WRITERS AND CRITICS - BERTRAND RUSSELL. by John Watling. NOTE: The pagination of this text corresponds as closely as possible to the original 1970 edition of Oliver and Boyd, Edinburgh. 1 Biography Bertrand Russell was born in 1872. His mother died only two years afterwards, and his father a year and a half after that. His parents held advanced opinions on matters of social reform. They supported universal suffrage and rejected the view that birth control was immoral, and they were actively engaged in discussing and furthering these views.1 They were acquainted with some of the leading progressive thinkers of the time, including John Stuart Mill. His father’s will left both Russell and his brother in the care of two men – one of them had been tutor to his brother – who were both atheists. Russell’s paternal grandparents did not share his parents’ progressive views. They had little difficulty in obtaining custody of the children, and Russell was brought up by his grandmother, for his grandfather died a few years later. This grandfather, Lord John Russell, was eighty-three when Russell’s father died. He had been Prime Minister during two Liberal administrations, and before he became Prime Minister had introduced the First Reform Bill. He and his wife lived in Pembroke Lodge, a grace-and-favour house in Richmond Park. There are still such houses in Richmond Park, but Pembroke Lodge and its gardens are now open to the public. Russell spent his childhood in this house where his grandparents were visited by many eminent people, chiefly from political life. He was not sent to school until he was sixteen, when he went to an army crammer to prepare for a Cambridge scholarship. In his later childhood he was intensely interested in mathematics, as well as in history and poetry. When he was eighteen, he sat the scholarship examination for Trinity College, Cambridge, gained a scholarship, and went up to Trinity a year later. Before going up 1 The Autobiography of Bertrand Russell 1872-1914, pp. 15-17. 1 he read J. S. Mill’s Autobiography, Political Economy and A System of Logic, Herbert Spencer’s The Man Versus the State, and some works of Henry George. At Cambridge Russell obtained a First in Mathematics after three years and a First in Moral Sciences after another one. In his second year, he was elected to a semi-secret discussion society – known to outsiders as “The Apostles” – which included both undergraduates and dons and whose members were chosen as undergraduates, one or two a year, for their intellectual brilliance. Through this society Russell quickly became acquainted with people of ability and like interests, for A. N. Whitehead, who had examined for the scholarships, had been impressed by Russell’s papers and had suggested to other members of the society that they should call on him. Besides Whitehead, he came to know Ellis McTaggart and, later, G. E. Moore. Between the summers of 1894 and 1895, Russell spent three months as an attaché at the British Embassy in Paris, got married, spent three months studying at a marxist socialist movement in Berlin, and wrote a dissertation on the foundations of geometry, on which he was awarded a Fellowship of Trinity. The Fellowship did not entail teaching duties and Russell and his wife spent only part of their time at Cambridge; however he lectured on Leibniz in 1899. In the summer of 1900, he attended an International Congress of Philosophy in Paris with Whitehead, and so became acquainted with the Italian mathematician G. Peano. Russell had been thinking about the foundations of mathematics since he was an undergraduate and Peano’s ideas inspired him to start work on the book which became The Principles of Mathematics. He had completed the first draft by the end of the year, and felt some satisfaction at having brought the problem of the nature of mathematics so close to a solution before the end of the nineteenth century. It was also about this time that he became a friend of the French logician and philosopher Louis Couturat. Until 1910, Russell was concerned with the writing of The Principles of Mathematics and the Principia Mathematica. He undertook the immense labour of writing out the manuscript of the Principia single-handed, but still found time to write a few articles on other philosophical topics and to engage in some political activity. He made public 2 speeches on behalf of Free Trade and contested a by-election as a women’s suffrage candidate in 1907. He was elected a member of the Royal Society in 1908. After the publication of the Principia, Russell sought again to enter politics. He was a member of the Fabian Society2 but his views cannot have squared very well with those of its other members, for Russell has throughout his life been an opponent of state control. In 1910, he sought to become a Liberal candidate but was rejected because of his atheism. After this he turned to academic life and accepted a Lectureship at Trinity. Russell has said that the writing of the Principia damaged his capacity for abstract thought, but the period from 1910 until 1914 was, philosophically, one of his most productive. It was during this time that Wittgenstein came to Cambridge to study the foundations of mathematics under Russell. About this time Russell gave away nearly all the money he had inherited. Since then he has earned his living either by academic teaching, by writing books, or by journalism. Russell says that he had become a pacifist in 1901, having until then supported the Boer War. During the next decade he was dismayed by the movement towards war with Germany, and when war was declared he was horrified both by the immediate and the more distant consequences he believed it would bring. He became an active anti-war propagandist, advocating that individuals should refuse war service. He was an equally active opponent of conscription and of the treatment meted out to conscientious objectors. In 1916, he was fined £100 for “statements likely to prejudice the recruiting and discipline of His Majesty’s Forces”. These were alleged to have been made in a leaflet issued by the No-Conscription Fellowship concerning a conscientious objector who had been sentenced to two years’ imprisonment. Immediately after this case he was dismissed from his lectureship at Trinity College. He was refused a passport to enable him to travel to the United States to lecture at Harvard University, and restrictions were placed on his freedom of movement in the British Isles. Another prosecution arose from an article Russell wrote in the No-Conscription Fellowship’s weekly 2 Alan Wood, Bertrand Russell the Passionate Sceptic, 1957, p. 75. 3 paper. The article was held to be defamatory of the British and American armed forces, and Russell was sentences to six months’ imprisonment. Because of the influence of his friends and relations he experienced little of the extreme mental and physical hardship of other prisoners at the time. His cell was furnished by his brother’s wife and provided with fresh flowers, and he was able to devote his whole time to study. He wrote his book Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy. He published no philosophical work in 1916 and 1917. In 1919, Russell accepted an offer from Trinity to reinstate him, but he applied for a year’s leave of absence in order to lecture at Peking University and, on his return, resigned his lectureship. He travelled to Russia as well as to China and wrote books about both countries. Soon after his return he twice stood as Labour candidate for Chelsea, but was not elected. In 1927, he started Beacon Hill School with his second wife, Dora. Russell’s ideas on education fell significantly short of those of the most advanced thinkers of the time, such as Homer Lane and A. S. Neill, but the school allowed and encouraged great freedom of expression. It does not seem to have been a great success, perhaps because neither Russell nor his wife gave it their full attention, and perhaps because they lacked the ability to deal with the difficult children which a progressive school is likely to attract. Dora Russell continued to run the school after their marriage broke up in 1932. Russell became the 3rd Earl Russell upon the death of his brother in 1931. He seems to have inherited little but liabilities from his brother and at that time it was impossible to renounce a title. In 1938, Russell went to the United States and he lived there until 1944. He held the post of Visiting Professor at the University of Chicago in 1938, and at the University of California in 1939. While in California he accepted a post as Professor of Philosophy at New York City College, but before he took up the appointment an action was brought against the College by a New York tax-payer to annul it. Russell was not a party to the proceedings and was not allowed to take any part in them. The action was successful and the appointment was annulled on three grounds: first, that Russell was not an American; second, that he had not obtained the post by competitive examination; and third, 4 that he had put forward “immoral and salacious doctrines” in his books. Harvard University resisted pressure to cancel an invitation to give the William James Lectures in 1940. These lectures were published as An Enquiry into Meaning and Truth. From 1940 until 1943, Russell lectured on the history of philosophy at the Barnes Foundation in Pennsylvania; he had a five-year contract but was dismissed at short notice and successfully sued for wrongful dismissal. His lectures at the Barnes Foundation formed the basis of The History of Western Philosophy, which figured several times in the United States bestsellers lists. In 1944, Trinity College offered him a Fellowship and Lectureship and he returned to England. He gave lectures at Trinity which he published as Human Knowledge, its Scope and Limits. This was his last large-scale contribution to philosophy. In contrast to his reputation in America, Russell became a respected figure in Britain, giving the Reith Lectures for the B.B.C. in 1948, and receiving the Order of Merit in 1949. In 1950, he received the Nobel Prize for Literature. In 1940, Russell renounced his pacifism, although not without misgivings. In 1914, he had thought the domination of Europe by the Kaiser’s Germany preferable to war; in 1939, he thought the domination of Europe by Nazi Germany worse than war. On similar grounds, he supported British and American rearmament after the war, going so far as to advocate that Russia should be compelled by the threat of force to accept the provisions of the Baruch Plan for the internationalisation of atomic energy.3 He continued in this opinion throughout the Korean War, but towards the middle of the ’fifties he began to speak against the possession of atomic weapons by any state. He argued that it was possible to produce scientific evidence to prove that in a future war no nation could be the victor, so that no nation could achieve its aims by war. He proposed an international conference of scientists to report on the probable results of a nuclear war.4 This proposal was sponsored by an American, Cyrus Eaton, and the conference was held on his estate at Pugwash, Nova Scotia. This was the first Pugwash Conference 3 4 Christopher Driver, The Disarmers, 1964, p. 18. Portraits from Memory, pp. 221-7. 5 and, according to I.F. Stone’s Weekly, not a single American newspaper published its report.5 After this, Russell became more and more active in the movement to ban the testing of atomic weapons and, later, the weapons themselves. He was a sponsor of a number of organisations, including the Campaign for Nuclear Disarmament, of which he became the first president. When C.N.D. split on the issue of civil disobedience, he resigned his presidency and was immediately elected president of the more militant Committee of 100. He took part in the first of the Committee’s sit-down demonstrations against the government’s decision to provide facilities for the nuclear-missile-firing submarines of the United States. Later in 1961, he was summoned to court, together with other members of the Committee, and required to bind himself over to keep the peace for one year. Together with most of the others summoned he refused, and was sentenced to two months’ imprisonment. This was reduced to one week on medical evidence. At this time Russell was eighty-nine years old. Early in the ’sixties, Russell became convinced, not only that the United States’ cause in Vietnam was unjust, but that it was being furthered in a barbarous manner. He became actively engaged in an attempt to bring the facts about the war to the notice of the American public and the rest of the world. These efforts culminated in the first session of Russell’s international War Crimes Tribunal in Stockholm in 1967. This Tribunal was based upon a speech made at the Nuremburg war crimes trials by the chief prosecutor, a judge of the U.S. Supreme Court: If certain acts and violations of treaties are crimes, they are crimes whether the United States does them or whether Germany does them.6 The members of the tribunal were writers, scientists, politicians, and lawyers, many of them with an international reputation. The Tribunal heard evidence and examined the people who presented it; these included observers which it had itself sent to Vietnam. In the ’sixties, the prodigious stream of publications which Russell produced during the previous seventy years has 5 6 Christopher Driver, The Disarmers, p. 29. War Crimes in Vietnam, p. 125. 6 diminished, but still averages at least one a year. In 1967, 1968 and 1969, he published three volumes of autobiography. These take the form of an anthology of autobiographical pieces, written at different times and many of them reprinted verbatim from earlier works, together with a large number of letters written or received by Russell. They succeed by the direct, simple and witty fashion in which Russell tells many aspects of his life, his relations and his distinguished friends. Of all the various subjects on which Russell has written – and these include politics, pacifism, marriage and education – the present book considers only one: philosophy. It deals mainly with his writings between 1900 and 1920, concerning the philosophy of logic and mathematics and of our apprehension of reality. It is these books and articles which contain his truly original work. Note. This book was in the press when Russell died on 2 February 1970 at the age of 97. 7 2 Leibniz Russell’s first book on philosophy was An Essay on the Foundations of Geometry, the published version of his Fellowship dissertation. This essay presents an account of the nature of space which is a modification of Kant’s. I shall begin, however, with his second book, A Critical Exposition of the Philosophy of Leibniz. The book arose out of the course of lectures which Russell gave at Cambridge in 1899, and it was published a year later. It is important for the light it throws on Leibniz’s philosophy and for the doctrines which Russell set against those doctrines of Leibniz he held to be mistaken. It is important also because of the influence which the study of Leibniz exerted on the development of Russell’s own philosophy. This influence reveals itself in a number of details but also in one fundamental respect. Russell discovered that Leibniz’s metaphysical doctrines had their foundation in logic: the philosophy which Russell himself developed had this same foundation. Russell tells, in the preface to his book, how Leibniz’s Monadology seemed to him like a fairy tale: a fantastic, although coherent, picture of the world which there was no reason to accept, and which gave no clue as to Leibniz’s reasons for proposing it. Russell found the reasons he was seeking in the Discourse on Metaphysics and in the letters to the theologian Arnauld. These works convinced him that the philosophy of the Monadology was deduced from a few doctrines concerning the nature of propositions; doctrines which, apart from the conclusions which Leibniz drew from them, might seem unexceptionable. What is more, Russell held that the deductions were, for the most part, valid, and that Leibniz’s logical doctrines do have as a consequence a large part of the philosophy of the 8 Monadology. The logical doctrines themselves, however, Russell rejected. The fairy-tale nature of the Monadology can hardly fail to strike anyone reading it for the first time. Leibniz held that nature was composed of simple substances which he called monads. These monads were without parts, so that they did not have any extension and shape, and were indivisible. They did, however, have qualities. Indeed each had an infinite number of qualities, for no two monads were alike and there were an infinite number of them. In one way each monad was a world apart, for no change in a monad could be produced by the influence of any other; but in another way they formed a unity, for each monad reflected the state of every other, so that in the qualities on any one monad the truth about the whole universe could be read. Each monad developed by an internal principle, but the changes in all the monads fitted together into a perfect order so that the monads gave the appearance of influencing one another. This order was pre-established by one of the monads, God, who necessarily existed. Russell did not believe that the whole of this system followed from the logical doctrines of the Discourse on Metaphysics. Two non-logical principles were required, and apart from these, certain inconsistencies were present. Some arose from Leibniz’s deference to the prevailing religious opinions. For example, Russell pointed out that Leibniz’s doctrine that men pursue what appears to them to be the greatest good is inconsistent with the existence of sin, which Leibniz accepted. Russell indeed had a low opinion of Leibniz’s honesty, holding that he chose his arguments for their persuasiveness rather than their validity. Other doctrines of the Monadology, for example the view that there is more than one substance, are equally consistent with Leibniz’s first principles but were genuinely held. Nevertheless, Russell considered that the logical doctrines of the Discourse on Metaphysics formed the principle foundation of Leibniz’s philosophy. That all sound philosophy should begin with an analysis of propositions, is a truth too evident, perhaps, to demand a proof. 9 That Leibniz’s began with such an analysis, is less evident, but seems to be no less true.7 The logical doctrines which, Russell held, constituted Leibniz’s analysis of propositions were three: I. II. III. Every proposition has a subject and a predicate. A subject may have predicates which are qualities existing at various times. (Such a subject is called a substance.) True propositions not asserting existence at particular times are necessary and analytic, but such as assert existence at particular times are contingent and synthetic. The latter depend upon final causes.8 Premise I needs further amplification. It is doubtful whether Premise II expresses Leibniz’s most fundamental definition of what a substance is. There is considerable doubt whether Premise III correctly presents Leibniz’s view. What is not in doubt is this: that each of these premises concerns a matter which is fundamental in Leibniz’s thought and that his views on these three matters did, to a very large extent, determine his philosophy. Russell’s identification of these fundamental problems was, in itself, an important contribution to the study of Leibniz. Russell had no difficulty in finding, in the Discourse on Metaphysics and Leibniz’s letters to Arnauld, passages which contained Premise I. In his letter to Arnauld dated 14 July 1686 Leibniz wrote: Finally, I have given a decisive reason which, in my opinion, takes the place of a demonstration; that is, that always in every affirmative proposition whether veritable, necessary or contingent, universal or singular, the concept of the predicate is comprised in some sort in that of the subject. Either the predicate is in the subject or else I do not know what truth is.9 7 P.L., p. 8. P.L., p. 4. 9 Leibniz, Basic Writings, tr. G. R. Montogomery, 1962, p.132. 8 10 Russell held that the importance of Premise I lay in its consequences for relational and for numerical propositions. Both of these sorts of proposition played a large part in Leibniz’s philosophy; he did not deny their possibility but supposed that both were species of subject-predicate proposition and would appear as such if properly understood. Here again, Russell drew attention to a passage of considerable importance. The ratio of proportion between two lines L and M may be conceived three several ways; as a ratio of the greater L to the lesser M; as a ratio of the lesser M to the greater L; and lastly, as something abstracted from both, that is as the ratio between L and M, without considering which is the antecedent and which the consequent; which the subject, and which the object. … In the first way of considering them, L is greater is the subject; in the second, M the lesser is the subject of that accident which philosophers call relation or ratio. But which of them is the subject in the third way of considering them? It cannot be said that both of them, L and M together, are the subject of such an accident; for if so, we should have an accident in two subjects, with one leg in one, and the other in the other; which is contrary to the notion of accidents. Therefore we must say that this relation, in this third way of considering it, is indeed out of the subjects; but being neither a substance, nor an accident, it must be a mere ideal thing, the consideration of which is nevertheless useful.10 Leibniz insists on regarding the fact that L is longer than M as the fact that L has the predicate “is longer than M”, or that M has the predicate “is shorter than L”, but not as the fact that the relation “is longer than” stands between them. Russell produced no argument against this attitude until his next book The Principles of Mathematics. There he offers several arguments of which the following is the simplest, and perhaps the most cogent. No predicate of L which does not involve a reference to M can imply a relation between them, while anything which does involve a reference to M is not merely a predicate of L.11 That Leibniz 10 Leibniz, The Leibniz-Clarke Correspondence, ed. H. G. Alexander, 1956, p.71. 11 P.O.M., p. 222. 11 regarded “being longer than M” as a mere predicate of L is clear, as Russell points out, from the passage quoted above. It is also implied by Leibniz’s view that in the predicates of any one substance the whole universe is revealed. Once the predicates of any substance are given, then its relations to all other substances are given too. I have not found this particular point in Russell, although he quotes selections from the passage in the letter to Arnauld of 14 July 1686, in which it occurs. Russell was able to cite passages which established that Premise I led Leibniz to his doctrine of the identity of indiscernibles, but he could nowhere find the argument set out. He makes a suggestion as to how the argument ran, and it seems very likely that he is right.12 Consider two substances, let us cal them A and B. Between A and B, the argument goes, there will hold a relation which, in the logician’s phrase, implies diversity. For example, A may be longer than B, or it may be at a distance from B. Each of these relations implies diversity, for A cannot be longer than itself, nor at a distance from itself. Doubts about the assumption that at least one such relation must hold may be answered by pointing out that whatever relations between A and B are lacking, one at least must hold: that of not being the very same thing. This, in fact, is the relation to which Russell points, but the assumption that “not being the very same thing” is a relation may reasonably be regarded with suspicion. Premise I implies that a relation between A and B must be regarded as a predicate of one of them, or perhaps as a pair of predicates, one of each of them. The latter seems more reasonable, since the relation concerns each. If this is so, Premise I implies, for the relation we are discussing, that if A and B are two different things, then A lacks the predicate of being the very same thing as B, and B lacks the predicate of being the very same thing as A. Now A is the very same thing as itself, and this relation must be regarded as a predicate of A, so that A will possess the predicate of being the very same thing as A, and B the predicate of being the very same thing as B. Therefore the predicate of being the very same thing as A is a predicate which A has and B lacks, while the predicate of being the very same thing as B is a predicate which B has and A 12 P.L., p. 58. 