ThiS article was downloaoed by:[Texas Tech University] On: 5 November 2007 Access Details [subscril1:ion number 782890830] Publisher: Routledge Informa Ltd Regstered In Engl<:tld and '/Vales Regstered Numtoer: 1072954 Registered office: Mortimer Hoose, 37-41 Mortimer street, London wn 3JH, UK The American Journal of Bioethics Publlca:lon details, Including Instructions for authexs and subscription Informa:lon' httP/!'M'!w,informaworld,cotrVsmRRIl:itle:content=t713606l39 Learning from Law's Past: A Call for Caution in Incorporating New Innovations in Neuroscience Jennifer S Bad a a Texas Tech university SchOU of Law, First PubliShed on: 01 september 2007 To cite this Article: B<rd, Jennifer S, (2007) 'Leamlng from LaN'S Past: A Call for Caution in Incexporating New Innov2tions in Neuroscience', The American J::lurnal of Sloelhics, 79, 73 - 75 To linktotnis Micle: 001' 10,108IY15265160701518888 URL: http/lax dcj orgl10 100011526510070151 Be88 PLEASE SCROLL FUll terms and corditions rj use: httP'MwN!lnlormawodd ooVVN FOR ARTlQ.E corrvtermNnd-condi~ors-ol-accesspdl This article maybe used lor research, teaching and pnvate stuOj purposes, ArT<J substantial or systemaUc reproduction, re-distribuUor, re-selling, lo<:tl ex sub-licensing, systematic supply or dislribuUor in <:tly fexm to anyone is express~ lorbi&len, The publisher does nct gve arT<J warr<:tlty eXlXess ex Implied ex make <:tly representa:lon tha: the contents 1'.'111 toe compete or accurate or up to d2te, The accuracy 01 any instructiors, lexmulae and ctug doses shoold toe independenUy venfied I'.'1th pnmay soorces, The publisher shall not be li2tlle lor any loss, actions, claims, proceedings, dem<:tld or costs or damages whatsoever or howsoever caused arising drect~ (( indirectly in connec~on I'.'1th or ansing oot rj the use olthis material Functional Neuroimaging and the La,,\, t- o o N ~ Factia, and polU:Yr l mes, 149-168. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Q) Press. E Johnson, D. 2001. Computer Ethics, 3rd ed. Upper Saddle River, NJ: ..c Q) 1; Prentice Hall. Z Rothstein, IV1., and '"o disdosure of health records: !\'fagnitude andirIlplications. A:met'h~im Journal (~f Bioethics 7(3): 38-45. N N Tovino, S. 2007. Functional neuroimaging and the la,v: Trends and « directionsf'or future scholarship. AmeriI'Rnjou!'I11l1 c:f Bioe!:hics (AIOB NeurGsci.eliCe) 7(9): 44---56. ~ :,,1. 'Talbott. 2007. Compelled authorizations for U. S. Department of ITealth and TIuman Services [HITS]. 2000, December 28. Standards for privacy of individually identifiable healthinf'ormation. FederalRegister45 CFRParts 160 and 164: 82461 82829. u. S. Department of Health and Human Services [HHS]. 2002, Au-gust 14. Standards for privacy of individually identifiable health information; Final rule. Federal Regi~ter 45 CFR Parts 160 and 16,1: 53181-53273. Westin, A. E 1967. PrizJacy and freedom. New York, NY: An theneurn. Learning from Law's Past: A Call for Caution in Incorporating New Innovations in Neuroscience Jennifer S. Bard, Texas Tech University School of Law Stacey 'Iovino's (2007) careful survey of the range of legal issues implicated by the CUlTent advances in brain imaging is an important contribution to the field of neurola\v, and I believe her revie'w will become foundational. Rather than comment on any of the specific areas of law she has identified, all of which 1 completely agree will be affected by the new imaging technologies, 1 'p,rouldlike to make some over all comments on the relationship of la'i'v, as distinct from law and ethics to brain imaging. 'What I 'i,vant to give primacy to is a call for caution 'i'vHh regard to using the technology in any field of law. 'rVe in law have an unfortunate history of jumping onto ne'p,r tedmologies only to find later that they do not live up to our expectations. In large part, I believe this is because there are so many areas of the linv that involve matters that carmot be quantified or definitely proved. Often, lav,ryers are trying to reconstruct an event that happened long ago or are trying to prove or disprove inher-ently intangible things such as the level of someone's pain from a physical or mental injury. As I 'will detail in the following text, there have been many technologies which 'ive have had to v,ratch as each new tedmology is first hailed as a definitive, scientific solution 'i'vhich 'i,vil1 incontrovertibly prove or disprove the maHer in dispute. 