(In)definite determiners and referential anchoring in sign language MOTIVATION. Besides the reduced amount of works which describe definiteness marking on index signs in sign language (Bahan et al. 1995, Tang & Sze 2002), the encoding of signed indefiniteness is still an understudied area. Traditionally, it has been considered that noun phrases (NPs) are divided into definites and indefinites, and that the latter are further categorised into specific and non-specifics, schematised in (1). Definiteness marks knowledge of the entity the discourse is about by both the sender and the addressee. As for indefiniteness, while specificity exhibits a sender-addressee asymmetry since only the sender knows the entity, non-specificity is symmetric since it marks that neither the sender nor the addressee know the entity. After a detailed and systematic analysis based on data from a small-scale Catalan Sign Language (LSC) corpus, I propose that the traditional division among the tripartite structure of noun phrases must be reconsidered into a dual one, as definites and specific indefinites have the same semantics if referential anchoring (von Heusinger 2002, Onea & Geist 2011) is considered. Interestingly, referential anchoring is overtly expressed in the visual-gestural modality by locus establishment. The two-fold distinction among the referentiality of NPs presented here is schematised in (2). PROPOSAL. Both definite NPs and specific indefinites denote an entity which belongs to the common ground. That is, they are part of the shared contextual information. As for their semantics, they are represented with a variable that has wide scope over the other possible embedded variables and it is interpreted outside the operator. The only difference among the two types of NPs concerns the different conditions they are attached to: while definite NPs denote an entity that is presupposed to exist in the model, indefinite NPs assert their existence. The evidence for this claim is shown in the encoding of LSC data. Both for definite and specific indefinites NPs, the entity is established with a locus associated on the lower part of the frontal plane, which extends parallel to the body of the signer. As indicated in the subscripts of the glosses, the definite NP in (3) and the specific indefinite in (5) are directed to a lower spatial direction (Fig.1 and Fig. 2, respectively). In contrast, non-specific NPs denote an entity which does not belong to the common ground. It is asserted into the discourse but it is non-referentially anchored. The articulation for the establishment of a non-specific NP (7) is directed to the upper frontal plane with a lax movement (Fig. 3). From a semantic perspective, the main distinction is that definite and specific are referentially anchored at the level of discourse representation. They are anchored to another discourse entity and its interpretation depends on a previously established entity, which is overtly or covertly expressed. This dependency proposes a pragmatic enrichment, which introduces a functional dependency into the restrictor of the existential quantifier and thereby allows for wide scope readings. In the semantic representation of the definite NP in (3), shown in (4), and the representation for the NP interpreted as specific indefinite (5), implemented in (6), the Ident condition anchors the variable to a previous entity. This condition is not present in an intentional context (8). Moreover, the visual-gestural modality allows an overt marking for this anchoring with the establishment of the locus, which is covertly expressed in the spoken languages studied to date. CONCLUSIONS. This paper presents a new perspective on the localisation of index signs towards signing space, by introducing the concept of referential anchoring and by incorporating into the analysis the encoding of definiteness and specificity marking in an understudied language, such as LSC. The modulations towards signing space are analysed considering the epistemic status of the entity and its incorporation in the common ground. EXAMPLES AND FIGURES (1) NP = {definite; indefinite {specific; non-specific}} (2) NP = {definite/specific indefinite; non-specific indefinite} (3) IX3c FOUND ORGANISE MATEIX PERSON-3ip-l HITLER. ‘This was founded by Hitler himself.’ Fig.1 Locus for definite NP (4) x (hitler (x) Ident(x, anchor) this(y) found(x,y)) (5) ____eg:ip-l IX1 1-OFFER-3ip-l ONE PERSON-3ip-l COMPUTER PEN-DRIVE _____eg:ip-l ____eg:ip-l 1-OFFER-3ip-l, BECAUSE PERSON-3ip-l ALWAYS++ WORK THEME IS/SAME COMPUTER. ‘I will offer the pen-drive to someonespec, since he/she always works with computers. (6) Fig. 2 Locus for specific indefinite NP x (individual (x) Ident(x, anchor) pen-drive (y) offer(1, x, y)) (7) ____________________________eg:book _______eg:ip-u IX1 THINK IX3 BOOK 1-OFFER-3 ADEQUATE PERSON-3ip-u _eg:cl-u __eg:c MUST PERSON-3ce LIKE HOBBY IS/SAME TRADITIONAL PAST SAME/ALWAYS. ‘I think that I would offer this book to someonenon-spec... It must be someone who likes traditional things. (8) Fig. 3 Locus for non-specific indefinite NP x (book (x)) ◊ (individual (y) offer (1, x, y)) REFERENCES Bahan, Benjamin, Judy Kegl, Dawn MacLaughlin, Carol Neidle. 1995. Convergent Evidence for the Structure of Determiner Phrases in American Sign Language. In FLSM VI. Proceedings of the Sixth Annual Meeting of the Formal Linguistics Society of Mid-America, vol. 2, 1-12. Bloomington: Indiana University Linguistics Club. von Heusinger, Klaus. 2002. Specificity and definiteness in sentence and discourse structure. Journal of Semantics 19, 245-274. Onea, Edgar & Ljudmila Geist. 2011. Indefinite Determiners and the Pragmatics of Referential Anchoring. International Review of Pragmatics, 3:2, 194-227. Tang, Gladys, & Felix Sze. 2002. Nominal expressions in Hong Kong Sign Language: Does modality make a difference. In Richard Meier, Kearsy Cormier & David Quinto-Pozos, eds. Modality and Structure in Signed and Spoken Languages, 296-320. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.