12 lacks. From the assumption that they are not the same thing we have deduced that they are not exactly alike. Against this argument Russell contends that, whatever relations can be reduced to difference of predicates, the relation of numerical diversity cannot: For the numerical diversity of the substances is logically prior to their diversity as to predicates: there can be no question of their differing in respect of predicates, unless they first differ numerically.13 He concludes that if there exist two things, then there will be at least one relation between them which is not reducible to predicates, so that Leibniz’s doctrine that there are no relational propositions should have led him to the conclusion that there is only one substance. When Russell argues that numerical diversity is logically prior to diversity as to predicates, his point must be that having different predicates and having the same predicates both imply diversity, and hence that the diversity of two things cannot be due to their possession of different predicates. This argument of Russell’s is no more than a denial of Leibniz’s conclusion. It is true to say that two things have the same predicates implies that they are two, but that does not establish that their being two is consistent with their having the same predicates. It is this consistency which Leibniz denies. In the light of the logic which Russell’s later work did so much to establish, the doctrine that all propositions have a subject and a predicate is refuted by the existence of universal propositions, such as that all men are mortal. In that logic this proposition has the import that everything is either not a man or mortal. This proposition does not, on the face of it, have a subject and a predicate. However, in the present work Russell is prepared to regard it having as subject the property of being a man, and as being the proposition that this property implies, or involves, the property of being mortal.14 It seems that Leibniz believed that his general view that all propositions had a subject and a predicate left room for further enquiry as to the nature of such propositions. Couturat later published a number of papers by Leibniz in which various approaches to the logic of universal 13 14 P.L., pp. 58-9 P.L., p. 15. 13 propositions are sketched. On the whole, however, it seems that the view that Leibniz most often expressed and most wished to hold was the one which Russell attributed to him. Russell’s main failure lies in his interpretation of Leibniz’s views about propositions concerning individual people and things. Russell himself wrote in his preface to the second edition of The Philosophy of Leibniz: Wherever my interpretation of Leibniz differed from that of previous commentators, Couturat’s work afforded conclusive confirmation… But Couturat carried inorthodoxy further than I had done, and where his interpretation differed from mine, he was able to cite passages which seemed conclusive.15 The trouble arises over Premise III, which is amplified by Russell in a number of passages. He takes it as equivalent to the view that a proposition to the effect that being a triangle implies having angles adding up to 180 degrees is an analytic and necessary proposition, while one to the effect that Caesar invaded Britain in 55 B.C. is synthetic and contingent. While he is developing an objection to Leibniz’s doctrine of substance he says: Moreover, if this were the case, predications concerning actual substances would be just as analytic as those concerning essences of species…16 contrary, Russell implies, to Leibniz’s actual views. Now Leibniz often speaks of predicates of individual subjects as being “within the subject”, and Russell regarded a proposition whose predicate is within the subject as an analytic proposition.17 Moreover, not only does Leibniz, in passages quoted by Russell, speak of true propositions about individuals as being those, and only those, where the predicate is contained within the subject, but at least one of the deductions by which, according to Russell, Leibniz obtained his metaphysical conclusions explicitly involves this premise. I have in mind the passage where Russell outlines the deduction of the conclusion that each monad, or simple substance, is a world apart, in which no change could be produced by any other. Consider the proposition that Caesar invaded Britain in 55 B.C. If this proposition is true, this can only 15 P.L., p. v. P.L., p. 50. 17 P.L., p. 17. 16 14 be because the notion of invading Britain in 55 B.C. is contained within the notion of the subject, Caesar. But if that is the explanation of its truth, then the explanation cannot lie in the influence of any other substance upon Caesar. As Russell puts it, closely following a passage in the letter to Arnauld dated 14 July 1686, from which I quoted earlier: Every predicate, necessary or contingent, past, present or future, is comprised in the notion of the subject. From this proposition it follows, says Leibniz, that every soul is a world apart; for every soul, as a subject, has eternally, as predicates, all the states which time will bring it; and thus these states follow from its notion alone, without the need of action from without.18 This passage shows that Russell himself doubted that Premise III correctly represented Leibniz’s views. Yet in other places he firmly attributes to Leibniz the view of Premise III. Russell assumed – and it is an assumption which there is some evidence for but more against – that Leibniz identified being necessary with being analytic, and hence being contingent with being synthetic. He held that Leibniz took the propositions of logic and mathematics to be analytic, but those of physics to be synthetic. Russell says: The discovery which determined his views on this point was, that the laws of motion, and indeed all causal laws… are synthetic, and therefore in his system, also contingent.19 However, the passage which Russell cites expresses only the opinion that causal laws are contingent. It says nothing about whether they are synthetic: [Dynamics] is to a great extent the foundation of my system; for there we learn the different between the truths whose necessity is brute and geometric, and truth which have their source in fitness and final causes.20 Couturat’s view that Leibniz did not identify necessity with analyticity but, believing all true propositions to be analytic, saw 18 P.L., pp. 10-11. P.L., p. 16. 20 Leibniz, quoted in P.L., p. 209. 19 15 the distinction between necessity and contingency as a distinction between two kinds of analytic proposition, fits much better with Leibniz’s writings. Probably the implausibility of regarding an analytic proposition as contingent prevented Russell from attributing this view to Leibniz. Russell, indeed, found it implausible enough to regard necessary propositions as analytic. He saw a continuous line of development from Spinoza who regarded all fundamental truths as analytic, via Leibniz who insisted on the synthetic nature of the causal laws of science, to Kant who insisted on the synthetic nature of the propositions of geometry. Russell, as we shall see, himself carried this development to its end by insisting on the synthetic character of the laws of logic. Perhaps the strongest evidence for Couturat’s view is that Leibniz himself recognises the implausibility of regarding an analytic proposition as contingent. In Section XIII of the Discourse on Metaphysics, there is a passage in which Leibniz insists that all true propositions are analytic and tries to reconcile this view with his view that propositions about particular individuals are contingent: We have said that the concept of an individual substance includes once and for all everything which can ever happen to it and that in considering this concept one will be able to see everything which can truly be said concerning the individual, just as we are able to see in the nature of a circle all the properties which can be derived from it. But does it not seem that in this way the difference between necessary and contingent truths will be destroyed, that there will be no place for human liberty, and that an absolute fatality will rule as well over all our actions as over all the rest of the events of the world?21 Later, to remove this appearance that the difference between contingent and necessary truths will be destroyed, he says: In order to meet the objection completely, I say that the connection or sequence is of two kinds; the one, absolutely necessary, whose contrary implies contradiction, occurs in the eternal verities like the truths of geometry; the other is necessary 21 Leibniz, Basic Writings, p. 20. 16 only ex hypothesi, and so to speak by accident, and in itself it is contingent since the contrary is not implied.22 This explanation seems to make matters worse rather than better, for how can a truth whose contrary does not imply contradiction be an analytic truth? Undoubtedly it is passages like this that led Russell to his view that Leibniz held contingent truths to be synthetic. Leibniz himself sees that this explanation raises the same difficulty again, and attempts another explanation, this new one relying on a distinction between what is necessary ex hypothesi and what is necessary in itself. This, presumably, is a distinction between “If anyone were Caesar, then he would cross the Rubicon”, which Leibniz admits to be necessary, and “Caesar crossed the Rubicon”, which he denies is necessary. However, the distinction does not exist if propositions about the individual Caesar are all analytic. In yet another explanation, Leibniz insists that the predicate of a true contingent proposition, as of a true necessary one, is contained in the subject, but points to a distinction in the manner in which it is contained. Couturat found passages which explained this difference of manner as arising from the simplicity of the concept of a triangle and the infinite complexity of the concept of Caesar. None of these explanations is satisfactory, but their failure should not have blinded Russell to the attempt that was being made to reconcile the analytic character of all propositions with the contingent character of some of them. Leibniz’s view that the negation of a true contingent proposition is not selfcontradictory cannot be reconciled, as might perhaps be thought, with his view that in every true proposition the predicate is contained within the subject, by ceasing to regard this latter phrase as implying that all true propositions are analytic. In Section VIII of the Discourse on Metaphysics Leibniz writes: Thus the content of the subject must always include that of the predicate in such a way that if one understands perfectly the concept of the subject, he will know that the predicate appertains to it also.23 22 23 Leibniz, Basic Writings, p. 20. Leibniz, Basic Writings, p. 13. 17 Russell’s failure to grasp Leibniz’s views about necessity and contingency led him to criticise Leibniz for views about subject-predicate propositions which he never held. Russell was right on a fundamental point, that Leibniz held nature to be made up of substances because all true propositions have subjects. Russell says: The ground for assuming substances – and this is a very important point – is purely and solely logical. What Science deals with are states of substances, and it is these only that can be given in experience. They are assumed to be states of substances, because they are held to be of the logical nature of predicates, and thus to demand subjects of which they may be predicated.24 How right Russell is in this can easily be proved, for the passage from the Discourse on Metaphysics which I quoted above is followed immediately by this passage: This being so, we are able to say that this is the nature of an individual substance or of a complete being, namely, to afford a conception so complete that the concept shall be sufficient for the understanding of it and for the deduction of all the predicates of which the substance is or may become the subject.25 However, since Russell could not credit Leibniz with the view that propositions about individual substances are analytic he did not do justice to Leibniz’s notion of substance. The passage from The Philosophy of Leibniz which I quoted above continues: And this brings us back to the distinction, which we made in Chapter II, between two kinds of subject-predicate proposition. The kind which is appropriate to contingent truths, to predications concerning actual substances, is the kind which says “This is a man”, not “man is rational”. Here this must be supposed defined, not primarily by predicates, but simply as that substance which it is…Thus the substance remains, apart from its predicates, wholly destitute of meaning. As to the way in 24 25 P.L., p. 49. Leibniz, Basic Writings, p. 13. 18 which a term wholly destitute of meaning can be logically employed, or can be valuable in Metaphysics, I confess that I share Locke’s wonder.26 As the passage from the Discourse on Metaphysics shows, Leibniz’s substances are not destitute of meaning. Exactly the opposite is true – the substances afforded a conception which enabled them to be understood. Russell is right in saying that Leibniz’s doctrine that nature is made up of substances stems from his logical doctrine that every proposition has a subject, but, being wrong about Leibniz’s conception of subject-predicate proposition, he is inevitably wrong about Leibniz’s conception of substance. This same mistake led him to give Premise II as Leibniz’s definition of substance rather than the definition quoted above from the Discourse on Metaphysics – that an individual substance has, of its nature, a complete conception from which all its predicates may be deduced. There is no space here to discuss more than the fundamental attitudes of Russell’s work on Leibniz. The insight that these metaphysical views were founded on logical ones, led Russell to suspect that the same was true of a metaphysician of his own time, F. H. Bradley. Indeed, he found that Bradley shared some of Leibniz’s assumptions but was led by them to very different conclusions. However, this can be discussed better after we have considered the views which Russell formed of the nature of logic. 26 P.L., pp. 49-50. 19 3 Geometry and Logic Russell’s next book, The Principles of Mathematics, is very different from his work on Leibniz. In the first place, it is not a work of criticism but treats directly of an important philosophical subject, the nature of mathematics. In the second place, it deals with the subject in a comprehensive manner, so that an enormous number of different problems are raised and discussed. Since the main thesis of the book is that mathematics is a part of logic, it is inevitable that among these problems are many which are central in logic. In order to establish that mathematics and logic are one, Russell sought to show that all the concepts of mathematics could be defined in terms of concepts which belong to logic, and that all the theses of mathematics could be deduced from principles which belong to logic. In particular, he offered definitions of the notions one, two, three and so on, as they occur in such propositions as “There is one chocolate in this box”, and of such notions as equality in number, as it occurs in such propositions as “There is the same number of chocolates in this box as in that one”. He offered definitions of such notions as the sum of… and the product of…, and he offered proofs of the theses of arithmetic such as “The sum of two and two is equal to the product of two and two”. Since he held that geometry, no less than arithmetic, is a part of logic, one might expect to find definitions of such notions as point, straight line, and triangle, as they occur in such propositions as “These three points lie in a straight line and do not form a triangle”, and proofs, from principles of logic, of such 20 theses as “The sum of the angles of a triangle is 180 degrees”. However, no such definitions and proofs are offered. Russell did not claim that spatial concepts could be defined in terms of those of logic, nor that theses such as Euclid’s theorems followed from principles of logic: …we are to remain in the region of pure mathematics: the mathematical entities discussed will have certain affinities to the space of the actual world, but they will be discussed without any logical dependence upon these affinities.27 In fact, Russell did not recognise the subject which is ordinarily called geometry as part of mathematics; he held that it belonged to applied mathematics, together with such subjects as mechanics. Applied mathematics, according to Russell, was not a part of logic but belonged to natural science. Nevertheless he held that mathematicians did study a subject which was properly, if not ordinarily, called geometry and which was a part of logic. How is this subject related to what is ordinarily thought of as geometry? When Euclid presented his geometry he divided his theses into two kinds: those based upon other theses, which are now called theorems, and those not based upon other theses, which are now called axioms. (He employed another category of proposition, the definitions, but these can be regarded as theses and counted among the axioms.) If chosen correctly, the axioms would imply the whole of Euclid’s geometry. These axioms, as we have seen, were not regarded by Russell as theses of geometry: geometry was not concerned with the question of whether these axioms were true, nor did any geometrical theory assert them to be true. He suggested that geometry was concerned, not with the question “Are Euclid’s axioms true?”, but with questions of the form “If Euclid’s axioms were true, then would … be true?” Similarly geometry was not concerned, according to Russell, with the truth of any of Euclid’s theorems but with the question of whether a theorem was implied by the axioms.28 In just the same way someone might turn from considering the question “Are all 27 28 P.O.M., p. 372. P.O.M., pp. 372-4. 21 men mortal?” to the question “Is it true that if all men are mortal, then nothing not mortal is a man?” However, these modified geometrical questions involve spatial concepts such as point and straight line which do not figure in principles of logic, and which Russell did not regard as definable in terms of concepts belonging to logic. Russell interpreted these modified questions strictly, as questions about implication according to the principles of logic. The questions with which geometry is concerned always take the form, “Do Euclid’s axioms imply, according to the principles of logic, that…?” In the same way one might ask “Does the proposition that all men are mortal imply, according to the principles of logic, that nothing not mortal is a man?” One way of answering such a question would be to argue that since the concepts of man and mortality do not occur in the principles of logic, and cannot be defined in terms of concepts which do, then any principle of logic according to which the implication holds will be a principle according to which the implication would hold, no matter what concepts replace those of man and mortality. Therefore we need only consider the question “Is it true that, whatever concepts X and Y may be, if all X are Y, then nothing which is not Y is X?” Russell held that geometrical theses provided answers to such questions. Variables have replaced the spatial concepts and the theses are universal; they have consequences for propositions obtained by taking any concepts as the values of the variables. By these two steps, which might be called conditionalising and generalising, Russell obtained a subject which was indeed a branch of logic from the subject which is ordinarily thought of as geometry.29 It is clear that this branch of logic is of great help in the study of what is ordinarily thought of as geometry, and which Russell called “applied geometry”. A knowledge of it will enable a scientist who is considering a body of theses of applied geometry, each of which he holds to be true, to tell that they follow from a group of axioms. He will know that the axioms embody everything which needs to be assumed in order to deduce the theorems. All assumptions, analytic or synthetic, a priori or a 29 P.O.M., pp. 7-8, 372-4. 22 posteriori, trivial or important, obvious or doubtful, will be there. Russell believed that Euclid intended to produce such an axiomatisation of his theses but that, through lack of rigour, he failed in the attempt.30 Again, this branch of logic enables a scientist who is considering a group of axioms to see what they imply, and so, perhaps, to decide their truth. It is equally clear how strange it is to give the name “geometry” to a subject which is not concerned with spatial concepts. This strangeness was concealed from Russell by his use of such words as “point” and “straight line” for concepts which do occur in his subject but which are not the concepts of point and straight line. How this came about needs to be explained. Consider the proposition “All flesh is grass, but there is grass which is not flesh”. This might be thought of as a proposition to the effect that the concepts flesh and grass are related in a particular way, that is, as species and genus. A logician who recognised the similarity between this proposition and others such as “All squares are rectangles, but there are rectangles which are not squares” might be said to have appreciated the species and genus relationship, and if he investigated what followed from the assertion that two concepts were related as species then he might be said to be investigating the species and genus relationship. In a similar way, Euclid’s axioms may be thought of as a group of propositions to the effect that the concepts of point, straight line, and so on, stand in a particular relation. This same relation might be asserted to hold between other, non-spatial, groups of concepts. Russell characterised it as one which established a particular sort of two-dimensional order. A logician who recognised a similarity between Euclid’s axioms and another group of axioms involving different concepts, perhaps concepts applying to complex numbers, may be said to have appreciated what it is for a group of concepts to establish a two-dimensional order of this sort, and if he investigated what followed from the assertion that a group of concepts did establish such an order, then he may be said to be investigating twodimensional orders of that particular sort. In short, just as the investigation of the species and genus relationship is not an 30 P.O.M., pp. 404-7. 23 investigation of what relationship holds between the concepts flesh and grass, but of one particular relationship which might be said to hold between them, so Russell’s Euclidean geometry is not an investigation of what relationships hold between spatial concepts, but of one relation which might be said to hold between them. This is the force of Russell’s definition of geometry as the study of orders of two or more dimensions.31 Now in saying that the concepts flesh and grass are related by the species and genus relationship, we need to indicate whether we mean that all flesh is grass but there is grass which is not flesh, or whether we mean that all grass is flesh but there is flesh which is not grass. We indicate that the former is our meaning by specifying that flesh is the species and grass the genus. If we lacked the words “species” and “genus” we might use those for well-known examples of concepts which have been held to exhibit this relationship. For example, if we wished to say that the concepts square and rectangular were related as species and genus we might say that they are related “as flesh and grass”, meaning that they are related as the concepts flesh and grass are said to be related in the proverb. If this usage were adopted, a logician investigating the species and genus relationship would be said to be investigating the flesh and grass relationship, although all he is doing is to investigate a relation which, in a well-known proverb, is held to relate these two concepts. In the same way, when someone says of a group of concepts that they are related in the way in which Euclid’s axioms assert spatial concepts to be related, he needs to specify which concept takes the place of point, which takes the place of straight line, and so on. It is natural for him, in the absence of other terminology, to use the words “point” and “straight line” to mean “any two concepts which are related as the concepts point and straight line are said to be related in Euclid’s axioms”. It then seems as if he is discussing the spatial concepts of point and straight line although the truth is that he is discussing a relation which has been asserted to hold between them in a wellknown group of axioms. This usage explains Russell’s assertion32 that the concepts of geometry are definable in logical terms: the 31 32 P.O.M., p. 372. P.O.M., pp. 435-6. 24 concepts of Russell’s geometry were not spatial concepts, although they were given the same names. Russell’s geometry does contribute to our understanding of Euclid’s axioms, so that if these present the facts about space it contributes to our understanding, but not our knowledge, of those facts. However, it does this without contributing to our understanding of the spatial concepts which the axioms involve. When logicians perceived a common from between the propositions “All flesh is grass, but there is grass which is not flesh”, “All swans are white, but there are white things which are not swans”, “All squares are rectangles, but there are rectangles which are not squares”, each being to the effect that the species and genus relationship holds between two non-logical concepts, their investigation of this common form contributed to the understanding of each such proposition, but not to the understanding of the non-logical concepts. In the same way, Russell’s geometers who perceive that Euclid’s axioms share a common form with other axioms concerning, perhaps, numerical rather than spatial concepts, contribute to an understanding of Euclid’s axioms but not to an understanding of the spatial concepts involved. Certainly an investigation of the species and genus relationship, together with the knowledge that this relationship held analytically between the concepts square and rectangle, would contribute to our understanding of these concepts. If it were true that the relationship which Euclid’s axioms assert to hold between the spatial concepts held analytically between them, then Russell’s geometry, together with a knowledge of this fact, would contribute to an understanding of the spatial concepts. However, Russell believed, with justice, that the truth of Euclid’s axioms was a question for natural science. Russell’s geometry does not contribute to an understanding of the spatial concepts, even when it is taken in conjunction with other facts about them. Indeed, in Russell’s view, the propositions of Euclid which are commonly called definitions were asserted and belonged with the axioms.33 Among asserted propositions Russell distinguished only between those whose truth could be decided 33 P.O.M., p. 429. 