysic and aesthetics. Kant was born in 1724 in Konigsberg then East Prussia or now the place is known as Kaliningad in Russia. Immanuel Kant was the fourth of nine children belong to Johann George Cant and he is a harness maker and his wife was Anna Regina Cant. Both Kant’s parents were devout followers from Pietism and 18th century branch of Lurtheran Church. Due to their family was closely engage with the church so the pastor did realized the potential of the young man Kant so he arranged the education for Immanuel Kant. While at school, Kant gained a deep appreciation for the Latin classic. In 1740, Kant enrolled at the University of Konigsberg in Theology student but however he attracted to mathematics and physic. Unfortunately, in 1746 his father died and he was forced to leave the education at the university to help his family. For a decade he worked as a private tutor to earn life and for the wealthy. During this time he published several papers dealing with scientific question exploring the middle ground between rationalism and empiricism. In 1755, he got back to the university and received his doctorate of philosophy and at the age of 31, he obtained an unsalaried as a private docent at the Konigsberg University At the age of 57, Kant published the first edition of the Critique of Pure Reason. This work of Kant is the most important work and difficult work in the western thought. Eventually, all of Kant’s work develops his article theory and it is clearly defined in Groundwork of Metaphysic of Moral, Critical of Practical Reason and Metaphysic Moral. 2.0 KANT ON MORAL WORTH Moral worth can be defined as a particular way in which an action or an agent are valuable or deserve credit or deserve discredit. A central thought about moral worth is that it involves the agent’s motives for acting. An action is morally worthy when and to the extent that it is performed 2 for the right moral reasons. The moral worth of an action then should not be identified with its value in producing good consequences or preventing bad ones including the very performance of the act. According to the philosopher like W.D.Ross claimed that a wrong action can be morally worthy or good and a right one can be morally unworthy or bad. According to Immanuel Kant, the German philosopher, he claimed that it is impossible to conceive anything at all in the world or even out of it, which can be taken as good without qualification, except a good will. Good wills are defined in terms of the intention to produce good states of affairs. He said that a good will is not good because of what it effects or accomplishes or because of its fitness for attaining some proposed end. Good will means that an action has moral only when performed by an agent who possesses a good will. An agent has a good will only if moral obligation based on a universally valid norm is the action’s sole motive. According to Kant, a good will is a will that chooses a certain action because it is the action dictated by duty. Kant on duty means that all persons must act not only in accordance with but for the sake of obligation. A person’s motive for acting must rest in a recognition that what he or she intends is demanded by an obligations. Kant has something to say about what makes someone a good person. Keep in mind that Kant intends this to go along with the rest of his theory, and what one’s duty is would be determined by the categorical imperative. However, one can treat this as separate theory to some extent, and consider that one’s duty is determined by some other standard. Kant argues that a person is a good or bad depending on the motivation of their actions and not on the goodness of the consequences of those actions. By “motivation” it means that the reason for doing something. It is what the caused you to do the action. Kant also argues that one can have moral worth only if one is motivated by morality. In other words, if a person’s emotions or desires cause them to do something, then that action cannot give them moral worth. The motivation is what matters for example like you can imagine that you win the lottery and you are wondering what to do with the money. So, you look around for what would be the most fun to do with it like you can buy a yacht and travel in the first class around the world. Then, you decide that what would be really fun is by giving the money to charity and you enjoy the feeling you get from making people happy. According to Kant, you are not a morally worthy person because you did it after you thought that was the most fun and there is nothing admirable 3 about such a selfish pursuit. Moral worth only comes when you do something because you know that it is your duty and you would di it regardless of whether you liked it. After that, what if we look at the Kant in term of wrong interpretation. We consider about the case above about the lottery winner giving the money to charity. Imagine that the