1l1ere are other ex amples of disappointments that are not related to proof, but rather promise ne\v solutions to v/hat had become unacceptable problems. Not to hide the ball, I refer here to the quest for a humane method of carrying out the death penalty. Civen this history of early adoption followed by very disappointing failures, I urge that that adoption ofnevv brain imaging technology, and indeed all new tedmology not be in advance of the pace of scientific research. In other words, we in law need to be not just sure but very sure that 'i'vhen live use a nev,,' technology 'we are doing so only to the limit at which science can offer an adequate assurance that the technology is indeed a reliable method of obtaining the information or result that 'i,ve are asking of it. In so doing, we must confront the reality that no technology 'i'vill every be 1C)(Y:i~ reliable and that it may take a long time to discover in \vhat 'Plays the technology is unreliable. A call for caution, however, is not a call for Ludditism. It is simpl.y a waluing that 'i,ve must appreciate that there will always be a risk of inaccuracy or inability to perform and that we must in advance establish the level of acceptable risk. Because the purpose of this comment is to be short and directly responsive to the target article, I make no claim that the follmving paragraphs provide anything such as a full history of the technologies we lawyers have adopted quickly and repented at leisure. 1 also will not elaborate on the current legal test for admission of scientific evidence into court because my concenlS are directed to the technologies themselves, not to their ad missibility. For a clear overvie'iv of this process there are several helpful texts in evidence (Mueller and Kirkpatrick 2003, 651-691) and law and science. (Areen et a1. 1996, ,150-483; SuHon 2001, I livill further disclaim that I am not Address correspondence to Jennifer S. Bard, Texas Tech Unive..l'sity School of Lell'v, 1802 Hartford Ave.nue, Lubbock, TX 79366. E-mail: iennifer.bard@thl.edll September, Volume 7, Nmnber 9, 2007 a/ob 73 The American loumal of BiDethies t- o o N ~ Q) ..c E Q) 1; Z '"o ~ N N « an expert in the history of technological disappointments in the law and can guarantee I am excluding -p,rhat may be the best examples. Fl:owever, here are four instances in ';,-,rhich technology \vas adopted quickly with great hope of solving a problem and was later discovered to be at best not as re-liable as expected and at V,rorst completely useless. I v,rill also note the consequences of these failures which, certainly in criminal matters involving IHe and death, are often quite serious. l EYEWITNESS TESTIMONY It is interesting how little the research of Elizabeth Loftus and her colleagues on the unreliability of eye"vitness testimony has penetrated either legal education or legal practice (Loftus and Do.VIe 1992; Mueller and Kirkpatrick 2003, 678680). Despite study after study in \vhich she, and those so-cial scientists -who have reproduced her -work, have shmvn that people not only are mistaken about "vhat they have witnessed but actually come to believe fully that v,rhat they think the.'v saw is what they did see. Although the unreliability of eyewitness testimony is discussed when the witness is a child, it is still true that in most cases when a \·vitness whom a jUl)!1 prosecutor or judge perceives as respectable testifies that he or she say\' something, unless another witness provides equally persuasive contrary testimony, the testimony is accepted as an accurate account of what happened. Although it is common in cross-examining an eyewitness to question, the conditions surrounding the identification if\vas it: dark?" Ii\·vere they wearing their glassesF' f/where were they standing?" ------it is not common to present direct evidence that eyev/itness testimony is neY! reliable. I think this is the case because unless directly challenged by a personal experience in which we believe we sa\v something but actually did not (and evidence professors he quently stage these events in classrooms) we all have an in-herent belief that the most reliable evidence is that v/hich we see ourselves. THE POLYGRAPH MACHINE When first invented, lie-detector machines seemed like a dream come true the fruition of the promise of certainty through technology was bringing to the 20th century. Based on observable measurements of physiological functions r the machine promised the ability to distinguish between a person who Vlas telling a lie and telling the truth. 