25 by principles of logic, and those whose truth was a question for natural science. None of the axioms of Euclid fell into the former group. He allowed no third group of analytic truths into which the proposition “All squares are rectangles”, or some of Euclid’s axioms such as “The whole is greater than the part”, have been thought to fall. This view has been adopted by W. V. O. Quine as a basic tenet of his philosophy.34 It might be thought that Russell’s geometry could be characterised as an investigation of relations which might hold between spatial concepts, but this is not the case. Just as the investigation of the species and genus relationship concerns a relationship which has been said to hold between the concepts flesh and grass but which, it might be thought, our understanding of these concepts shows us to be one which could not possibly hold between them in the literal sense, so spatial concepts might be said to establish a certain sort of order and that order might be investigated, but an understanding of spatial concepts might show that they could not possibly establish an order of that sort. An example is provided, perhaps, by orders of more than three dimensions. Four-dimensional orders have been studied, and someone could assert that the spatial concepts establish a fourdimensional rather than a three-dimensional order, yet it is very doubtful whether they could possibly do so. It is very doubtful whether space could possibly have four dimensions, and an understanding of the spatial concepts may be sufficient to show it to be impossible. This subject which Russell held geometry to be, the study of orders of more than one dimension, is important and is a part of logic. It is the subject which a logician would make of geometry. Russell’s thesis that geometry is a part of logic entails regarding this de-spatialised subject, not only as part of geometry, but as the whole of that part of geometry which is not natural science. To regard it as a part of geometry is not unreasonable since it is of assistance in geometrical studies. It is the exclusion from geometry of any studies which contribute to the understanding of spatial concepts which is the great fault of Russell’s thesis. 34 W. V. O. Quine, From a Logical Point of View, 1953, Essay II. 26 Indeed the very same objection can be brought against his view of geometry that he himself brought against the view of arithmetic called formalism. The formalists, as Russell explains in the introduction to the second edition of The Principles of Mathematics, treat the numerals 0, 1, 2, and so on as variables and consider whether any concepts, related as the axioms of arithmetic declare the integers to be, would be related as the theorems of arithmetic declare the integers to be. The symbols “0”, “1”, “2”, undergo at the hands of the formalists the same change of meaning as the words “point”, “straight line”, and so on underwent at Russell’s hands: they come to represent positions in one-dimensional order and cease to represent integers. Russell says: Accordingly the symbols 0, 1, 2, … do not represent one definite series, but any progression whatsoever. The formalists have forgotten that numbers are needed, not only for doing sums, but for counting.35 The formalists regard arithmetic as the study of one-dimensional orders and leave no place in it for the attempt to define the numerical concepts which are used in counting. This criticism of the formalist view of arithmetic is the same as that which I have brought against Russell’s formalist view of geometry. Since he accepted it he should have admitted that, besides the investigation of whether Euclid’s axioms are true, there is another part of what is ordinarily called geometry which does not belong to logic. The nature of this part of geometry, the attempt to contribute to the understanding of spatial concepts, is left unexplained by Russell’s thesis that geometry belongs to logic. There is, however, one strong argument in favour of Russell’s view of geometry which I have not yet considered. Russell points out36 that mathematicians came, during the nineteenth century, to regard the non-Euclidean geometries as no less a part of geometry than Euclid’s. The axioms of the nonEuclidean geometries contradict those of Euclid’s, yet mathematicians considered that the study of all these geometries 35 36 P.O.M., p. vi. P.O.M., p. 373. 27 yielded truths. Russell’s view of geometry explains easily enough how this is possible: if these various geometries are concerned only with the question of whether their axioms imply their theorems, there is no contradiction between them. But this explanation raises a problem. On the ordinary view, according to which geometers are interested in whether Euclid’s axioms are true, there was a conflict between Euclidean and, for instance, Riemannian geometry, so that it was clear that both were theories about the same subject: one asserted what the other denied. But on Russell’s view the two geometries make independent assertions. Why should they be regarded as parts of the same subject? Russell’s answer was that just as Euclid’s axioms assert of a group of spatial concepts that they establish a two-dimensional order of a particular sort, so the axioms of one of the nonEuclidean geometries assert, of the same group of spatial concepts, that they establish a two-dimensional order of a different sort. A person who pursues the subject which Russell calls Euclidean geometry investigates one sort of two-dimensional order, a person who pursues one of the non-Euclidean geometries investigates another. Russell is right that geometers came to consider that both Euclid’s geometry and the non-Euclidean geometries yielded truths, but there is another explanation of how it is that they were able to do so. The fact that two assertions cannot both be true does not imply that they cannot both be possibilities. It may be that Euclid’s geometry and the non-Euclidean geometries present various possibilities for space. Each of the geometries may be possibly true, not merely in the sense that its axioms are not contradictory according to the principles of logic, but in the sense that the relations which its axioms assert to hold between the spatial concepts are relations in which the spatial concepts could stand. The invention of the non-Euclidean geometries would then be the realisation of spatial possibilities which had not been realised before: that lines which point in the same direction may yet meet, or that a straight line may be of finite length and yet have no ends. The truths of both the Euclidean and the nonEuclidean geometries may have concerned neither logical possibilities nor spatial actualities but spatial possibilities. This explanation fits, just as Russell’s does, without the fact that 28 scientists have suggested that one of the other geometries, and not Euclid’s, presents the truth about space. It fits too, as Russell’s does not, with something which many people feel: that the nonEuclidean geometries are spatial possibilities whereas the fivedimensional geometries are not. Russell’s explanation can make no distinction between those non-Euclidean geometries which are not as a matter of fact true of space and the geometries of more than three dimensions which could not be true of space, for none of them contradicts the principles of logic. In The Principles of Mathematics Russell not only argued for the thesis that mathematics is a part of logic, but presented a view of the nature of logic itself. The view is implied by the distinction he made between applied mathematics, which did not belong to logic, and pure mathematics, which did. In pure mathematics, the process of generalising has replaced every concept which does not belong to logic by a variable: this absence of any non-logical concepts constituted the defining characteristic of a proposition of logic. Russell called this characteristic “formality”, so that his definition of logic can be put by saying that it is a purely formal discipline. Since this definition relies on a distinction between those concepts which belong to logic and those which do not, it raises the question of how this distinction is to be made. Russell sometimes suggests that it can be done by reference to the process of generalisation. After describing an example of an application of the process, he writes: Here at last we have a proposition of pure mathematics…So long as any term in our proposition can be turned into a variable, our proposition can be generalised; and so long as this is possible, it is the business of mathematics to do it.37 This passage implies that the logical concepts cannot be replaced by variables, but this is not true. Perhaps the most outstanding example of the use of variables is provided by algebra, where they replace particular numbers which, Russell held, can be defined in terms of logical concepts. The logical concepts, or “logical constants” as Russell often calls them, cannot be defined as the residue of the process of generalisation. 37 P.O.M., p. 7. 29 Elsewhere38 Russell asserts that the logical concepts cannot be defined but only enumerated. He did not mean that they have no character in common which distinguishes them from other concepts. If that were true there would be no way of recognising a new concept as one belonging to logic, unless it could be defined in terms of those already admitted. That consequence fits the traditional conception of logic as a completed doctrine, but not Russell’s conception of it as a developing branch of enquiry. Russell meant, not that the concepts of logic have no character in common, but that it is impossible to define what that character is. He thought that the concepts of logic were so fundamental that they must enter into the definition of anything whatever and he thought it objectionable that they should enter into the definition of their own common character. It would be as if the concept of triangle were employed in the definition of shape. Russell held that with his definition of logic he had accounted for the differences between logic and the natural sciences. He held that the propositions of logic and mathematics concerned the fundamental logical concepts and other concepts of logic and mathematics which could be defined in terms of them. He held that they concerned such concepts and nothing else. He treated the process of generalisation as if it yielded propositions which have no concern with the subject matter of the original proposition, but are concerned with a new subject matter, the concepts of logic. Many of these are concepts of the different types of propositions, or of the different forms propositions may have: The process of transforming constants in a proposition into variables leads to what is called generalisation, and gives us, as it were, the formal essence of a proposition. Mathematics is interested exclusively in types of propositions….39 This view makes a convincing distinction between logic and natural science but it is not consistent with Russell’s definition of logic. The subject matter of a generalised proposition must 38 39 P.O.M., pp. 8-9. P.O.M., p. 7. 30 include the subject matter of the original. For example, if the theorem “No straight lines meet at more than one point” is generalised so that it yields “No matter what X, Y and Z may be, no two things which are X will Z more than one thing which is Y”, then the result implies the original theorem, and it also implies that no two sign-posts point to more than one town. Although generalisation will yield a proposition of logic, it is unlikely to yield a true proposition of logic. The process of conditionalisation will be needed before a logical truth is obtained, and conditionalisation does yield a proposition having different consequences from the original. It does not, however, yield one with a more restricted subject matter. Whatever conditional clauses are added to the above generalised theorem the result, provided that it is not tautological, will still have consequences concerning signposts and towns. J. S. Mill held, like Russell, that mathematics was the most universal discipline, but he did not make the mistake of combining this with the view that it had a narrower subject matter than the other sciences.40 This difficulty leads to another. Russell held that because logic has as its subject matter the different forms which propositions may have, whereas the natural sciences have particular things and non-logical properties, the principles of logic could be known a priori – that is, without experience – while those of the natural sciences could not. However, Russell’s definition of logic as a completely general subject means that logical principles imply some propositions concerning particular things and non-logical properties. If these cannot be known a priori, as his distinction between logic and the natural sciences requires, then neither can the principles of logic which imply them. In different works Russell gave different solutions to these problems. A discussion in The Problems of Philosophy41 hesitates between two solutions. In one of these he argues that a general proposition does not imply the existence of particulars of any kind, so that it does not imply any propositions concerning particular things. This inference, as we shall see later, is not in 40 J. S. Mill, A System of Logic, 1965, Book III, Chapters V and VI. 41 P.P., pp. 103-6. 31 accordance with Russell’s views on propositions, but even if the inference is valid the argument does not show that general propositions can be known a priori, for there are many propositions which cannot be known a priori but which deny, rather than imply, the existence of particulars of a certain kind. The proposition that there are no immortal men is an example. In the other solution, he argues that whether or not completely general propositions imply propositions concerning particulars or non-logical properties, they do not themselves concern those particulars or properties. They cannot do so, because we can understand the completely general propositions without any acquaintance with those particulars or properties, or any knowledge of what kinds of them exist. Therefore one fact which makes it impossible to have a priori knowledge of propositions concerning particulars or non-logical properties does not make it impossible to have a priori knowledge of completely general propositions implying them: the fact that we cannot even understand a proposition concerning particulars or non-logical properties without acquaintance with them, or knowledge of what kinds of them exist. However, this fact is not the only one which makes it impossible to know such propositions a priori. Even if a person is acquainted with certain particulars and so understands a proposition concerning them, there remains the question of whether he can know that proposition to be true without observing it to be true. Any reasons for holding that he cannot, apply equally to any general proposition which implies it. In another discussion,42 Russell asserts that the propositions of logic apply to all things and all properties, and that the proposition that if Socrates is a man, and all men are mortal, then Socrates is mortal is true “in virtue of its form”. He asserts that because the truth of logic of which this proposition is an instance does not mention any particular thing or particular quality it is wholly independent of the accidental facts of the existent world. This last assertion seems inconsistent with the first, and suggests the arguments he employed in Problems of Philosophy. However, it seems likely that by the qualification “accidental” Russell intended no more than “not true in virtue of 42 O.K.E.W., pp. 65-7. 32 its form”, so that the latter assertion implies only that the truths of logic are independent of those truths concerning particulars which are not true in virtue of truths of logic. This assertion is not a complete tautology; it means that the only facts concerning particulars and non-logical concepts which follow from truths of logic are those which arise from, and are explained by, truths of logic. Russell here admits that some facts concerning particulars do follow from truths of logic. This is the solution which is most consistent with his view of logic as having a subject matter peculiar to itself, but it is not consistent with his view that the truths of logic can be characterised as completely general truths. This is because a completely general proposition does not explain its instances, but merely summarises them. Russell’s views on the nature of logic are, in fact, a strange combination of rationalism and empiricism; the empiricist element – that the truths of logic can be characterised as completely general truths – best fits a philosophy in which no distinction is made between logic and mathematics on the one hand and the natural sciences on the other, except that the truths of the former are more general. The truths of logic and mathematics have no necessity which those of the natural sciences lack, their subject matter is no different, nor can they be known in any different way. It is a consequence of such a philosophy that there is no distinction, such as Russell makes, between those propositions concerning particulars and non-logical properties which are true by virtue of their form and those which have some other foundation. For example, there would be no distinction between the proposition that if Socrates is a man and all men are mortal, then Socrates is mortal, on the one hand, and the proposition that all men are mortal on the other. Such a view was held about mathematics by J. S. Mill before Russell and about logic and mathematics by W. V. O. Quine after him. There is an argument against this view which Russell was unable to advance, because it would have led him to the conclusion that the truths of logic were trivialities. It might be argued that the process of generalisation will never yield a true proposition unless the proposition about particular things to which the process is applied is a triviality. For example, if the proposition that Socrates is mortal is generalised it yields the 33 proposition that all things have all properties, which is false. Only, this contention goes, if the process of conditionalisation has first yielded a triviality, such as that if Socrates is a man and all men are mortal, then Socrates is mortal, will generalisation yield a truth. This argument is not obviously correct. For one thing, it might well be denied that such conditionals are trivialities. Again, if the process of generalisation is applied to an existential proposition it may yield a completely general proposition which is not obviously false. For example, the proposition that there is something mortal becomes the proposition that every property is exemplified by at least one thing. This contention cannot be decided without a more precise specification of the process of generalisation than Russell gives, but whether or not it is true it would offer no solution of his difficulties. Generalisations of trivialities are themselves trivialities, so that this contention would have the consequence that logic and mathematics were composed of trivialities and embodied no knowledge whatever, no knowledge, therefore, of the different forms which propositions may have. In the same way, Russell rejected the view that the truths of logic are analytic for, as we saw in Chapter 2, he accepted Kant’s view that analytic propositions are trivialities. He makes the same point in Problems of Philosophy.43 However, in a later work – “The Philosophy of Logical Atomism”44 – Russell seems inclined to revise his opinion. He reiterates the view that logic is concerned with the forms that propositions may take, but he also says that the propositions of logic must in some sense be tautologies.45 He was presumably influenced here by a doctrine of Wittgenstein’s which was a principal element of the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. This doctrine was intended to reconcile the view that the truths of logic are empty with the view that they are not trivial. Wittgenstein held that the truths of logic are tautologies, or analytic propositions,46 and he regarded tautologies as empty – to utter a tautology is to assert nothing. However, the utterance of a tautology may show what it does not 43 P.P., pp. 82-3. L.K., pp. 177-281. 45 L.K., pp. 239-40. 46 L. Wittgenstein, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, 1922, p. 155. 44 34 assert. Tautologies are not trivialities, for what they show is important. What Wittgenstein believed tautologies to show corresponded very closely with what Russell held the facts of logic to be: “the formal – logical – properties of language and the world”.47 It appears, therefore, that this doctrine of Wittgenstein’s – that there are truths which can be shown but not stated – would, if it were true, present an escape from the dilemma which confronted Russell, so long as he maintained his view that logic can be characterised as a completely general subject: either to accept that logic and mathematics belong with the natural sciences or to accept that they are wholly composed of trivialities. However, in his introduction48 to the Tractatus Russell says that he is not convinced of the truth of Wittgenstein’s doctrine although he did not believe that there was any respect in which it was obviously mistaken. It was at this point that Russell left the problem of the nature of logic. 47 48 L. Wittgenstein, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, p. 157. L. Wittgenstein, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, p. 21. 35 4 Bradley’s Idealism and the Doctrine of Internal Relations Russell and Moore became united in opposition to a philosophy which both had at one time accepted, the idealist philosophy of F. H. Bradley. The central theses of this philosophy are two: first, that what common sense and science take to be facts about nature are no more than misleading appearances; second, that this is inevitable, since it arises from the character of thought. Idealism shares with scepticism the thesis that knowledge of nature is impossible, but whereas the sceptic admits that we might believe what happens to be the truth – denying only that we can ever know it to be so – the idealist holds that this too is impossible. Indeed he derives this possibility from a more fundamental one, that of conceiving what happens to be the truth. No proposition whose truth we might consider could present nature as it really is. Bradley begins his book Appearance and Reality, which was first published in 1893, by arguing this thesis for propositions of subject-predicate form. In Chapters II and III he argues that a proposition such as “This lump of sugar is white” can only be explained as expressing a relation between the various qualities of the lump of sugar. Then he argues that it cannot be understood in that way, since propositional relationships cannot be understood at all. …a relational way of thought – any one that moves by the machinery of terms and relations – must give appearance, and not truth.49 49 F. H. Bradley, Appearance and Reality, 1930, p. 28. 36 In Chapter III, Bradley considers a number of ways in which relational propositions might be understood and rejects each of them. He must have been dissatisfied with his discussion, for in an appendix to the second edition he takes up the subject again. There he appears to have modified his conclusion and to be arguing, not against the relational way of thought in general, but only against one form of it: that in which relations are treated as external to their terms. Russell and other commentators have taken Bradley in this way and supposed him to conclude in the appendix that there are relations but that they are internal, not external, to their terms. This conclusion contradicts the discussion in Chapter III. It implies, as Russell pointed out, that there are relational propositions which are reducible to subjectpredicate propositions, yet in Chapter III, Bradley explicitly rejects this: The relation is not the adjective of one term, for, if so, it does not relate. Nor for the same reason is the adjective of each term taken apart, for then again there is no relation between them. Nor is the relation their common property, for what then keeps them apart?50 What Bradley in fact contends in the appendix is not that there are relations which are internal to their terms, but that relations could not be real unless they were internal to their terms. This, he believes, they cannot be, for if there are terms, those terms must be related, and must be related by external relations. Therefore relational propositions cannot adequately represent reality. The upshot is the same as in Chapter III, that a relational way of thought, “any which proceeds by the machinery of terms and relations”, must give appearance and not truth. However, in Chapter III this conclusion is based upon the contention that relational propositions cannot be understood; in the appendix, on the contention that relational propositions cannot adequately present reality In one place in the appendix where Bradley is developing this argument he takes the example of spatial relations. These appear to be external to physical things. The very same chair 50 F. H. Bradley, Appearance and Reality, p. 27n. 37 which stands near the table might, it seems, have stood elsewhere. What is more it might have stood elsewhere and retained the properties it now possesses. Why this thing is here and not there, what the connexion is in the end between spatial position and the quality that holds it and is determined by it, remains unknown… But any such irrationality and externality cannot be the last truth about things. Somewhere there must be a reason why this and that appear together. And this reason and reality must reside in the whole from which terms and relations are abstractions, a whole in which their internal connexion must lie… The merely external is, in short, our ignorance set up as reality, and to find it anywhere, except as an inconsistent aspect of fact, we have seen is impossible.51 Our attempt to present reality as a spatial arrangement of physical things is an attempt to present it as constituted by terms in external relations. We realise that this picture could not adequately present reality unless the relations were internal to their terms: that is, unless the nature of the things in space determined their spatial position. Reality has a character which could only be presented by terms in relation, if the relations were internal to their terms. Yet the externality of relations is essential to the relational way of thought. Therefore, reality has a character which cannot be presented by the machinery of terms and relations. Bradley did argue, in the appendix, that our feeling that relations must be internal to their terms is a recognition of a feature which belongs to reality but which we cannot properly express. He did not claim to be able to express this feature of reality, so he was not able to show directly that it could not be presented by the relational way of thought. Instead, he falls back on the arguments which, like those used in Chapter III, are directed against the intelligibility of that way of thought. The doctrine that relations must be internal to their terms would imply, as Russell saw, that if there are relational propositions they are reducible to subject-predicate propositions. However, in the appendix, Bradley’s words often suggest a further implication, and this is confirmed by what he writes elsewhere in 51 F. H. Bradley, Appearance and Reality, p. 517. 