winner gives to a charity and he intends to save hundreds of starving children in a remote village. The food arrives in the village but a group of rebels finds out that they have foo and they come to steal the food and end up killing the children in the village and the adults too. The intended consequences of feeding starving children was good and the actual consequences were bad. Therefore, Kant is not saying that we should look at the intended consequences in order to make a moral worth is properly assessed by looking at the motivation of the action, which may be selfish even if the intended consequences are good. Therefore, Kant does not forbid happiness. A careful reader may notice that the example above is about one of the selfish person’s intended consequences is to make himself happy and so it might seem to be that intended consequences do matter. One might think Kant is claiming that if one of my intentions is to make myself happy, that my action is not worthy. The consequence of making myself happy is actually a good consequences, even according to Kant also the same. You can get moral worth doing things that you enjoy, but the reason you are doing them cannot be that you enjoy them. However, the reason must be that they are required by duty. Keep in mind that what is said in the above has to do with how one evaluates people, not actions. A person’s actions determine her moral worth, but there is more to this than merely seeing if the actions are right or wrong. According to Kant a good person is someone who always does their duty because it is their duty. It is fine if they enjoy doing it, but it must be the case that they would do it even if they did not enjoy it. The overall theme is that to be a good person you must be good for a goodness sake. 4 3.0 MORAL AND IMPERATIVES Kant’s moral philosophy revolves around free will in three ways. Firstly, we as a human being are impossible to avoid the Categorical Imperative, because this implicit in free-will being. Secondly, the core of the morality is to will in according with moral’s demand. Lastly, the demand should in line that we need to respect freedom of persons. Principle of Categorical Imperative describe on how a perfectly rational being would act. For human like us as being an imperfect rational being, it prescribes how we as human should act. Categorical Imperative typically does not contain ‘if’ because if it does, it will become hypothetical. By imperative, Kant does not means orders or commands issued by other people.1 Immanuel Kant formulate several formulas to explain this principle. The first one is universal law. Kant stated in his work; Act on that maxim through which you can at the same time will that it should become universal law.2 Universal law means that the law is universalizable and applicable to all. The law cannot be referred to this particular person for it to be part of morality. Besides, the universalizability of law precludes or reject inconsistent willing. The following examples show how universalizability work: i. Kant's example of a false promise (Using Test One) Maxim: I may make a false promise in order to reap financial gain. Generalized: Anyone may make a false promise to get something she or he wants. This is self-contradictory because: If anyone may make a "false promise," nobody would take a promise seriously; promising becomes meaningless. Result: I may not act on that maxim. The maxim fails Test One. ii. Kant's example of the Bad Samaritan (Using Tests One and Two) 1 Atwell, John E. End and Principles in Kant Moral Thought. Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, 1986 Kant, Immanuel. The Metaphysics of Morals. Translated by Mary Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991. 2 5 Maxim: I may refuse to help another person in distress who cannot pay me even though I could do so at little cost to myself. Generalized: Anyone may refuse to help another person in distress who cannot pay her even though it would cost her little to help. Can it be conceived? Yes. Could you will this to be a universal law? Probably not, because you might find yourself in a situation of extreme need and nobody else would help you. Result: You cannot act on the "Bad Samaritan" maxim. According to Kant, it is said that there are 2 kind of inconsistent willing. The first type of inconsistent willing is that some maxims strictly cannot be universalized which means it is impossible to universalize maxims. This give rise to perfect duties which means act that one must not perform at any time. To explain, no matter what happen, one cannot perform that act. The second kind of inconsistent willing is that some maxims are not strictly self-contradictory when universalize but they are inconsistent with some natural end that a rational person would will. This maxim render imperfect duty which act that generally one should perform, that means at some time one should perform the