'nlis promise was hailed not just by the legal system but perhaps more frighteningly by the various military and national security agencies entrusted with preserving the nation's safety by making sure that secrets did not fall into the hands of enemy agents. It Vlas also \videly adopted in various commercial settings to screen job applicants and employees accused of theft or other misdeeds. Unfortunately, on further study it \vas discovered that although the machine did accurately measure these bodily functions such as blood pressure and heart rate, there was no reliable correlation between these functions and truth telling. Many states "viII not permit any polygraph evidence and some will only permit it with the agreement of both parties (lvlueller and Kirkpatrick 2003, 675---678). It is the early promise and inherent plausibility of the lie detector's ability to ascertain truth telling that should be the closest cautionary example for use of functional magnetic resonance imaging (fMRI) tedmology as a lie detector. Although earl.'v results are promising that an fMRI can identify patterns in thinking, it is not yet and may never be the case that it untangle the very complicated human behavior of lying. DNA ANALYSIS The most recent example of a much heralded technology turning out to have unexpected limitations is the growing bod.V of evidence that it may be possible for a single inclividual to have more than one set of DNA (Arcabascio 2007). 'nle consequence of this finding is to call into question what has become an accepted fact: that a failure to match an in dividual's DNA with that found at the crime scene or even inside the body of a rape victim is sufficient proof to release a person from prison. The reliability of DNA evidence IS currently the gold standard for individual identification (Mueller and Kirkpatrick 2003, 668673), and has such a strong hold on the legal system that there are many active programs to free convicted felons based on re-examination of evidence in light of DNA technology. 'There has always been concerns that, \·vhen the jury is told of a DNA match, the match is represented as {'prooe that the sample tested is the defendant's DNA. In fact, DNA evidence only indicates the probabilit.V that the DNA belongs to someone other than the defendant (Mueller and Kirkpatrick 2003, 672). However, recent reports in the popular press that the phenomena of 1::\vo embryos merging to create one person with more than one set of DNA casts doubt on the underlying principle of DNA evidence,which is that ever.v person has a single and unique DNA makeup. While human chimeras may be as rare as their mythical counterparts, they will cast doubt on the reliability of DNA evidence until reliable research is conducted on the existence of these phenomena and, more importantl.v; on their prevalence. HANDWRITING ANALYSIS At one timer handwrlting experts \·vere touted as having a special ability to identH)! hand\vriting and to compare 1:\vo handwriting samples. VVhile these experts still exist! their rate of accuracy has not met expectations and in most juris-dictions any person is as qualified as any declared expert to compare a known writing sample of a person and a second sample v,rhose authorship is disputed. Indeed, the jury is often allowed to do this themselves (Mueller and Kirkpatrick 2003/1005). SUMMARY l 74 ajob 'fhis list could be extended to other tedmologies which held ~rTeat promise, were adopted \vith enthusiasm and turrted September, Volmne 7, NumbeT 9, 2007 Functional Neuroimaging and the La..\' t- o o N ~ Q) ..c E Q) 1; Z '"o ~ out to be at best much less reliable than hoped. In the case of neuroimaging I believe that, although the lay\' has no choice but to address the current reality that it exists! v/e must be very careful not to get ahead of the science by ascribing a level of validity and reliability to the technology beyond that v,rith which V,re v,rauld be comfortable in other areas. III t N N « Arcabascio r C. 2007. Chimeras: Double the DNA-double the fun for crinte scene investigators, prosecutors, and defense attorneys·? Akron Law l<eview 40: 435. LofhlS, E. 1996. Eye n;itness testimony. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Mueller, c., and L. Kirkpatrick. 2003. E'vidence. New York, NY: As- pen Publishers. Sutton, V. 2001. Tomv ami science. Ne,v York, NY: Carolina Press. REFERENCES Areen, Let aL 1996. Law, science and medicine, 2nd ed. Westbury, NY: The Poundahon Press. September, Volume 7, NlUIlber 9, 2007 Tovino, S. A. 2007. hmctional nemoimaging and the hw: Trends and directions for future scholarship. Ameru~an JounUil of BiDethu:s (.AJOB-Neuroscu:nce) 7(9): 44-56. a/ob /)