38 the book. For example, he says in one place, in an argument against external relations: But if the terms from their inner nature do not enter into the relation, then, so far as they are concerned, they seem related for no reason at all….52 When he speaks here of the “inner nature” of the terms he might mean their predicates, or adjectives, but he might mean more than this. A passage in Chapter XXIV indicates that he does mean more. In the passage he is concerned to prove that nothing which fails to give the whole truth can be true at all: For that which is not all-inclusive must by virtue of its essence internally disagree….53 His argument is this: That which exists in a whole has external relations. Whatever it fails to include within its own nature, must be related to it by the whole, and related externally. Now these extrinsic relations, on the one hand, fall outside of itself, but, upon the other hand, cannot do so. For a relation must at both ends affect, and pass into, the being of its terms. And hence the inner essence of what is finite itself both is, and is not, the relations which limit it. Its nature is hence incurably relative, passing, that is, beyond itself, and importing, again, into its own core a mass of foreign connexions. This to be defined from without is, in principle, to be distracted from within.54 Here Bradley asserts that the relations which a thing has to other things must be included in what he calls, variously, its nature, essence, or definition, and yet cannot be included in this. This is the further implication of the doctrine that if there are relations they are internal to their terms: in the definition of a term its relations must be contained. 52 F. H. Bradley, Appearance and Reality, p. 514. F. H. Bradley, Appearance and Reality, p. 322. 54 F. H. Bradley, Appearance and Reality, p. 322. 53 39 Bradley, no doubt, held that the second of these two parts of the doctrine would imply the first. For the fact that two things were related in a certain way would have to be explained, he held, by the nature, essence, or definition of the things and if it was explained by the definitions of each of the two things separately then the same fact would have two explanations. Or he might argue that it is essential to the fact of two things being two that one of them can exist without the other existing. Hence the relation between them cannot follow from the nature, essence, or definition of either. But with certain categories of individual it is not true, when two of them are related, that one can exist without the other existing. The natural numbers are an example: the existence of any number implies the existence of another number related to it. Bradley may have been wrong, therefore, to suppose that the first part of this doctrine would follow from the second. Russell discussed Bradley’s doctrines in The Principles of Mathematics55 and in a paper which he read to the Aristotelian Society in 1907, called “The Nature of Truth”.56 In both of these discussions he puts great emphasis on the impossibility of reducing relational propositions to subject-predicate ones. His intention was to disprove the view that the subject-predicate form was the only form which propositions could take. It is a common opinion – often held unconsciously, and employed in argument, even by those who do not explicitly advocate it – that all propositions, ultimately, consist of a subject and a predicate.57 In The Principles of Mathematics, he distinguishes two ways in which the reduction of relational propositions to subjectpredicate ones might be thought to hold. One he called the monadistic view of relations. It is the view that a relation between terms is reducible to predicates of the separate terms. As we have seen he attributed this view, with justification, to Leibniz. The other he called the monistic view. It is the view that a relation is a predicate of the whole made up by its terms taken together. This 55 P.O.M., Chapter XXVI. M.P.D., pp. 55-61. 57 P.O.M., p.221. 56 40 view he attributed, with less justification, to Bradley. We have already considered one of Russell’s arguments against the monadistic view. It is an amplification of an argument which Bradley himself employed in the passage quoted above58. Against the monistic view, Russell argued that there was one sort of relation for which the monistic reduction failed. These are relations, such as “greater than”, which if they hold between A and B do not hold between B and A. These relations are called asymmetrical. Now a proposition which has as its subject the whole composed of A and B together makes no distinction between “A is greater than B” and “B is greater than A”: it can express no more than that A and B differ in size. Hence asymmetrical relations cannot be reduced to subject-predicate ones in the monistic way. The inadequacy of both the monadistic and the monistic ways proved, Russell held, that relational propositions cannot always be reduced to subject-predicate ones. This conclusion is the contradictory of one of the two things which Bradley would have held to follow from the thesis that there are relations which are internal to their terms. Russell ignored the other, and called this one the “axiom of internal relations”. His argument convincingly refutes it. The impossibility of reducing relational propositions to subject-predicate ones established that if there are relational propositions they stand in no need of reduction. In The Principles of Mathematics, Russell showed that many of the propositions with which mathematics is concerned, for example, propositions about number, about space, and about infinite series, involve asymmetrical relations. Therefore, if these propositions are intelligible, the relational form of proposition must be admitted as legitimate in its own right, alongside the subject-predicate form. Russell, very reasonably, assumed the intelligibility of these propositions about space, number and infinite series, and claimed to have established that relational propositions are legitimate in their own right. In this way he could claim to have established that unless the view that all propositions are of subject-predicate 58 See note 2, above. 41 form abandoned, there could be no adequate philosophy of mathematics.59 Since, as we have seen, the doctrine that if there are relational propositions then they must be reducible to subjectpredicate ones was a central part of Bradley’s idealism, Russell’s argument, by establishing that relational propositions are legitimate in their own right, removed one of the main supports of that philosophy. However, Russell is mistaken in suggesting that it was the discovery of asymmetrical relations which refuted idealism. Bradley himself argued that no reduction of relational propositions to subject-predicate ones was possible. Russell’s argument concerning asymmetrical relations does no more than reinforce arguments which Bradley himself put forward. The difference between Russell and Bradley lay, rather, in the fact that Russell accepted the relational form of thought as intelligible whilst Bradley denied the intelligibility of any proposition which was not of subject-predicate form. The impossibility of reducing relational propositions to subject-predicate ones, in conjunction with their respective premises, led Russell to reject Bradley’s conclusion that only the subject-predicate form of thought was intelligible and led Bradley to reject Russell’s conclusion that the relational form of thought was intelligible. What refuted idealism was Russell’s perception of the absurdity of rejecting the intelligibility of all propositions about space and number, which compose a large part of science and common sense, on the grounds of the doctrine that all propositions are of subjectpredicate form. Russell often suggests that he has removed the reasons for accepting idealism, but the only argument he had against those reasons lay in the rejection of the conclusions which Bradley himself drew from them. This is indeed a good argument, and Russell sometimes brings it out clearly. Asymmetrical relations are involved in all series – in space and time, greater and less, whole and part, and many others of the most important characteristics of the actual world. All these aspects, therefore, the logic which reduces everything to subjects and predicates is compelled to condemn as error and mere appearance. 59 P.O.M., p. 226. 42 To those whose logic is not malicious, such a wholesale condemnation appears impossible. But later in the same paragraph he suggests that he has other reasons, besides the absurdity of the wholesale condemnation, for rejecting the bases of idealism. It is impossible to argue against what professes to be an insight, so long as it does not argue in its own favour. As logicians, therefore, we may admit the possibility of the mystic’s world…. But when he contends that our world is impossible, then our logic is ready to repel his attack. And the first step in creating the logic which is to perform this service is the recognition of the reality of relations.60 Of course it is not impossible to argue against what professes to be an insight. The fact that a man offers no arguments in favour of a contention does not make it impossible to offer arguments against it. What Russell intended was, presumably, that he had no arguments against the idealist rejection of the reality of relations, but did have arguments against any reasons the idealists might produce in favour of that rejection. He is mistaken, however, in implying that he has any argument other than that which consists in asserting that relations are indeed real, and his last sentence concedes this. Russell’s recognition of asymmetrical relations appears to be a refutation of Bradley, because he presents Bradley as asserting that there are relations which are internal to their terms: that is, he presents him as a philosopher who accepts the intelligibility of relational propositions, but reconciles himself to them by the belief that they can be reduced to subject-predicate ones. Such a philosopher might be convinced by the example of asymmetrical relations that relational propositions are intelligible in their own right. This was not Bradley’s position. He held both that if there are relations they are internal to their terms, and that if there are relations they are external to their terms. The example of asymmetrical relations reveals nothing to him that he was not already aware of. Bradley had in fact already done all the work of drawing out the consequences of the doctrine that all 60 O.K.E.W., p. 59 43 propositions are of subject-predicate form. It only remained to Russell to point out the absurdity of those consequences. By doing this and rejecting the doctrine he freed logic and philosophy from the dilemma either of engaging in the hopeless struggle to reduce relations to predicates, or of rejecting all apparently relational facts as unreal. This was Russell’s achievement. G. E. Moore wrote in an autobiographical essay61 that he devoted a long time to reading and trying to understand The Principles of Mathematics. It seems possible that he came to grasp the character of this argument of Russell’s more clearly than Russell himself did, for such arguments are very prominent in his work. He saw clearly that the conclusion which a philosopher draws from certain doctrines may constitute a reason for rejecting those doctrines, even if no other reason against them exists. For example, when considering the principles of Hume’s philosophy he wrote: Hume does not, therefore, bring forward any arguments at all sufficient to prove either that he cannot know any one object to be causally connected with any other or that he cannot know any external fact. And, indeed, I think it is plain that no conclusive argument could possibly be advanced in favour of these positions. It would always be at least as easy to deny the argument as to deny that we do know external facts….62 We must now turn to Russell’s discussion of the second part of Bradley’s doctrine concerning relations: that if a thing stands in relations to other things, then those relations must be included in its nature, essence, or definition. Russell considers two arguments for this doctrine, the second of which is the more important. This argument rests on the alleged fact that if two things have a certain relation, they cannot but have it, or, as Russell also puts it, if two things are related in a certain way, then if they were not so related they would be other than they are. The phrase “would be other than they are” must be taken to mean “would be different things”, 61 P. A. Schilpp (ed.), The Philosophy of G. E. Moore, 1952, pp. 339. 62 G. E. Moore, Philosophical Studies, 1922, p. 163. 44 and not “would have different qualities”, if the second of these expressions of the alleged fact is to square with the first. That they would be different things if not so related has the consequence that their not being so related implies a contradiction, hence that they cannot but be so related. That they would have different qualities if not so related does not imply that they could not but be so related. This premise implies, the argument goes, that if two things are related in a certain way, then it follows from their nature, essence or definition that they are related in that way. Russell does not cite any use of this argument by Bradley but it is not of much importance whether he ever employed it, for not only does the premise imply the conclusion but the conclusion implies the premise. Consequently whether or not any considerations which tell against the premise tell against a reason which Bradley relied upon, they tell against his conclusion. The premise indeed implies, and is implied by, the conclusion, for the premise is equivalent to “If two things are related in a certain way, then if they were those two things they would be related in that way”. Now the consequence that if they were those two things they would be related in that way will be true if, and only if, their being those two things implies that they stand in that relation. That is, it will be true if, and only if, their standing in that relation follows from their nature, essence, or definition. Is the premise true? Ambiguities which arise over such words as “must”, “cannot” and certain “if…, then…” constructions can make it seem plausible. The sentence “If two things are related in a certain way, then they must be related in that way” may be taken to express the triviality that if two things are related in a certain way then they are related in that way, but it may be taken to express the premise of the argument Russell is examining, that if two things are related in a certain way then they have to be related in that way. In the first interpretation the word “must” is taken to express no more than the necessity of the trivial implication. In the second interpretation it is taken to express the necessity of the consequent of that implication. Now to assert that this consequent is necessary is to assert that the two things have to be related in that way, that being those two things implies being related in that way. Therefore, in the second interpretation the word “must” is taken to express the necessity, not of the trivial 45 implication that if two things are related in a certain way then they are related in that way, but of the quite different implication, asserted to be a consequence of the circumstance that two things are related in a certain way, that being those two things implies being related in that way. This ambiguity is especially confusing in an argument from an assertion expressed by the sentence we are considering, for when the word “must” becomes separated from the “if…, then…” construction it can more easily be taken to apply to the consequent of the more trivial implication. For example, “If St Paul’s Cathedral and the Eiffel Tower are at least a hundred miles apart, then they must be at least a hundred miles apart. St Paul’s Cathedral and the Eiffel Tower are at least a hundred miles apart. Therefore, St Paul’s Cathedral and the Eiffel Tower must be at least a hundred miles apart.” Of course, it is natural to employ the word “must” in expressing the conclusion of an argument, just in order to indicate that it is the conclusion of an argument, but if the word remains in the sentence when it is used to assert the proposition which, once established, is needed as the premise of a new argument, then it may mislead someone into thinking that what was established was the impossibility of St Paul’s and the Eiffel Tower being less than a hundred miles apart. A similar ambiguity over which of two implications is being expressed can arise over certain “if..., then…” constructions. This ambiguity is directly relevant to the second of the two ways in which Russell puts the premise of the argument he wishes to examine. The sentence “If A and B are related in a certain way, then if any two things are not related in that way they are not the two things A and B” can be taken to mean that if two things, A and B, are related in a certain way, then any two things are either related in that way or are not the two things A and B. This seems the most natural way to take the sentence and it is an obvious truth, but there is another interpretation in which it expresses the premise of the argument Russell wishes to examine. In this interpretation it expresses the validity of the inference from the premise that two things, A and B, are related in a certain way to the conclusion, which is itself an implication, that if any two things are not related in that way then they are not the two things A and B. Once these interpretations have been separated it 46 is possible to accept the first and reject the second. This is what Russell does or, rather, seems about to do. He says that the force of the argument depends upon “a fallacious form of statement” and suggests that the premise “If A and B are related in a certain way, then if they were not so related they would be other than they are”, which is in the fallacious form, might be replaced by “If A and B are related in a certain way, then anything not so related must be other than A and B.”63 Russell seems to recognise the distinctions we have been considering, reject the premise, and suggest that it gains its plausibility from its similarity to the acceptable, and evidently true, proposition by which he replaces it. The sentence he uses for the replacement does express an acceptable and true proposition if we take the word “must” to express the necessity of the implication and not that of what is implied. It seems that the word should be taken in that way, for otherwise there would be no contrast with the premise which Russell declares to be fallacious. However, once he has made this point he restricts himself to the remark: But this only proves that what is not related as A and B are must be numerically diverse from A or B; it will not prove difference of adjectives, unless we assume the axiom of internal relations.64 Remember that to say of two things that they are numerically diverse is to say that they are different things, while to speak of adjectives of a thing is Bradley’s way of speaking of those of its properties which do not concern its relation with other things. The word “quality” is perhaps a more natural one to use for such non-relational properties. Russell’s comment seems irrelevant, for the conclusion of the argument did not concern difference of adjectives. The conclusion was that not being related as A and B are, implies having a different nature, essence or definition from A and B. To reach the further conclusion that not being related as A and B are, implies having different qualities from A and B we need to assume, as we have already seen, that only the qualities of a thing, and not its relations, can be part of its nature, or essence, or can follow from its definition. Therefore even the fallacious 63 64 M.P.D., pp. 58-9. M.P.D., p. 59. 47 premise did not prove difference of adjectives, and the fault to which Russell points is additional to, not consequent upon, the fallacious form of the premise. The implication which the fallacious premise has, and Russell’s revised premise does not have, is that things not related as A and B are could not but be numerically distinct from A and B. Russell’s comment leaves it doubtful whether he saw that this was so. Of course, it may well be that he took it for granted that only the qualities of a thing, and not its relations to other things, can be part of its nature. Together with that assumption the original premise does imply difference of adjectives while, even with the assumption, the revised premise does not, so that if the assumption is justified Russell’s comment draws a correct, if rather indirect, distinction between the force of the two premises. The suspicion that Russell did not grasp the distinction properly is strengthened by the explanation he gives of why the original premise is fallacious in form. After he has cited the premise “If A and B are related in a certain way, then if they were not so related they would be other than they are”, he goes on: Now if two terms are related in a certain way, it follows that, if they were not so related, every imaginable consequence would ensue. For, if they are so related, the hypothesis that they are not so related is false, and from a false hypothesis anything can be deduced. Thus the above form of statement must be altered.65 Far from showing why the premise is of fallacious form this explanation implies that it is true and of an acceptable form. Moreover, Russell was committed to the view that anything follows from a false hypothesis by the account of implication which he gave in The Principles of Mathematics.66 According to that account, whether one proposition implies another is determined solely by whether each of them is true or false. This is not ordinarily held to be the case. Of course, the fact that a premise is true and a conclusion false does mean that the premise does not imply the conclusion, but it is ordinarily held that the fact that both premise and conclusion are true, the fact that the 65 66 M.P.D., p. 59. P.O.M., pp. 33-4, 36. 48 premise is false and the conclusion true, and the fact that both premise and conclusion are false, all leave it open whether the premise implies the conclusion. According to Russell’s account, each of these three facts about the truth of the premise and of the conclusion means that the premise implies the conclusion and if the premise implies the conclusion, one of these three facts must hold. The relation in which a proposition stands to another when either it is false or the other is true, Russell called material implication. According to his account, implication and material implication are the very same thing. Since implication is the relation which justifies inference, Russell’s contention that a false proposition implies every proposition means that to infer from a false proposition is to infer validly. Of course, it does not mean that an argument with a false premise is a proof of its conclusion, for an argument fails if one of its premises is false, just as it does if the inference it involves is invalid. There is no similar mitigation of Russell’s contention that a true proposition is implied by every proposition. There is another consideration which seems to lessen the divergence between Russell’s view of implication and that which is ordinarily held. Russell puts it forward rather tentatively, after a complicated discussion, in The Principles of Mathematics,67 but he became more convinced of it later. For example, he makes use of it in the passage from Our Knowledge of the External World which we discussed in Chapter 3. He held that there is only one kind of implication: the proposition that no green things are red implies that no red things are green in no stronger, or different, a manner from that in which it implies that Paris is the capital of France. He held, however, that there are differences between propositions which express implications, for some have a greater degree of generality than others. The most general have no constants except logical constants and are completely formal propositions of logic and mathematics. Therefore, Russell can distinguish those principles concerning implications which belong to logic from those which do not. He assumes that this enables him to distinguish, among all the implications which hold, those which do so for logical reasons, that is, by virtue of their form. For 67 P.O.M., pp. 38-9, 41. 