act. Nevertheless, perfect duty and imperfect duty is crucial to differentiate between law and virtue. The following are examples of Kantian Ethics that shows perfect duty and imperfect duty: Examples of perfect duty to ourselves: i. Someone miserable is contemplating to commit suicide and Kant shows how the categorical imperative entails that the person has a duty not to commit suicide regardless of how miserable they are. ii. Someone wants to borrow money promising that they’ll pay it back, but they know that they will never be able to pay it back within the agreed time limit of the loan. Kant believes the categorical imperative to show that making false promises cannot be universalised and it cannot be a duty because it is morally wrong. Examples of imperfect duty to ourselves: i. Someone with natural talents let them go to waste because they are lazy. Here Kant uses the categorical imperative to show that it is wrong for us to waste our natural talents. We must at least choose to develop some of them as this is why it is an imperfect duty because we can choose to let some of our talents rust. 6 ii. Someone who is doing pretty well in life is considering helping out other people. Kant shows that although it is possible to universalise the maxim don’t help others, it is not possible to make this to happen because we would not want to be in a situation where we need assistance and yet no one wants to help us.3 The second formula is respect for persons based on what Kant had stated in his work; Act in such a way that you always treat humanity, whether in your own person or that of another, never as a mere means but always at the same time as an end.4 This statement explains that a rational person should value the fact that persons have free-will. This kind of will must be determined by an end therefore cannot be based on any desire. The word ‘mere means’ here means being nothing just than an instrument for accomplishing goals. To understand the statement of ‘treat someone merely as a means’ means that person is using another person simply to get what they desire out of the situation. Basically, they are doing the action for their own purpose, not for someone else. On the other hand, ‘all human beings treated as ends’ simply means that treat other as if they and their well-being are the goal. Thomson explained that means exist only for sake of ends and ends exist merely for sake of guiding rational beings. 5 In additional, Scruton stated that we cannot treat rational agents merely as the means through which external forces operate: to do so is to deny their autonomy and therefore to violate their claim to our respect.6 The third one is autonomy. Kant stated that: So act that your will can regard itself at the same time as making universal law through it maxims.7 This formula is just similar to the first one. When we regard a being as a rational, we regard him or her as making universal law. This statement means that human being should regard their will as making universal law. The last formula for the principle of Categorical Imperative is kingdom of ends. Kant stated that: 3 Garrett, Jan Edward. “Kant's Duty Ethics”. 2006. http://people.wku.edu/jan.garrett/ethics/kant.htm Kant, The Metaphysics of Morals 5 Thomson, Garrett. On Kant. Australia: College of Wooster, 2003. 6 Scruton, Roger. Kant. London: Oxford University Press, 2001. 7 Kant, The Metaphysics of Morals 4 7 Act on maxim of a member who makes universal law for a merely possible kingdom of ends.8 This formula rises an idea on each rational human being in a community should reckon his or her maxim also be applicable to guide others action. By this way, rational human being can treat one others as ends. Thomson refer kingdom of ends to a community of persons each one of whom act autonomously without infringing autonomy of the others.9 4.0 KANT’S THEORY OF PUNISHMENT Immanuel Kant’s concept of punishment is what we can say as retributivist. Retributive justice is a theory that holds that the best response to a crime is a punishment proportional to the offense committed and inflicted because the offender deserves the punishment.10 According to Kant, punishment must only be imposed for the sake of Justice. If the intention of the punishment is to give lesson to the community, it is considered unethical. This is because it can be considered as manipulative and according to Kant, human must not be manipulated. Another view of Kant is that a proportional punishment is also considered as equality as it can help in restoring to what had been before the crime was committed.11 Based on this, a punishment must be determined by a court of law only and not personal judgement, as it could lead to unfairness and biasness. This is unethical as it is unfair towards the criminal if he were sentenced something unproportioned with the offence he had committed. For example, it is unethical and unjust to cut the hand of a person, if the only thing he steal are foods for him to survive. Based on this, punishment must not be determined through utilitarianism as it could affect the concept of equality. 8 Kant, The Metaphysics of Morals 9 Thomson, On Kant 10 Aune, Bruce. Kant’s Theory of Moral. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press, 1979. 11 Potter, Nelson T. Jr., "The Principle of Punishment Is a Categorical Imperative"(1998). Faculty Publications Department of Philosophy. 22. http://digitalcommons.unl.edu/philosfacpub/22 8 To compare it to the Muslim world, during the time of Umar al-Khattab, few slaves were caught stealing from their owner. At first, he decided on amputation of the hand as punishment as it was mentioned in the Quran and Sunnah. However, after further investigation, he found out that the slaves only stole because after all the work they’d done, the owner did not feed them. Later, he revoke back his decision and punish the owner instead.12 From this, we could say Kant’s view of punishment is quite similar to the view of Muslims. What matters most is justice. 4.1 METHODS OF PUNISHMENT As briefly mentioned before, punishment must only be inflicted for the sake of justice. Only when the offender deserves it and the punishment must be proportionate. Many methods mentioned by Kant is prohibitions against punishments that could violate moral obligations towards other human being.13 Although this is not a specific method, it somehow provides control restraint in deciding a punishment for a crime. Alas, despite the crimes they committed, criminals are still human being and are not objects that can be handled without respect and care. Which is why, Kant had strike out punishments such as torture, mutilation and others similar to it. Plus, a way to determine whether a punishment is considered proportionate or not is to make sure that the punishment is the closest to the crime committed. As an example, if the criminal is a thief, the punishment must be to take away her property. If the person killed someone, his punishment must also be death. As the saying goes, “an eye for an eye and a tooth for a tooth and a life for a life.” According to Kant, any other punishment which is not the same as the crime committed is considered as unproportioned, therefore, unethical.14 Another point made by Kant is that, the principle of punishment is a categorical imperative. What he meant by this is that the principle is not to be altered or derived for the sakes of someone’s preference or convenience.15 Again, this is why, punishment must be determined by a person with 12 Faruqi, Muhammaf Yousuf. "Modes of Ijtihad in the Judgements." Intellectual Discourse 1, no. 1 (1993). http://journals.iium.edu.my/intdiscourse/index.php/islam/article/download/329/286/ 13 Hoffman, Robert. "A New Reading of Kant's Theory of Punishment" (2015). Publicly Accessible Penn Dissertations. 1063. https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations/1063 14 Aune, Kant’s Theory of Moral. 15 Potter, Nelson T. Jr., "The Principle of Punishment Is a Categorical Imperative"(1998). Faculty Publications Department of Philosophy. 22. http://digitalcommons.unl.edu/philosfacpub/22 9 capability instead of personal individual. More so if the person is related to the criminal or the victim, surely there will be element of bias. 5.0 COMPARISON BETWEEN KANTIANISM AND UTILITARIANISM Many confuse with the idea and concept bring up by both Kantianism and Utilitarianism. Despite of their similarity in term of the normative kind of ethics by which there is an objective of good can be sought, there are several differences between both Kantianism and Utilitarianism such as categories of ethics, basic approach applied and test of ethical correctness in both ethical theories. One of the differences between both ethical theories is the type of ethics categories in which they fall. As for Kantian ethics, it has been categorized under non-consequential theory or also known as deontological refer to the ethical doctrine that denies the consequences of an action is the only criteria for determining the morality of an action. On the other hand, utilitarianism is a part of consequential theories or in other word, teleological refer to theory that measure the morality of action on the basis of their non-moral consequences. An action is determined as right by considering the ratio of good to evil that the action produces. Both different category of ethics theories leads to the different implementation of action according to the situation as well. Furthermore, the basic approach in both ethical theories are also differ to each other as Kantianism applies autonomy in making ethical decisions which means an individual has the ability to make decisions about what to do rather than being influenced by biased-decision making. Apart from that, the approach being used by Utilitarianism is just that the greatest amount good or happiness for the greatest