49 example, he would say that the proposition that no red things are green implies that Paris is the capital of France for no better reason than that Paris is the capital of France, while it implies that no green things are red because of the logical law that whatever properties F and G may be, any premise to the effect that no things which have F have G materially implies a conclusion to the effect that no things which have G have F. This latter implication, he would say, is grounded in a purely formal fact. This comes out in his discussion of the correct expression of the traditional syllogism in the final chapter of Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy.68 Unfortunately the view that material implication is the only relation of implication between propositions plays such havoc with the notion of reasons, or grounds, that once it has been adopted, there is no possibility of distinguishing one true proposition rather than another as the reason, or ground, of a truth. Since it is true that the proposition that no red things are green implies that Paris is the capital of France, and true that it implies that no green things are red, the logical law is equally the reason, or ground, of both implications. Russell can distinguish between a logical and a non-logical principle concerning implication, but not between implications which hold for logical reasons and those which hold for non-logical ones. Once implication has been identified with material implication, the premise of the argument Russell presented for consideration must be accepted. There is no possibility of distinguishing between “If A and B are related in a certain way, then if any two things were not related in that way they would not be the two things A and B” and “If A and B are related in a certain way, then any two things are either related in that way or are not the two things A and B”. Therefore, to be consistent, Russell should have accepted that every relation which A and B have does follow from their being A and B and is part of the nature, essence, or definition of A and B. He should have agreed with Bradley and accepted the second of the two parts of the doctrine that if there are relations, then those relations are internal to their terms: the view that relations would have to be part of the nature, essence, or definition of the related things. He could have rejected the further 68 I.M.P., p. 197 50 consequence that A and B could not but be related in the way that they are, for, according to his account of implication, the fact that one proposition implies another means that it is not the case that it is true and the other false, but does not mean that it could not be the case that it is true and the other false. However, although Russell rejected any distinction between the necessity of a proposition and its truth, he does not seem sure whether to reject the notion of necessity or to accept it and identify it with truth. Everything is in a sense a mere fact…. On the other hand, there seems to be no true proposition of which there is any sense in saying that it might have been false.69 If, as this suggests, Russell made no distinction between truth and necessity, it would help to explain how he could accept material implication as implication, for he would make no distinction between it not being the case that a certain premise was true and a conclusion false, and it not being possible that the premise should be true and the conclusion false. So, perhaps, if he had accepted that the relations between A and B are part of their natures he would not have jibbed at the conclusion that A and B could not but be related as they are. Russell’s quarrel was with the first part of the doctrine that if there are relations they are internal to their terms, not the second. He should have considered whether the second part implies the first, that is, whether it could be part of the nature of one thing that another thing existed. Russell’s treatment of the argument he presents for consideration can be explained in the following way. He saw the distinction between the idealist premise and the revised form he proposed and he saw that the idealist premise gained its plausibility from the obvious truth of the revised form. However, his commitment to material implication made it impossible for him to explain the distinction, or, indeed, had he grasped the distinction clearly, to accept it. Therefore he contented himself with the remark that the revised premise does not imply the view that relations are reducible to qualities. Since he fails to explain why that view follows from the original premise any more than the revised one, the relevance of this remark to the distinction he 69 P.O.M., p. 454 51 made between the premises is obscure. However, there is some justification for thinking that the premise in its original form does imply that view, and he should have considered more fully whether it does so, for, unless he abandons material implication, he is committed to that premise. Russell’s interest lay in the first part of the doctrine of internal relations. However, it seems that the second part too should be rejected and his account of implication commits him to accepting it, at least in part. Certainly it prevents him from distinguishing between relations – and for that matter qualities – which are part of the nature, essence, or definition of a thing and those which are not. In an article called “Internal and External Relations”70, published much later than Russell’s article, G. E. Moore argued that such a distinction could be made, and that while many relations were internal to their terms, many were not. He gave the relation “being father of” as an example of one which is external to its terms, and the relation “being intermediate in the shade between” as one which is internal to its terms. It does not follow, he asserted, from the fact that two individuals were, respectively, Edward VII and George V that the one was the father of the other. No one would think this followed unless he confused “Edward VII was father of George V and A was not father of B, implies that A and B were not, respectively, Edward VII and George V” with “Edward VII was father of George V implies that the proposition that A was not the father of B implies that A and B were not, respectively, Edward VII and George V”. The former is an obvious truth, the latter is not true, yet according to Russell’s account of implication they are equivalent. On the other hand, from the fact that three colours are respectively, orange, red, and yellow, it does follow that the former is intermediate between the two latter: these three colours could not have been related otherwise. Moore was correct in thinking that the identification of implication and material implication was responsible for this confusion but he was not correct in thinking that Russell was committed to the consequence that Edward VII could not but have been father of George V. If implication is material implication, the fact that one 70 G. E. Moore, Philosophical Studies, pp. 276-309. 52 proposition implies another does not have the consequence that it could not be that the latter was false and the former true. At least, it does not have that consequence unless, as Russell seems to have been inclined to hold, every truth is a necessary truth. Moore’s example of an internal relation is of a relation between colours, which are universals. His example of an external relation is of a relation between people, that is, between particulars. Wittgenstein claims that internal relations stand between such entities as propositions, possibilities and numbers: The series of numbers is ordered not by an external, but by an internal relation.71 It is distinctions such as that between the way in which the relation “being twice” is internal to the numbers four and two and the way in which the relation “being father of” is not internal to Edward VII and George V, that Russell’s account of implication confuses. It is perhaps surprising that one such distinction plays an important part in Russell’s own philosophy. This is the distinction between those entities which are constituents of a certain proposition and those which are not. These, then, were the arguments which led Russell and Moore to reject the doctrine that relations would have to be internal to their terms, and, since one of the central theses of Bradley’s idealism – that no proposition can ever present more than an illusory appearance – rests on this doctrine, led them to reject the idealist philosophy. The arguments reduce to two. First, against the doctrine that relations would have to be qualities of their own terms, Russell brought the demonstration of the fundamental importance of relations in mathematics and the absurdity of rejecting mathematics and much of common-sense belief in order to preserve the logical principle that all propositions are of the subject-predicate form. Second, against the doctrine that all relations would have to be part of the nature, essence, or definition of their terms, Russell in a confused way, and later Moore with greater clarity, pointed to the distinction between the triviality that it must be the case that if two things are related in a certain way then they are related in that way, and 71 L. Wittgenstein, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, p. 83. 53 what is not a triviality, that two things which are related in a certain way could not but have been related in that way. Besides the confusion between these two, Moore argued, there is no reason to believe the latter proposition. This leaves us free to believe what seems evidently true – that relations are not inevitably internal to their terms. The rejection of idealism left Russell with the task of developing a philosophy according to which it is possible to formulate propositions which present reality, not appearance, and so to conceive, and believe, the truth. 54 5 The Theory of Descriptions Bradley undertook his criticism of relations in order to demonstrate that there could be no facts of subject-predicate form. He says towards the beginning of Appearance and Reality: We find the world’s contents grouped into things and their qualities. The substantive and adjective is a time-honoured distinction and arrangement of facts, with a view to understand them and to arrive at reality. I must briefly point out the failure of this method, if regarded as a serious attempt at theory.72 A remark which he makes a few sentences later, concerning a lump of sugar which we might say is white, hard and sweet, indicates that he found the subject-predicate form of proposition as suspect as the subject-predicate form of fact. The sugar, we say, is all that; but what the is can really mean seems doubtful. Nevertheless Russell was not mistaken in attributing Bradley’s rejection of relations to his preoccupation with the subjectpredicate form: Bradley thought it of fundamental importance but believed it had not been properly understood. The distinction between subject and predicate, he held, was not a distinction within the reality which we think about – facts do not divide into subject and predicate – nor was it a distinction within ideas. Rather it was a distinction between the reality we think about and the ideas we apply to it, between what we think about and what we think it to be, between reality on the one hand and thought on the other. The distinction is essential to Bradley’s account of the nature of thought. He held that all thought is either complete or incomplete judgement. Judgement is an activity, half-way between believing and asserting, in which people engage. A 72 F. H. Bradley, Appearance and Reality, p. 16. 55 person makes a judgement when he applies an idea to a reality or, in other words, when he predicates an idea of a reality.73 It is because this is the only way in which a judgement can be made that the subject-predicate distinction is fundamental to judgement. All other thinking, such as questioning or supposing, is incomplete judgement. Perhaps Bradley would have regarded questioning as hesitation over whether to apply an idea to reality. On Bradley’s view, what is ordinarily expressed by saying that someone thinks that the lump of sugar is white would be more correctly expressed by saying he thinks whiteness of the lump of sugar. However, as we shall see in a moment, there is a further aspect of Bradley’s view which means that this expression, too, is not correct. It is, therefore, neither facts nor propositions which are of subject-predicate form, but thoughts and judgements. Indeed his view of thought dispensed with such entities as views, or hypotheses, which have been held to be the objects of questioning, supposition, belief, or assertion: in short, it dispensed with propositions. Bradley took this view of thought to have the consequence that a person can think of a subject only by applying ideas to it. Because thought is essentially the application of ideas to a subject it cannot be that a person thinks of, or has in mind, a subject to which he goes on to apply ideas. Rather it must be that he applies ideas to a subject which he does not otherwise think of at all. Russell endorses this inference of Bradley’s when he says in The Principles of Mathematics, that the doctrine that every proposition has …an immediate this, and a general concept attached to it by way of description… develops by an internal logical necessity into the theory of Mr Bradley’s Logic, that all words stand for ideas having what he calls meaning, and that in every judgement there is a something, the true subject of the judgement, which is not an idea and does not have meaning.74 This consequence of Bradley’s view leads to another. Because the subject of a person’s thought cannot enter his thought otherwise 73 74 F. H. Bradley, Appearance and Reality, p. 144 P.O.M., p.47 56 than through the ideas he predicates of it, a man cannot make one judgement by having in mind St Paul’s Cathedral and predicating whiteness of it and another by having in mind the Eiffel Tower and predicating whiteness of that. These two buildings cannot enter his thought, and any ideas by which he might be supposed to single them out will be part of the predicates of his judgements. So Bradley came to hold that all judgements have the same subject: the whole of reality. St Paul’s is not the subject of the judgement expressed by the sentence “St Paul’s is white”. The subject is the whole of reality and of this subject a complex idea is predicated, involving not only the idea of whiteness but also that of a cathedral dedicated to the first apostle. Any difference between two judgements which the same person might make at the same time must reside, on this view of Bradley’s, in the ideas which would be predicated in making it. He admits no propositions as the objects of thought and belief, but he cannot ignore the difference which he is unable to express in saying that in one judgement one proposition is judged true and in another, another. Instead, he expresses this difference by saying that the two judgements have different contents. It is the content of a person’s judgement which plays an analogous role to that played, in other views of thought, by the proposition he would be said to believe. The content of a judgement is made up of the ideas which are predicated in making the judgement: it is a complex idea. The proposition is made up of the things, qualities and relations which the person is considering: it is a complex of realities. Bradley’s view that the ideas a person predicates determine, at least in part, the content of his judgement, stands opposed to the view that the things, qualities and relations a person has in mind determine, in part, the proposition which he holds to be true. Russell rejected Bradley’s view of the nature of thought. He believed that when a person thinks, he is directly related to things in the world, to the qualities which they might have, and to the relations in which they might stand. This constitutes the realism which is the main characteristic of Russell’s mature philosophy, although in The Analysis of Mind, nearly twenty years later, he modified it so greatly that he could scarcely be said to hold it any longer. In The Principles of Mathematics, Russell accepts that when a person considers a question, makes a 57 supposition, holds a belief, or makes an assertion he is related to a proposition. He often speaks of propositions as containing or not containing entities of various kinds. For example, he says: Whatever may be an object of thought, or may occur in any true or false proposition, or can be counted as one, I call a term.75 Again, And it seems undeniable that every constituent of every proposition can be counted as one, and that no proposition contains less than two constituents.76 This notion of the constituents – Russell also speaks of the terms – of a proposition is one which he made considerable use of to express views both about the nature of propositions in general and about the interpretation of propositions of some particular kind. The notion of constituents is a correlative of the notion of logical form. We saw in Chapter 3 how Russell held that different propositions may share the same logical form. Euclid’s axioms, for example, share their logical form with any group of propositions which differ from them only in that other concepts stand in place of Euclid’s spatial concepts. The definition of logical form to which such examples point – that it is what a proposition shares with every other which differs from it only in respect of non-logical particulars of concepts – closely resembles Russell’s definition of a proposition of logic and suffers from the same circularity. The constituents of a proposition are the nonlogical particulars or concepts whose replacement yields a different proposition, but one of the same logical form.77 The view that propositions have a logical form and constituents implies that every proposition can be defined. Each definition must specify a logical form, the constituents, and the manner in which the form relates the constituents. For example, a proposition might be defined as having Socrates as subject and wisdom as 75 P.O.M., p. 43. P.O.M., p.44 77 L.K., p.238 76 58 predicate: its form is subject-predicate and its constituents Socrates and wisdom. If each proposition can be defined, then a distinction can be drawn between those of its characteristics which follow from its definition and those which do not. The former will be internal to it, the latter external. It is internal to a proposition that it has a certain logical form and certain constituents, but that it is true, if it is, is external. The proposition just defined could not have had a different subject but it could have been false. The definition of a proposition someone has singled out must not be confused with the characteristics by which he singles it out. It is no part of the definition of the hypothesis called after Avogadro that it is called after Avogadro. It could have been called after someone else and probably would have been if someone else had discovered it. It is part of the definition of Avogadro’s hypothesis that it is of universal form and concerns gases. It could not have been singular and concerned rocks. As we have seen, Russell’s account of implication has the consequence that there can be no distinction between what is internal and what is external. This did not prevent him from employing these notions in other guises. Russell may, of course, be wrong about the characteristics of a proposition which must be included in its definition. Different views may be held about what are the internal characteristics of a proposition. Among these internal characteristics certain relationships to other things might be included. In that case, the proposition would be internally related to these things but would not have them as terms. A word is needed for this more general relationship and it is natural to speak of such a thing being a part of, or occurring in, a proposition. Russell does speak in this way but sometimes, confusingly, he uses the word “constituent” in this more general sense. Russell’s realism is faced with three difficulties. First, it seems that a person can think of things that do not exist. Second, the proposition he considers sometimes seems determined, not by the object he is thinking about, but by the characteristics he singles it out by. Third, a person can think of things which he has never perceived, sometimes could never perceive, such as events which took place in the distant past or the experiences of other 59 people. In his first presentation of this view in Chapters IV and V of The Principles of Mathematics, he ignored the last problem and the solutions he gave to the first to are inconsistent with his realism. In “On Denoting”78, he repudiated these solutions, attacking views of Meinong and Frege which he took to be versions of them, and put forward a new solution. This was provided by the theory of descriptions. In “On Denoting” he is concerned mainly with the first two problems, and certain other difficulties. The solution which the theory of descriptions provides to the third problem was developed in Problems of Philosophy, and will be considered in the next chapter. In The Principles of Mathematics79 Russell includes chimaeras in his list of things which may be terms (that is, constituents) of propositions and again, later in the same chapter, he speaks of terms which do not exist, such as the points in a nonEuclidean space or the characters of a novel.80 The need for such non-existent terms is evident. On Russell’s theory a person cannot wonder whether Socrates was wise unless the proposition that Socrates was wise exists, and that proposition cannot exist unless it has Socrates as a term. Now it is at least plausible to assume that the non-existence of Socrates is no bar to wondering whether Socrates was wise. Certainly it is no bar to wondering whether Socrates existed. If Socrates could be a term of the proposition without existing, the problem would be solved. However, that Socrates is a term of the proposition implies that if he did not exist the proposition would not exist, so the suggested solution is a contradictory one. It is impossible that a proposition should have non-existent terms. When Russell argues, in “On Denoting”81, against his former theory, he points out that it is possible to consider propositions whose subjects, if they existed, would have contradictory properties – for example, the proposition that the round square is round. If this proposition is to exist, it must have the round square as a term but that is an entity which not only does not exist, but could not exist. Russell finds the notion of a 78 L.K., pp. 41-56. P.O.M., p. 43. 80 P.O.M., p. 45. 