majority number of people in ethical decision-making by which an individual must acknowledge the consequences of an action in the future. For instance, a public hospital is considering closing a service line that is having trouble meeting budgeted revenues due to low volumes and difficulty recruiting needed physicians. After reviewing all the financial data and market information, hospital executives find themselves at odds over whether to shut down the service line or not. The CEO suggests they take a step back and look at the situation from an ethical perspective. As in Kantian’s approach of autonomy, they would come out with several questions such as; “Am I acting from the basis of reason alone?” “Can I rule out political influence, monetary influence, and pure self-interest?” While according to utilitarianisms in this case, they 10 will definitely prioritize the majority number of patients who are maybe in suffering when they decided on service line’s closure. Another aspect to compare both ethical theories is the test of ethical correctness. Kantianism bring up the idea of categorical imperative which formulated of universalization and maxim in making and determining ethical decisions. However, utilitarianism focused on the utility calculation where by actions taken should produce the highest amount of happiness and pleasure to an individual. As long as an action creates the greatest happiness at the end, the action is morally acceptable. For example, the euthanasia case of Brophy by which viewed in the definition of Kant, passive euthanasia as ethically wrong. There is need for the family to uphold the dignity to the life of Brophy, as highlighted in the decision made by the court. Such high regard for life will motivate the family to support the hospital in offering care to Brophy to prolong his life irrespective of his current hopelessness. This will demonstrate that they are responding to both the good will principles and duty as defined by Kant’s categorical imperatives. Moreover, Kant highlighted that it is the responsibility of the hospital staff to prolong the life of Brophy. In doing so, the doctors will be responding to moral duty as according to Kantianism, ethical decisions should reflect moral worth, goodwill and response to duty. On the other hand, utilitarianism is likely to support passive euthanasia intended by the family because it would make him happy. The prolonging of life in the vegetative state was not something pleasurable and therefore, passive euthanasia is the most ethical action at the moment according to utilitarianism. Moreover, passive euthanasia will translate to promoting common good because those people will leave the hospital bed and other resources that were being used for other patients who present a higher chance of surviving. As conclusion, both ethical theory of Kant and Utilitarian have different concept as well as way to implement in the real-life situations. To recap, categories of ethics, basic approach applied and test of ethical correctness in both ethical theories have been discussed as several differences between both ethical views which shared same purpose of being moral in human actions. 11 7.0 REFERENCES Atwell, John E. End and Principles in Kant Moral Thought. Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, 1986 Aune, Bruce. Kant’s Theory of Moral. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press, 1979. Bowen, Shann A. How Would Kant Approach This? A Model for Ethical Healthcare Business Decisions. 2015. http://www.hfma.org/Leadership/EBulletins/2015/July/How_Would_Kant_Approach_T his__A_Model_for_Ethical_Healthcare_Business_Decisions/. Faruqi, Muhammaf Yousuf. "Modes of Ijtihad in the Judgements." Intellectual Discourse 1, no. 1 (1993). http://journals.iium.edu.my/intdiscourse/index.php/islam/article/download/329/286/ Garrett, Jan Edward. “Kant's Duty Ethics”. 2006. http://people.wku.edu/jan.garrett/ethics/kant.htm Hoffman, Robert. "A New Reading of Kant's Theory of Punishment" (2015). Publicly Accessible Penn Dissertations. 1063. https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations/1063 Johnson, Robert, and Adam Cureton. "Kant's Moral Philosophy (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)". Stanford University. 2004. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/kant-moral/. Kant, Immanuel. The Metaphysics of Morals. Translated by Mary Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991. L. Anton, Audrey. "Kant on Irresistible Inclinations: Moral Worth, Happiness and Belief in God." Minerva-An Open Access Journal of Philosophy 19, 2015: 109-131. Potter, Nelson T. Jr., "The Principle of Punishment Is a Categorical Imperative"(1998). Faculty Publications - Department of Philosophy. 22. http://digitalcommons.unl.edu/philosfacpub/22 12 Scruton, Roger. Kant. London: Oxford University Press, 2001. Thomson, Garrett. On Kant. Australia: College of Wooster, 2003. 13