81 L.K., p. 45 79 60 term which could not exist more objectionable than that of a term which does not exist, although the notions are equally contradictory. He was here considering a view he attributed to Meinong, according to which some things exist and others do not. The latter were granted a lower degree of existence and were said to subsist. Russell had earlier regarded subsistence as sufficient to allow a thing to be a term of a proposition but in fact nothing short of existence is consistent with his notion of a term. However, the objection he presses is the absurdity of allowing any degree of existence to such things as round squares. The second inconsistent feature of the view of thought put forward in The Principles of Mathematics, arises over propositions expressed by such sentences as “I met a man”, “Every man is mortal”, and others involving such words as “all”, “any”, “some” and “the”. In part, Russell’s view of these propositions is in accordance with his realism. He says that the proposition that I met a man is not about the concept of being human: …this is a concept which does not walk the streets, but lives in the shadowy limbo of the logic-books. What I met was a thing, not a concept, an actual man with a tailor and a bank account, or a publichouse and a drunken wife.82 On the other hand he says a little later that the actual man he met is no more a constituent of the proposition than any other man: What is asserted is merely that some one of a class of concrete events took place. The whole human race is involved in my assertion: if any man who ever existed or will exist had not existed or been going to exist, the purport of my proposition would have been different…. What is denoted is essentially not each separate man, but a kind of combination of all men.83 A combination – more specifically, a disjunction – of all men is a strange entity. He seems to have postulated it in order to avoid accepting that the single sentence “I met a man” might express a 82 83 P.O.M., p. 53 P.O.M., p. 62 61 disjunction of propositions: either I met Jones, or I met Smith, or… He certainly held that the proposition expressed by that sentence implies and is implied by the disjunction, so the strangeness of the combination of all men does not make his view unacceptable. Equally strange entities are postulated as constituents of propositions expressed with the help of the words “all” etc., but “the” is treated differently. He held that a proposition expressed with the help of the phrase “the Prime Minister” had the one man who was Prime Minister as constituent, not a combination of men. So far this view is consistent with Russell’s realism, but it is open to an objection which led him to add other features which were not. Of course it also raises the first difficulty in another form, for it seems that the sentence “A round square is round” expresses a proposition, even though no round squares exist to be constituents of the disjunction of propositions this sentence is held to express. The view as I have so far expounded it does distinguish the proposition that I met a man from the proposition that I met a mathematician, even when the man I met happens to have been a mathematician, because it is all men, not merely the man I met, who are constituents of the former proposition and not every man is a mathematician. It cannot distinguish the proposition that I met a man from the proposition that I met a featherless biped, because every man is a featherless biped and every featherless biped a man. Nor can it distinguish the proposition that I met the Prime Minister from the proposition that I met the leader of the party in power, since both will have the same constituents. Russell believed that each of these propositions should be distinguished. To achieve this he allowed that the concept of being a man occurred in the proposition that I met a man, and the concept of being Prime Minister occurred in the proposition that I met the Prime Minister. He allowed a special class of concepts which he called denoting concepts. Such a concept could occur in a subject-predicate proposition while being neither its subject nor its predicate. For example, Russell regarded the concept the Prime Minister as occurring in the proposition expressed by the sentence “The Prime Minister is speaking” although he did not regard that concept as subject or predicate of this proposition. Again, he regarded the denoting 62 concept a man as occurring in the relational proposition that I met a man although he did not regard it as one of the terms of the relation. But such concepts as a man have meaning in another sense: they are, so to speak, symbolic in their own logical nature, because they have the property which I call denoting.84 Besides providing him with this distinction, the view that there are denoting concepts enabled him to argue that the implications of a subject-predicate proposition involving a denoting concept depend upon that concept and not upon what subject it happens to denote. The proposition that the Prime Minister is speaking implies that a minister is speaking, but it does not imply that Jones is speaking even when Jones is the Prime Minister. He also held that denoting explained why it is worth while to assert identity. It is a triviality that Jones is Jones, but, even when Jones is Prime Minister, it is not a triviality that Jones is the Prime Minister. His explanation depends on the occurrence of a denoting concept in the non-trivial identity, but it is not clear what the explanation is. This view that there can be denoting concepts which occur in propositions is inconsistent with Russell’s realist view of thought, for that view has the consequence that a person is concerned in thought with a proposition which is determined once its terms, its logical form, and the manner in which the form relates the terms are given. There can be no difference between propositions which have these three characteristics in common. Presumably it is this inconsistency which prevented Russell from explaining how denoting concepts enter into propositions. He seems to have held that a proposition had two parts – a symbolic part, or meaning, to which the denoting concepts belong, and an objective part to which the terms, or constituents, belong. This raises a number of problems. For example, if the proposition is composed of both the symbolic and the objective parts, why is it only the symbolic part which determines the implications of the proposition? 84 P.O.M., p. 47 63 When he returned to these problems in “On Denoting”, Russell confirmed two of his earlier assumptions and rejected two. He remained convinced that a person could, in some sense, consider questions and hold beliefs about non-existent things. On his realist view, thought is concerned with propositions, so this meant that the fact that there are no unicorns does not imply that there is no proposition to the effect that I met a unicorn, nor does the fact that France has no king imply that there is no proposition to the effect that the King of France is bald. Second, he remained convinced that the proposition that the Prime Minister is speaking is distinct from the proposition that the leader of the party in power is speaking, although the Prime Minister is the leader of the party in power. He reinforces this view with the new argument that the proposition that Scott was the author of Waverley must be distinct from the proposition that Scott was Scott, since George IV wished to know whether the former was true but, not being a logician, showed no interest in the latter.85 However, as we have already seen, he rejected the assumption that the King of France could be a term of a proposition without existing, and he rejected the view that concepts can occur in propositions in the form of denoting concepts, that is, as meanings rather than terms. We will consider his reasons for this presently. These four views left him with no alternative but to seek an account according to which propositions expressed with the help of such phrases as “a unicorn” and “the King of France”, do not have unicorns, or disjunctions of unicorns, or the man who is King of France, as terms, but do have as terms the properties of being a unicorn, and being a King of France. Since the question a person raises when he wonders whether he has ever met a wise man cannot depend on whether any wise men exist – although the answer to his question may depend upon that – the account of the propositions expressed by the sentences “I met a man” and “I met a unicorn” must be parallel. Russell discovered an account of all propositions expressed with the help of the words “a”, “all”, “the”, etc., which, he claimed, fulfilled all of his conditions. This account came to be called the theory of descriptions. It enabled him to solve all three of the problems 85 L.K., p. 50. 64 which faced his realism. Before discussing this theory we must consider some criticism of the arguments in “On Denoting”. Russell begins by referring to the theory concerning the words “a”, “all”, “the”, etc. which he put forward in The Principles of Mathematics. He says that this earlier theory is nearly the same as the theory which Frege suggested in an article called “Uber Sinn und Bedeutung”86 and he goes on to criticise a theory which he says is Frege’s. The title of Frege’s article has been translated in various ways; Russell would have given it as “On Meaning and Denotation”. Russell’s earlier theory is not the same as Frege’s and the theory he criticises in “On Denoting” is not Frege’s but his own. Russell takes Frege to hold, as he himself had done, that propositions have two parts – a meaning and a denotation. The concept of being the Prime Minister belongs to the meaning of the proposition that the Prime Minister is speaking, the man who is Prime Minister belongs to the denotation. Frege distinguishes the two elements of meaning and denotation everywhere, and not only in complex denoting phrases… In the proposition “Mont Blanc is over 1,000 metres high”, it is, according to him, the meaning of “Mont Blanc”, not the actual mountain, that is a constituent of the meaning of the proposition.87 Frege did not hold that a proposition consisted of two parts, a meaning and a denotation. He held that a sentence had a meaning, and sometimes a denotation, and he identified the meaning of the sentence with the proposition. For this reason he did not hold that the meaning of the phrase “Mont Blanc” belonged to the meaning of the proposition. He held that it belonged to the meaning of the sentence, that is, to the proposition itself. The denotation of the sentence, to which the actual mountain belonged, was no part of the proposition. In Frege’s theory, as in Bradley’s, the real things we think about do not enter into our thought. This misunderstanding, which is by no means without excuse, explains why Russell criticises Frege’s theory for 86 G. Frege, “On Sense and Reference”, in Philosophical Writings of Gottlob Frege, tr. Max Black & P. Geach, 1952, pp. 56-78. 87 L.K., p. 46n. 65 consequences which that theory was designed to avoid. The passage in which he does this is perhaps the best known in his work. If we say “the King of England is bald”, that is, it would seem, not a statement about the complex meaning “the King of England”, but about the actual man denoted by the meaning. But now consider “the King of France is bald”. By parity of form, this also ought to be about the denotation of the phrase “the King of France”. But this phrase, though it has a meaning provided “the King of England” has a meaning, certainly has no denotation, at least in any obvious sense. Hence one would suppose that “the King of France is bald” ought to be nonsense; but it is not nonsense, since it is plainly false.88 Russell is considering the theory that a meaning and a denotation are needed to make up a proposition and argues that the meaning being King of England is not what the proposition that the King of England is bald is about, so that it is not part of the denotation. The King himself is part of the denotation – in fact, he is the subject of the proposition – so that if England had no king a constituent of the denotation, and hence of the proposition, would be lacking. But if a constituent of the proposition is lacking, then the proposition itself is lacking. Russell actually writes that, on this theory, since there is no King of France, “ ‘The King of France is bald’ ought to be nonsense”, but this is his way of saying that the proposition that the King of France is bald ought to be nonsense, that is, that the proposition that the King of France is bald ought not to exist. He has been taken, particularly by P. F. Strawson89, to be saying that the sentence “the King of France is bald” ought to be meaningless but, although he is not consistent in his use of quotation marks, he cannot here be speaking of the sentence for since, earlier in the passage, he admits that the phrase “the King of France” would have a meaning, he cannot have thought that he had given any reason for concluding that the sentence containing the phrase would have none. It is not unnatural to say that a proposition is nonsense and 88 L.K., p. 46 P. F. Strawson, “On Referring”, in Classics of Analytic Philosophy, ed. Robert R. Ammerman, 1965, pp. 315-34. 89 66 to mean that there is no such proposition. In fact, Russell asserts in this passage exactly what Strawson himself maintains: that on a theory according to which denoting phrases, such as “the King of France”, have a meaning and denote a denotation, the sentences in which the phrases occur will have a meaning but will express no proposition if the denotation is lacking. Strawson differs from Russell only in his attitude towards this consequence. Russell held that, since it is plainly false that the King of France is bald, there plainly is a proposition to the effect that the King of France is bald, and the theory must be rejected. Strawson held that it is neither true nor false that the King of France is bald, so that the theory can stand. Strawson is mistaken in attributing Russell’s rejection of the theory to a mistake about meaning. He claims that Russell confused having meaning with expressing a proposition which is true or false and that he argued from the premise that the sentence “the King of France is bald” has meaning to the conclusion that it expresses a proposition which is false. However, in this passage Russell rejects his former theory on the grounds that while it allows meaning to the phrase “the King of France” it cannot explain how the sentence “the King of France is bald” can express a false proposition. The closing words of the passage are “since it is plainly false”. Whether the “it” stands for the sentence “the King of France is bald” or the proposition that the King of France is bald, these words express the premise, not an intermediate step, of his argument. What is interesting in Strawson’s criticism is the suggestion that Russell should not have been so ready to reject the conclusion that when there is no King of France there is no proposition to the effect that the King of France is bald. Probably Russell argued that if he accepted it, then he would have to accept the conclusion that when there is no King of France there is no proposition to the effect that the King of France does not exist. Strawson’s own theory is a revised form of Russell’s earlier theory. Whether it avoids the other objections Russell brought against that theory cannot be considered here. The view that denoting phrases have meanings which, in favourable circumstances, single out an entity or group of entities which may be called their denotation might be thought to leave three possibilities open. Either the meaning alone, or the denotation alone, or both meaning and denotation, might be 67 regarded as internal to a proposition expressed with the help of the phrase. If he had believed that this view of denoting phrases did leave open all three possibilities, Russell would have accepted the first and rejected the second and third. He rejects the third in the passage we have been considering, because it has the consequence that if there is no denotation there is no proposition. He rejects the second for the same reason and, independently, because it has the consequence that, although the sentences “Scott is Scott” and “Scott is the author of Waverley” have different meanings, they express the same proposition. He would accept the first because it avoids both these difficulties. That, too, was Frege’s reason for accepting it. However, Russell did not believe that the view did leave either the first or the third possibility open. He argues that if the meaning of a denoting phrase were part of a proposition then that proposition would have as a term, not the meaning, but the entity singled out by the meaning. Therefore the meaning cannot be part of a proposition. He says that whenever a denoting phrase occurs in a sentence …what is said is not true of the meaning, but only of the denotation, as when we say: The centre of mass of the solar system is a point. A little later he concludes: …so long as we adhere to this point of view, we are compelled to hold that only the denotation can be relevant.90 He is arguing from his realist position that a proposition is composed only of the particulars, qualities and relations which are its terms. If the phrase “the centre of mass of the solar system” has a meaning and a denotation, then one or the other of them would be the subject of the proposition. Clearly that one would be the denotation, not the meaning, so that it would be the denotation which was internal to the proposition. Frege, holding a very different view of thought, was able to accept that the meaning and not the denotation of the denoting phrase could be internal to the proposition expressed with its help, and so hold that the view that denoting phrases have meaning and denotation 90 L.K., p. 50 68 had just the consequences which Russell was seeking to embody in a theory. Here again there is an unrecognised agreement between Strawson’s views and Russell’s. Like Russell, Strawson seems to find only the second possibility consistent with this view of denoting phrases. Unlike Russell he is prepared to accept it. According to Strawson it is the fact that denoting phrases have meaning that enables people to use them to single out entities – he calls this activity “referring” – and so to express propositions about those entities. However, he does not seem willing to admit that this view has the consequences which led Russell to reject it, for example, that by the sentences “Scott is Scott” and “Scott is the author of Waverley”, a person expresses the very same proposition, although by different means. We must now turn to the theory of descriptions, Russell’s own solution of these difficulties. He found propositions, whose expression did not involve denoting phrases, which, he claimed, clearly did not have the entity which he had formerly regarded as the denotation of the denoting phrase as a term, and clearly did have as terms the qualities and relations which he had formerly regarded as the meaning of the denoting phrase. These propositions he identified with the propositions expressed with the help of denoting phrases. For example, he identified the proposition expressed by the sentence “I met a man”, which involves the denoting phrase “a man”, with that expressed by the sentence “there was something which was both human and met by me”. This procedure he calls presenting an analysis of the proposition. Although he gives different analyses for the different denoting phrases, they have a common feature. In the unanalysed expression of the propositions the denoting phrases occur as units such as “a man”, “all men”, “the men”, and they seem to work as units, having a meaning by which they single out an entity or group of entities as a term of the proposition. In the analysed expression the words “a”, “all”, “the”, are no longer united with the concept words, nor do the pairs work as units. The word “the” disappears entirely. For example, the proposition that I met a man is identified with the proposition that a thing was both human and met by me. The proposition that I met all men is identified with the proposition that all things were either not 69 human or met by me. The analysis of the proposition that I met the man is more complicated. Russell held that this proposition implies the proposition that I met a manrom it solely in having the further implication that only one man exists. If it were true that there was one and only one thing which was human Russell would be prepared to speak of that man as the denotation of the phrase “the man”. That man, however, is not a term of the proposition expressed by the sentence “I met the man”, nor does the phrase “the man” have a meaning as a unit because if it had, its function would be to single out an entity as a term of the proposition expressed by the sentence.91 These analyses enabled Russell to explain in what sense it is that we can consider questions about non-existent things. If a person considers whether he has ever met a wise man he considers whether there was something which was wise, human, and met by him. He can do this even if no wise men exist. Similarly, he can consider whether the author of the Iliad was blind because he can consider whether there was no more than one person who wrote the Iliad and whether there was a person who both wrote the Iliad and was blind. He can do this even if the Iliad was in fact a collection of folk tales without an author. However, if the analysis is to be used to explain in what sense we can think of Homer if he did not exist then the proposition that Homer was blind must be identified with some proposition expressed by means of a denoting phrase. It might be identified with the proposition that the author of the Iliad was blind. Russell held that we can think about non-existent things or people only in such ways as this. He says that in the sentence “Homer was blind” the word “Homer” is a description and not a proper name. He sometimes says that it is not a logically proper name, meaning that it is grammatically a proper name but does not introduce an entity as subject, or other constituent, of the proposition. He held that a person can understand a proposition only if he can have its constituents in mind directly. This, he thought, a person can only do if he has been in some direct cognitive relation to them. A person cannot understand a proposition having a particular as constituent unless he has perceived that particular, nor one 91 L.K., p. 51 70 having a quality or relation has constituent unless he has acquired an intellectual grasp of that quality or relation. These were the two ways in which a person could have acquaintance with an entity.92 If the proposition that the author of the Iliad did not exist is analysed in the way we have been considering, it would be identified with the contradiction that only one person wrote the Iliad and did not exist. For such propositions Russell proposed a different analysis: it is not true that one and only one person wrote the Iliad. Even existential propositions concerning particulars which are objects of acquaintance should, perhaps, be analysed in this way. A particular with which a person is acquainted might not have existed. If it had not, then it could not have been a constituent of the proposition that it exists. Some philosophers take it as a principle that the thoughts a person thinks, and consequently the propositions he considers, cannot be restricted by non-logical facts such as the non-existence of a particular. This principle stems from Leibniz. Philosophers who adopt it, for example Quine93 and A. J. Ayer94, do not allow that any particular is a constituent of a proposition and, with qualifications, regard all proper names as descriptions. It has been pointed out by Martin Shearn95 that Russell’s analysis of propositions concerning the existence of particulars sometimes yields implausible results. An example similar to one of Shearn’s would be the proposition that the god feared by the ancient Israelites did not exist. Russell’s analysis would be: it is not true that there was one and only one god feared by the Israelites. Yet Russell very likely accepts, surely without selfcontradiction, both that the god feared by the ancient Israelites did not exist and that the ancient Israelites feared one and only one god. In fact many propositions concerning human attitudes and activities pose difficulties for the theory of descriptions. One which Russell mentions is the proposition that George IV asked whether Scott was the author of Waverley. Does this imply, as it 92 L.K., p. 41. W. V. O. Quine, From a Logical Point of View, p.2 94 A. J. Ayer, The Concept of a Person, 1963, p. 134. 95 M. Shearn, “Russell’s Analysis of Existence”, in Analysis vol. 11, 1950-51, p. 124ff. 93 71 would on the analysis we have been considering, that someone wrote Waverley? Russell deals with this difficulty by introducing another element into his analysis: the distinction between primary and secondary occurrence of denoting phrases.96 If the proposition is analysed as: only one person wrote Waverley and of a person who wrote Waverley George IV asked whether he was Scott, then the denoting phrase “the author of Waverley” has been treated as having a primary occurrence. If it is analysed as: George IV asked whether only one person wrote Waverley and Scott wrote Waverley, then the denoting phrase has been treated as having secondary occurrence. Quine97 has suggested a means of extending this distinction of Russell’s to other propositions which raise difficulties. An example is the proposition that Hudson tried to find the North West Passage, which would be true even if no North West Passage existed. Quine would analyse this proposition as: Hudson tried to bring it about that he knew where the North West Passage lay. The phrase “the North West Passage” can now be treated as having secondary occurrence. The theory of descriptions provides nearly all that Russell asked of it. It explains in what way we can think and speak of things which do not exist. It distinguishes between the proposition that the Prime Minister is speaking and the proposition that the leader of the party in power is speaking. It explains both these without implying that concepts can occur in propositions other than as terms. The only doubt arises over whether, according to the theory, propositions expressed with the help of denoting phrases do not have as constituents those entities which the denoting phrases denote. This doubt arises in the following way. It is not internal to the proposition that there was something which was both human and met by me, that there was something human, i.e. that there were any men. The proposition implies, of course, that there were men, but it would have existed whether or not there had been men, and could have been considered, believed or disbelieved. This is a point Russell often stresses. The same argument applies to the proposition that I met the man. However, the question whether Brown is a constituent 96 97 L.K., pp. 52-3. W. V. O. Quine, Word and Object, 1960, pp. 151-6. 72 of the proposition that there was something which was both human and met by me, is not the same as the question whether it is internal to that proposition that there are men. Brown might not have been a man, so that his existence might be necessary to that of the proposition although the existence of men is not. What, according to the theory of descriptions, are the constituents of the proposition that I met a man? Russell’s account98 of them suffers from complete circularity. It is founded upon the notion of a variable and that notion is inseparable from another, that of a propositional function. A propositional function, as Russell explains it, is an entity which is got by omitting a term from a proposition. It is symbolised by an expression in which the gap left when the name of the missing term is removed is filled by a letter such as x. For example, if we take the proposition that Brown is human and omit Brown we get the propositional function x is human. Again, if we take the proposition that Brown is both human and met by me and omit Brown we get the propositional function x is both human and met by me. Once he has introduced this notion Russell goes on to consider three properties which propositional functions may have – the property of being always true, the property of being sometimes true and the property of being never true. He says that the last two can be defined in terms of the first, but that he is going to treat the first as indefinable. He then explains the proposition that there is something which is both human and met by me as the proposition that the propositional function x is both human and met by me is sometimes true. This completes his account of the constituents of the proposition that I met a man. It seems that he intends that the subject of this proposition is a propositional function and the predicate is the property of being sometimes true. Although Russell says at the beginning of “On Denoting” that he intends to take the notion of being always true as “ultimate and indefinable” he does, of course, expect us to understand what he means by it. In a later work99 he explains that to say that a propositional function is always true is to say that, 98 99 L.K., pp. 42-3. I.M.P., p. 158 73 whatever entity we take to complete the propositional function, the result is always a true proposition. Similarly, to say that a propositional function is sometimes true is to say that some one of the entities which might be taken to complete the propositional function would yield a true proposition. But these notions were introduced for the very purpose of giving an analysis of propositions such as that something is human or that everything is human which would make it clear what their constituents were. Since the analysis proposed is itself one of these propositions it leaves us no clearer about their constituents. There is, however, another explanation of the notions of being sometimes true and being always true which is not circular and which Russell may have intended. It might be held that the propositional function x is human is always true if, and only if, the conjunction of all the propositions which can be obtained by completing the propositional function is true. Since the gap symbolised by x might be filled by one of the men but might equally be filled by any other entity this conjunction will be very long, perhaps infinitely long. Similarly, the propositional function x is human will sometimes be true if, and only if, the disjunction of all these propositions is true. This is suggested by the following passage: It is to be observed that “all S is P” does not apply only to those terms that actually are S’s; it says something equally about terms which are not S’s…. In order to understand “all S is P”, it is not necessary to be able to enumerate what terms are S’s; provided we know what is meant by being an S and what by being a P, we can understand completely what is actually affirmed by “all S is P”, however little we may actually know of actual instances of either. This shows that it is not merely the actual terms that are S’s that are relevant in the statement “all S is P”, but all the terms concerning which the supposition that they are S’s is significant.100 This suggests that whereas on his earlier view the proposition that I met a man was taken to be equivalent to a disjunction of propositions involving all men, on his later view it is taken to be equivalent to a disjunction of rather different propositions 100 I.M.P., pp. 161-2. 74 involving all entities. The original disjunction was that either I met Brown, or I met Jones, or I met Robinson, or… The revised disjunction is that either Brown is human and I met Brown, or Fido is human and I met Fido, or Excalibur is human and I met Excalibur, or…. This difficulty concerns only one of the consequences Russell drew from the theory of descriptions but it is an important one, for he relied on it in the explanation of how it was possible for a person to understand propositions concerning entities which did exist but with which he had no acquaintance. The theory cannot explain this unless it has the consequence that, even when a denoting phrase does denote an entity, that entity is not a constituent of the proposition expressed with the help of the phrase. However, in considering Russell’s views concerning a person’s knowledge of the world beyond his own sensations – in which this consequence plays a central part – I shall make no more mention of the difficulty. 75 6 The External World The theory of descriptions enabled Russell to avoid the implausible consequences of his view that when we think, we are directly related to entities which are independent of us and our minds. It did this at the price of re-introducing a distinction between thought and knowledge which Bradley had made much use of: that between appearance and reality. In the theory of descriptions this took the particular form of a distinction between the apparent constituents of a proposition and its actual constituents. These are confused, Russell held, because of a confusion between the subject of a sentence and the subject of the proposition expressed by that sentence. The phrase “the golden mountain” is the grammatical subject of the sentence “The golden mountain does not exist”, but the proposition expressed by that sentence does not have the golden mountain as its subject, for there is no such mountain. In misleading us about the constituents of our propositions, grammar misleads us about their logical form. We are misled by grammar into attributing to the proposition expressed by the sentence “The golden mountain does not exist” the subject-predicate rather than the existential form. The idea that the grammar of a language can mislead us about the logical form of the propositions which it enables us to express, suggests that a language might be designed with a perfect grammar which would not mislead us. Russell regarded the symbolic language of Principia Mathematica as a first step towards such a perfect language. He never succeeded in improving on the unsatisfactory account of logical form which he gave in The Principles of Mathematics, and this difficulty of explaining what it is that grammar misleads us about led later 76 philosophers, inspired by the logical insights of the Principia, to seek a different account of the inadequacies of natural languages. Rudolf Carnap101 identified grammatical form with logical form and held that the fault in the grammar of a natural language lay in its ambiguities and inconsistencies rather than in its failure to express the true logical form of propositions. Tarski102 and Quine103 adopted a similar approach. To identify the actual constituents of the proposition expressed by a sentence Russell employs his principle that …in every proposition that we can apprehend… all the constituents are really entities with which we have immediate acquaintance.104 For example, if we can understand the proposition expressed by the sentence “Hadrian visited Britain”, that proposition cannot be that only one person became Emperor of Rome in A.D. 117 and someone both became Emperor of Rome in A.D. 117 and visited Britain, for we no more have immediate acquaintance with ancient Rome than with Hadrian. The proposition expressed might perhaps be that only one person built Hadrian’s Wall and someone both built Hadrian’s Wall and visited Britain, if Hadrian’s Wall is a thing which we can, at this time, have immediate acquaintance with. This illustrates one way of interpreting a sentence which seems to express a proposition having constituents with which we are not acquainted: the actual constituents include entities which the apparent constituents are implied to have brought into being. There are at least two other ways in which such sentences may be interpreted. The actual constituents of the proposition expressed may be taken to be qualities which, the proposition is held to imply, are possessed by, and only by, the apparent constituents. For example, the sentence “Pegasus rose into the air” might be interpreted as expressing the proposition that only one thing ever was a winged horse and that at least one thing both was a winged horse and rose into the air. In order to 101 R. Carnap, The Logical Syntax of Language, 1937. A. Tarski, Logic, Semantics and Metamathematics, 1956. 103 W. V. O. Quine, Word and Object. 104 L.K., p. 56 102 77 understand this proposition we need acquaintance with the qualities of being a horse and having wings, but not with Pegasus. Again, the actual constituents of the proposition expressed by a sentence might be taken to include certain universals with which we have acquaintance and with which the apparent constituents are implied to be uniquely related. For example, the sentence “Newton investigated light” might be taken to express the proposition that only one person first distinguished the properties of mass and weight and that at least one person both did this and investigated light. If we knew one of these propositions to be true we would know that there existed an entity of a certain kind or an entity related to the constituents of the proposition in a particular way. We would know that there once existed someone who had Hadrian’s Wall built, that there once existed a winged horse, and that there once existed someone who first distinguished the properties of mass and weight. Russell says that if we had this knowledge we would have “knowledge by description” of these three entities. He contrasts the manner in which our knowledge that only one person had Hadrian’s Wall built and someone both had Hadrian’s Wall built and visited Britain is knowledge of the man who had Hadrian’s Wall built, with the manner in which Hadrian’s knowledge that he himself had the Wall built is knowledge of the man who had Hadrian’s Wall built. The former knowledge is knowledge of the man who had the Wall built because it includes the knowledge that one and only one man had the Wall built; the latter knowledge is knowledge of the man who had the Wall built because that man is a constituent of the proposition which is known to be true.105 This is the distinction which Russell intended by the phrases “knowledge by description” and “knowledge by acquaintance”. It is a distinction between two ways in which our knowledge can be of an actual entity. The former is made possible by our knowing that one and only one entity satisfies a certain description, the latter is made possible by our having acquaintance with the entity itself. Unfortunately some of the things Russell says when he is discussing this topic in Problems of 105 P.P., pp. 54-7. 78 Philosophy suggest that the contrast he has in mind lies between acquaintance as one sort of knowledge and description as another sort. Knowledge of things, when it is of the kind we call knowledge by acquaintance, is essentially similar than any knowledge of truths…. Knowledge of things by description, on the contrary, always involves… some knowledge of truths as its source and ground.106 A little later he says, speaking of a particular shade of colour which he is seeing: …so far as concerns knowledge of the colour itself, as opposed to any knowledge of truths about it, I know the colour perfectly and completely when I see it, and no further knowledge of it itself is even theoretically possible.107 The first passage means, I think, that that knowledge which is knowledge of a thing because we have acquaintance with it is not knowledge of that thing because of anything we know to be true, while that knowledge of a thing which Russell calls knowledge by description is knowledge of that thing because of something we know to be true. However, the second passage does explicitly state that when a person has acquaintance with a thing, he knows that thing perfectly and completely. This view is irrelevant to the distinction between knowledge by description and knowledge by acquaintance which Russell goes on to make, but criticisms of the view have sometimes been regarded as criticisms of the distinction. G. E. Moore criticises Russell’s use of the phrase “knowledge by acquaintance” on the grounds that acquaintance is not knowledge at all, but direct perception.108 He is right about acquaintance but the criticism is beside the point: knowledge by acquaintance of an entity is knowledge which is of it because we have acquaintance with it, not knowledge of it which is acquaintance with it. 106 P.P., p. 46. P.P., p. 47. 108 G. E. Moore, Some Main Problems of Philosophy, 1953, p. 77n. 107 79 Acquaintance with an entity does not prevent us, Russell held, from having knowledge by description of it. He illustrated this by the sentence “The candidate who gets the most votes will be elected”. Someone who utters this sentence may be acquainted with all the candidates, yet the proposition he intends to express is unlikely to be one which has the candidate who will get the most votes as subject. The proposition which he is most likely to have intended implies that anyone, if he gets most votes, will be elected. However, this example throws doubt on Russell’s notion of knowledge of an entity by description, for it hardly seems that someone who knows that anyone, if he gets most votes, will be elected, has knowledge of the candidate who will get the most votes. On the other hand, if the seat was a safe one, someone might employ the sentence “The candidate who will get the most votes is a scoundrel” to express something he knows to be true, and then, it seems, his knowledge would be knowledge of the candidate who will get most votes. However, the proposition he intends is one which does have the candidate who will get the most votes as its subject, not one which implies that anyone, if it is true that he will get the most votes, is a scoundrel. This suggests that the plausibility of Russell’s view that there is such a thing as knowledge of an entity by description rests on sentences which are ambiguous. In one interpretation they express propositions of such a character that anyone who knows them to be true knows that there is one and only one entity of a certain kind. In the other interpretation they express propositions of such a character that anyone who knows them to be true has knowledge which is knowledge of a certain entity. The existence of such ambiguities can be shown by another example. When we speak of a painting as being Turner’s we mean that it was painted by Turner, so by the sentence “Turner’s paintings were painted by Turner” we may mean that Turner painted some paintings and that anything, if it was painted by Turner, was painted by Turner. In fact we might mean, besides the fact that Turner painted some paintings, nothing more than a tautology. However, we might wish to express the fact that the paintings which were painted by Turner might have been painted by someone else, and, if we knew of nothing in common between Turner’s paintings except that they 80 were all painted by Turner, we might express this fact by the sentence “It might not have been the case that Turner’s paintings were painted by Turner”. Since we would, in that case, be using this sentence to express a fact, and not merely the fact that Turner might have painted nothing, it cannot be that the proposition we would express by the words “Turner’s paintings were painted by Turner” is, besides the implication that Turner painted some paintings, a tautology. This latter sentence is therefore ambiguous. In its first meaning it expresses knowledge which, according to Russell, is knowledge of Turner’s paintings (by description) and the knowledge it expresses is that they were painted by Turner. However, it cannot in fact embody this knowledge, for nothing about any paintings in particular is entailed by the fact that Turner painted some paintings. In its second meaning the sentence expresses a proposition which embodies knowledge of certain paintings – the knowledge that they were painted by Turner – but it is not a conjunction of an existential statement and a tautology. It seems that it is a proposition which has Turner’s paintings as subject. Only the confusion of these two propositions gives plausibility to Russell’s view that if our knowledge includes the fact that there is one and only one entity, or group of entities, of a certain kind, then our knowledge is knowledge of that entity. Russell often writes as if, although we can have no acquaintance with people or things which ceased to exist before we were born, or will come into existence only after our death, yet we do have acquaintance with people and things when we see or touch them, and do have acquaintance with ourselves. He takes this position only for the sake of simplicity of exposition. In reality he believed that we can have acquaintance with particular things only if we can perceive them directly, and he did not believe that we have direct perception of physical objects, of other people, or even of ourselves. …the real table, if there is one, is not the same as what we immediately experience by sight or touch or hearing. The real table, if there is one, is not immediately known to us at all, but must be an inference from what is immediately known.109 109 P.P., p. 11. 81 If we see a thing, as opposed to seeing something which that thing has brought into being, we have immediate experience, or direct perception, of that thing. If we see that a thing has a certain property, as opposed to inferring that fact from another which we see to hold, then we have immediate knowledge of that fact. Russell held both that we have no direct perception of physical objects and that we have no immediate knowledge of facts concerning physical objects. The reasons which led him to this view have a long history in philosophy. He sets them out in the first chapter of Problems of Philosophy. Three arguments can be distinguished. A table appears to have very different colours in different lights. Therefore there is no colour which it appears to be, and hence no colour which we see it to be.110 The colour a table appears to have does not depend only upon the colour it has. It depends upon many other factors such as the incident light and the eyesight of the observer. Therefore we do not see what colour the table has. Russell concludes that we only see what colour it seems to have in a certain light to an observer of a certain kind.111 The shape a table appears to be changes as we shift our position, even if the shape it is remains unchanged. Therefore what we see from one position has one shape, what we see from another, has another. Hence we do not see the table itself. Russell concludes that we see various appearances of the table.112 Since Russell wrote, these arguments have received considerable attention from both philosophers and psychologists. They cannot be discussed very fully here. The work of the Gestalt psychologists such as Wolfgang Köhler,113 has shown that the premise of the first argument needs qualification. There is also considerable doubt whether the conclusion follows from the premise. After a person has looked at a table from various angles there is often a definite colour and shape which it appears to him to have. The premise of the second argument is undoubtedly correct, but the different factors upon which the appearance of the table depends do not all have the same status. For example, 110 P.P., pp. 8-9. P.P., pp. 9-10. 112 P.P., pp. 10-11. 113 W. Köhler, The Gestalt Psychology, 1947. 111 82 the fact that it depends upon the incident light perhaps supports the conclusion that when we look at an object in different lights, we see the reaction of the object to light of different kinds, and not one thing – the colour of the object. On the other hand, the fact that the appearance of the object depends upon the condition of the observer shows that some observers cannot see what colour an object is, but not that no observer can see this. Russell’s third argument is perhaps the strongest, but certain doubts arise. The inference is invalid unless the premise that a table appears to have one shape from one angle and another from another implies that what we see from one angle does not have the same shape as what we see from another. Yet the fact that what a person saw on one occasion did not seem to have the same shape as what he saw on another is not a very strong argument for the conclusion that what he saw on one occasion had a different shape from what he saw on the other. There is, however, some plausibility in Russell’s contention that when we look at the same thing on two occasions we may see colours and shapes on one of the occasions, which we do not see on the other. Whatever the strength of these arguments, they led Russell to the conclusion that we have immediate perception of colours, shapes, sounds, smells and textures, but not of tables and chairs or the bodies of other people. The colours are coloured patches – non-physical things which are coloured – rather than the colours red, blue, etc. Russell held that a colour, such as red, is a universal. He believed that we were acquainted with that universal, but acquaintance with the universal was a different thing from acquaintance with the colours we see when we look at a physical object. In Problems of Philosophy, Russell argued in these ways for the view that our knowledge of the expressions on the faces of other people, of the marks they inscribe on paper and the vibrations they impress on the air, rests upon inference. He took it for granted that a further inference was involved in our knowledge of their thoughts and feelings. He believed that we have acquaintance with our own thoughts and feelings, and direct knowledge of facts about them, but he was doubtful whether we have acquaintance with the self whose thoughts and feelings they are. He says, echoing Hume, that when we look for ourselves we find nothing but our thoughts and feelings. He was inclined 83 nevertheless to accept that we do have acquaintance with ourselves, on the grounds that we often know that we have a certain feeling and that we could not even understand a proposition to that effect without acquaintance with ourselves.114 However, he combined this view with the belief that we do not know directly that we have a continuing self with a past and a future. Descartes went beyond what he knew when he asserted that he himself existed, for all we know at any time is that we have a momentary self experiencing the feelings of the moment.115 Russell found the explanation of how we might have knowledge concerning physical objects and the feelings of other people in the possibility of knowledge by description. He suggested propositions such that anyone knowing them to be true would have knowledge concerning physical objects but which could be understood without acquaintance with physical objects, so that lack of acquaintance with the objects was no bar to knowing the propositions to be true. However, other difficulties arose about our knowledge of these propositions. We know, concerning a table, that it has a certain property if we know that there exists only one thing which is causing a certain collection of colours and sounds with which we are acquainted and that nothing causing those colours and sounds lacks the property. The problem remained of how we can know that a collection of colours and sounds has one cause, or what properties that cause has, if we cannot perceive it directly and cannot perceive directly any facts about it. This problem presented difficulties because if we do not perceive physical objects our knowledge of them must be obtained by inference from our knowledge of the colours and sounds we do perceive. Now there is no logically valid inference from the occurrence of certain sounds and colours to the conclusion that they all have one cause, or to the conclusion that they all have a cause of a certain kind. Therefore the proposition which, according to this view of Russell’s, we must know, if we are to have knowledge concerning physical objects and their properties, are propositions which we can never infer with logical validity from the data of perception. 114 115 P.P., pp. 50-1. P.P., p. 19. 84 In Problems of Philosophy116, Russell met this difficulty by arguing that although it is logically possible that our sense-data are not produced by the presence of single physical objects having a definite colour and shape, yet the fact that a much simpler view of the world is obtained by supposing that they are so produced is an adequate reason for supposing that they are. He found further support for this view in the fact that we instinctively believe we see and touch physical objects. He thought that this instinctive belief could not stand up to the arguments he had brought against it and he argued that the trust we instinctively have in it must be transferred to that view which can stand up to criticism and which is closest to the original. This he held to be the view that our sense-data are produced by the presence of physical objects. He defined an instinctive belief as one which “we find in ourselves as soon as we begin to reflect”. His belief that there are such things probably derives from Descartes. He argued that philosophy cannot find reasons against our whole body of instinctive beliefs, but can only find, in some of our instinctive beliefs, reasons against others. Therefore a consistent system of instinctive beliefs is worthy of acceptance. This argument may be questioned at several points. First, why should not philosophy discover propositions which we do not find ourselves to believe when we begin to reflect but to which, when they are pointed out to us, we at once transfer our allegiance? A man must base his proofs on what he believes to be true, but, as Stuart Hampshire has argued117, when he is constructing a proof he is not restricted to those premises which he believes to be true when he begins the task, for his beliefs may change as he considers the problem. Indeed this is what, in his own opinion, happened to Russell when he was led to abandon the view that we see physical objects. Second, even if he could find no reason against such a system it would not follow that there was no reason against it. The explanation of his being able to find no reason against it lies, for Russell, in his inability to stray far from his instinctive beliefs, but that inability does not have the consequence that no beliefs besides those are worthy of acceptance. 116 117 P.P., p. 22. Stuart Hampshire, Freedom and the Individual, 1965, p. 97. 85 Russell’s argument here is a less plausible version of Moore’s argument against Hume’s scepticism which I quoted in Chapter 4. Moore claimed that it was impossible to prove that we cannot know any external facts on the grounds that it would always be as easy to deny the argument as to accept its conclusion. It is doubtful whether Moore’s claim is justified, for how can he be sure that it will always be at least as easy without having considered all the arguments which might be brought? However, Russell’s argument is worse, for he claims not merely that it is as easy to take the sceptical as the non-sceptical side, but that it is impossible to take the sceptical side. Later, in “Four Forms of Scepticism”,118 Moore used a less general and therefore more acceptable version of this argument against the sceptical views which, as we shall see, Russell himself had come to hold. Russell held that these arguments from simplicity and from instinct show that we had good reason for the belief that some collections of colours and sounds which we do directly perceive are caused by a single thing which we do not. Yet we shall be able to know little concerning a thing we cannot perceive directly, such as a table, unless we can tell not only that some collection of colours and sounds has a cause but that whatever is its cause has certain properties, such as a definite shape, colour and texture. Now among the arguments which convinced Russell that we do not perceive directly that a table has such properties, was one which convinced him that we have no reason to believe that it has them at all.119 This was the argument that the colour a table seems to have depends upon many factors besides the properties of the table itself, such as the character of the light falling on it, the colour of its surroundings or the medium lying between it and our eyes. He was also impressed by the scientific theories which explained light and sound in terms of quite other properties. He concluded that science provides convincing reasons for doubting whether physical objects have any such properties as colour, pitch and warmth. This conclusion is undoubtedly true, but he goes on to describe in much too extreme terms the contemporary scientific picture of nature. 118 G. E. Moore, “Four Forms of Scepticism”, Philosophical Papers, 1959, pp. 196-226. 119 P.P., pp. 34-5. 86 Physical science, more or less unconsciously, has drifted into the view that all natural phenomena ought to be reduced to motions. Light and heat and sound are all due to wave-motions, which travel from the body emitting them to the person who sees light or feels heat or hears sound.120 He is here assuming the elastic solid theory of the propagation of light rather than the electromagnetic theory which had by that time replaced it. Sound is transmitted in air because a to-and-fro movement of air particles communicates itself to neighbouring particles, so that a wave of particle movement travels through the air. Thus sound can fairly be said to be reduced to the motion of particles. Light is transmitted because a variation in the strength of the electrical and the magnetic fields at one point in space is communicated to neighbouring points, so that a wave of electrical and magnetic field variation passes through space. Light is not reduced to motions. This mistake, which might be regarded as no more than a slip if it did not play a central part in the view of our knowledge of the properties of physical objects which Russell was putting forward, does not affect the validity of his contention that science denies physical objects such as colour, pitch and warmth. To conclude from science that we have no knowledge of the properties of physical objects would be flagrantly circular. What Russell did was to admit that we could have knowledge of the relations of physical objects in physical space and time. This knowledge he thought sufficient for knowledge of the laws of physical science – hence the importance of the view that science reduces all natural phenomena to motion, which can be defined in terms of space and time. The laws of physical science known in this way had the consequence that physical objects do not have all the properties they are commonly held to possess. The fact that science does not reduce all phenomena to motion means that there are considerable parts of science which Russell cannot accept that we know to be true unless he accepts that we can know more about physical objects than their relations in space and time. He might have invoked considerations of simplicity to justify our beliefs in this part of science, but he did not do so. This 120 P.P., pp. 22-8. 87 may have been because he had in mind another difficulty which faces his explanation, a problem which he mentions but does not discuss at any length. He suggested, as we have seen, that it is possible for us to know concerning a physical object that it has a certain property, although we cannot perceive that object directly, because it is possible for us to know that a collection of colours and sounds has a single cause and that whatever is their cause possesses that property. This proposition can be understood without acquaintance with the physical object. The further difficulty is that it cannot be understood without acquaintance with the property in question. Since Russell believed that we were not acquainted with any properties of, or relations between, physical objects, he was committed to the view that we cannot understand this proposition or know it to be true. Although he did not believe that we were acquainted with the spatial properties of physical objects, such as shape, or with the spatial relations between them, such as distance, he thought that the relative positions of objects in physical space might correspond with those of colours in visual space.121 He thought that a similar correspondence would exist between the arrangement of colours in visual space and the arrangement of touch-sensations in tactile space which arise from seeing an object and exploring that same object by touch. We can know all those things about physical space which a man born blind might know through other people about the space of sight…122 The correspondence Russell was thinking of might also be illustrated by that between the variations in pressure of the steam in the boiler and the movement of the needle of its pressure gauge. When we watch the movement of the needle we perceive a variation in its position which will, if the gauge is accurate, be the very same as the variation in the pressure of the boiler. Although pressure is a very different property from position, a pressure and a position may vary in the very same way, and an understanding of the variation of the one provides understanding of the other. It seems likely that Russell held that our acquaintance with the 121 122 P.P., pp. 30-1. P.P., p. 32 88 arrangement of colours in our visual field was acquaintance with arrangements in which physical objects might stand, and that it was on this acquaintance that he believed our understanding of the properties science ascribes to physical objects to be based. The difference Russell found between our understanding of the spatial and temporal properties and relations of physical objects and our understanding of their other properties and relations would arise from his belief that when we are acquainted with an arrangement of colours in visual space we are acquainted with an arrangement in which physical objects might stand, whereas when we are acquainted with the variation in position of a gauge needle we are acquainted, not with properties and relations of physical objects, but with relations which may hold between those properties and relations. However, this difference is an illusion, as Russell comes to admit later in his discussion. Just as a relation between pressures may be the same as a relation between needle movements, so a relation between physical distances may be the same as a relation between visual distances. Russell has not shown that a relation between physical objects could be the same as a relation between colours. He has explained how we might come to grasp relationships in which relations between physical objects, such as distance, might stand, but not how we might come to grasp those relations themselves. Thus we come to know much more about the relations of distances in physical space than about the distances themselves.…123 Russell’s explanation of how we can grasp the properties which science ascribes to physical objects does not, therefore, depend on the reducibility of all properties to motions, since it explains how we can understand relations between any properties whatever. But this difficulty is replaced by another, for it has become clear that he has failed to explain how we can have any understanding of the properties themselves. The correspondence upon which Russell relies in explaining our understanding of these properties is the very same 123 P.P., pp. 31-2. 89 as that Wittgenstein employs in his explanation of how a sentence can express a possibility. To the configuration of the simple signs in the propositional sign corresponds the configuration of the objects in the state of affairs.124 Wittgenstein discusses such correspondences in much more detail than Russell, but it seems likely that Russell’s use of such correspondences to explain the relation between our sense-data and the physical world suggested to Wittgenstein that they might be used to explain the relation between language and the world. Russell makes one assertion125 which suggests another explanation of how we can understand propositions ascribing properties to physical objects. This is the assertion that we may have knowledge by description of universals as well as particulars. He does not develop this suggestion at all, but it would fit the general attitude of Problems of Philosophy better than an attempt to show that we are acquainted, if not with properties and relations between physical objects, at least with relations between those properties and relations. That general attitude is that there are facts which we cannot perceive directly to hold and which concern things with which we are not acquainted. The suggestion is that just as it might be held that we have knowledge concerning the property which steam has of being at a certain pressure by knowing that there is a single cause of the gauge needle, so we might have knowledge of the shape of the table by knowing that there is a single cause of the position of the gauge needle, so we might have knowledge of the shape of a table by knowing that there is a single cause of the various shapes of some of our sensedata. This is an important suggestion, but it faces the difficulty that to speak either of a physical object or of a property of a physical object as causing our sense-data is artificial. What causes our sense-data, if they have causes, must be some fact, perhaps the fact that a physical object has a certain property. If knowledge of a proposition to the effect that a collection of our sense-data has a single cause is knowledge concerning that cause, then it is knowledge concerning a fact. We know that there is a fact which 124 125 L. Wittgenstein, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, pp. 47-9. P.P., p. 101. 90 is a cause of our sense-data but we do not know which physical object it concerns, nor understand the property ascribed to it. It hardly seems that this account shows how we can have knowledge by description of the properties of physical objects. The explanation which knowledge by description was intended to provide of how we can have knowledge concerning particulars, properties and relations with which we have no acquaintance, is not consistently developed in Problems of Philosophy. In later works it is abandoned altogether, and Russell’s view of scientific knowledge and common sense no longer invoked knowledge of things by description, and hence no longer had the theory of descriptions as its basis. The change arose from his coming to take a sceptical attitude towards beliefs which do not follow with logical validity from any facts we perceive to be true. The view he arrived at did not dispense with such beliefs altogether, but minimised their importance. Whereas before, as we have seen, he was prepared to accept that we could know to be true propositions to the effect that a collection of our sense data had a single physical object as cause; in Our Knowledge of the External World he says there is no good reason to believe such propositions and refers to beliefs in them as a priori and unwarranted.126 We saw that if we are to have knowledge by description of physical objects with which we cannot be acquainted, we must be able to know the truth of propositions to the effect that our sense-data have causes. Scepticism about the possibility of such knowledge led Russell to abandon the view that we had any knowledge concerning things with which we cannot be acquainted. Indeed it led him to abandon the view that we had any knowledge concerning objects with which we might have been acquainted but as a matter of fact were not. For example, he speaks in Our Knowledge of the External World of the various perspectives which make up the appearance of the world to a single observer. These he calls “actual” perspectives, but says that we conceive of “ideal” perspectives which are appearances that the world would have had to an observer who might have been, but was not, stationed at a particular place at a particular time. Of these he writes: 126 O.K.E.W., pp. 110-12. 91 It is open to us to believe that the ideal elements exist, and there can be no reason for disbelieving this; but unless in virtue of some a priori law we cannot know it, for empirical knowledge is confined to what we actually observe.127 He still accepted that the theory of descriptions could show us a proposition we could understand by which we could replace a proposition we seemed to understand, but the replacement it offered was one which he no longer thought we had any reason to believe to be true. There was no way out except to take the proposition we knew and understood to be concerned only with objects of our acquaintance and to regard a physical object as a series of sense-data. Our belief that certain propositions concern physical objects is a convenient fiction, concealing the fact that they concern nothing but our sense-data. This view is a form of phenomenalism. Russell summed it up in his version of Ockham’s razor: Wherever possible, logical constructions are to be substituted for inferred entities.128 It differs from other forms of phenomenalism in one very important respect. Russell did not regard sense-data – the colours, shapes and sounds of immediate acquaintance – as mind-dependent, or mental. Although he thought we had no reason to believe that any existed when we were not perceiving them, he did not believe that it was logically impossible that they should exist unperceived. It was impossible for Russell to find an interpretation of scientific knowledge according to which it had no implications which are not actually perceived by somebody to be true. He asserts that physics has implications concerning how things would appear at times when they are not appearing to anyone.129 He thinks, however, that these implications should be regarded as hypotheticals concerning the sense-data someone would have had if he had had certain other sense-data, rather 127 O.K.E.W., p. 117. Mysticism and Logic, p. 155. 129 O.K.E.W., p. 116. 128 92 than as existential propositions implying the existence of sensedata which no one experienced. These propositions, whether hypothetical or existential, have not been perceived to be true by anyone. It seems that Russell preferred to regard the implications as hypotheticals because he thought them verifiable, although not verified, but believed that an unperceived sense-datum could not have been perceived.130 In fact, the hypotheticals have no advantage in verifiability: that a sense-datum was unperceived does not imply that it could not have been perceived. Russell regarded minds too as constructions out of sense-data. He held that no person could perceive directly any entity which was his own mind and which was logically independent of his sense-data; still less could he perceive directly an entity which was the mind of another. Nor did he believe that anyone had any good reason to assume that there did exist a single entity which was the subject of his experiences, so that no one could have any knowledge of any mind by description. Therefore that knowledge which we think of as knowledge of our minds must be knowledge of series of sense-data. To speak of certain kinds of knowledge concerning sense-data as knowledge of minds is no more than a convenient fiction. Since the sense-data out of which both minds and physical objects were constructed were themselves neither mental or physical Russell called this doctrine neutral monism. It took different forms in later works. Indeed, in Human Knowledge he again argued, as in Problems of Philosophy, that science includes principles which we cannot perceive directly to be true and that in reaching our scientific beliefs we must assume the validity of inferences which are not logically valid. He attempted to formulate the minimum of assumptions which would enable scientists to arrive at those principles which they believe to be true.131 130 131 O.K.E.W., pp. 88-9, 116-17. Human Knowledge, Its Scope and Limits, Part VI, pp. 439-527. 93 7 Fact and Belief Russell’s sceptical attitude towards the claim that there exist causes of the colours, shapes and sounds which we perceive directly was accompanied by scepticism concerning entities of a different category, which had played a fundamental role in his logic. Two of the most important were propositions and classes. He had supposed these to be objects of acquaintance, so his rejection of them did not arise from doubts about the validity of inferences from directly perceived facts. Rather it sprang from difficulties and contradictions which their existence entailed. Not only were his reasons for scepticism different, but the scepticism itself was of a different kind. Whereas he had accepted that there might be causes of our sense-data, holding only that we had no reason to believe that there were any, he did not accept that the existence of propositions or of classes was even a possibility. However, just as his scepticism about the external world had left him the task of re-interpreting propositions which seemed to concern physical objects, so his rejection of propositions and classes left him the task of re-interpreting many kinds of proposition from logic and psychology. Unfortunately there is no space in this book to discuss, except very briefly, one of the most important parts of Russell’s philosophy, his definitions of the concepts of arithmetic132, his discovery of contradictions in the logic of classes, and in other branches of logic, to which those definitions led him133, and the theory of types – developed in the Principia Mathematica134 – by which he sought to free logic from these contradictions. Georg Cantor defined a cardinal number as a property of a class, a property which a class shared with all other classes whose 132 P.O.M., pp. 111-20. P.O.M., pp. 101-7. 134 P.M., pp. 37-65. 133 94 numbers could be paired off with its members. A cardinal number is the number of members in a class, an ordinal number the position of a member in a sequence. For example, on 1 January 1900, the Christian era was one thousand eight hundred and ninety-nine years old. This is a cardinal number since it is the number of years which had elapsed since the birth of Christ. But the year which began on that day was the one-thousand-ninehundredth year of the Christian era. This is an ordinal number, for it gives the position of that year in the sequence of years. Thus an age is a cardinal number, being the number of years for which something has been in existence, but a date is an ordinal number, giving the position of a year, or a day, in a sequence. This explains why Russell had time to finish The Principles of Mathematics before the end of the nineteenth century: the twentieth century did not begin until 1 January 1901. Russell showed how Cantor’s definition of a cardinal number could be used to define the concepts of arithmetic in terms of the concepts of logic and to prove the theorems of arithmetic from principles of logic. However, the supposition that classes must be recognised among the entities which make up the world led, Russell saw, to some paradoxical conclusions. Cantor had proved that any class with more than one member has more sub-classes than it has members. This is not surprising for finite classes. The class whose members are the first four letters of the alphabet has six two-member sub-classes – A and B, A and C, A and D, B and C, B and D, C and D. These are only some of its sub-classes. But Cantor proved that it also held for classes with an infinite number of members. This theorem, which is called Cantor’s Theorem, together with the assumption that classes are among the things which make up the world, has the consequence that there is no class which is the class of all existing things, for, whatever we take that class to be, there must be a larger class with members our class has not got. The difficulty this poses for Cantor’s and Russell’s definition of cardinal numbers is obvious. If numbers are properties of classes, and if there are some true propositions in which numbers are ascribed, then classes must exist. If classes exist, then surely all the things there are must make up a class. But Cantor’s Theorem proves that there is no 95 such class.135 Russell accepted that there were no such things as classes but preserved his definition of numbers by analysing propositions which seem to concern classes into propositions which do not have classes as constituents. Thus he regarded the definition of numbers as properties of classes as a stage on the road to a satisfactory definition. It is convenient to speak as if classes exist, just as it is convenient to speak as if physical objects exist, but the supposition that such entities exist is no more than a fiction and the propositions that seem to concern them can be identified with propositions into which they do not enter. He calls both classes and physical objects “logical fictions”136. Russell thought that the rejection of classes gave him a freedom he would not otherwise have had. If there were classes it could hardly be that there was not the class of all existing things, but if propositions which seem to concern classes are to be analysed as propositions into which classes do not enter, then the analysis can be done in such a way that certain propositions which seem to concern classes are declared not to exist at all. This was what Russell did. The analysis of class propositions provided by the theory of types allows no analyses for propositions which seem to concern what Russell calls “classes of mixed type”. These are, for example, classes having as members both entities which are not themselves classes and entities which are classes of such entities. This has the consequence that no analysis is provided for propositions which seem to concern classes which are members of themselves. Of course the success of this resolution of the paradox posed by Cantor’s Theorem depends upon whether Russell’s analysis of class propositions is one according to which it is plausible to contend that propositions concerning classes of mixed type can be given no interpretation at all. This is an investigation which we must forego here. Although there are propositions which seem to exist but which can be proved to be both true and not true, such as the proposition expressed by the sentence “The proposition expressed by this sentence is false”, Russell’s scepticism concerning propositions did not rest on such contradictions and had very 135 136 I.M.P., pp. 135-6. L.K., pp. 265-6, 271-2. 96 different grounds from his scepticism concerning classes. It sprang from his adoption, in opposition to Bradley, of the view that truth consists in correspondence with fact137. Bradley believed it to be impossible to arrive at a thought which could be wholly true, for he held that no thought could be entirely selfconsistent. Concentrating on this insuperable bar to making a true judgement, which he believed could be overcome to some degree but never altogether, he slipped from the view that the more a thought was self-consistent, the more truth it could have, to the view that the more a thought was self-consistent, the more truth it had. Russell and Moore regarded truth as a necessary, but not a sufficient, condition of truth. To obtain a sufficient condition, correspondence with fact must be added138. Now it is natural to speak of a judgement, or of a proposition, as corresponding with fact if there exists a fact to which it corresponds and as failing to correspond if there does not exist a fact to which it corresponds. In this way, Russell and Moore were led to identify the proposition that it is a fact that lions are carnivorous with the proposition that the fact that lions are carnivorous exists. They came to treat facts as entities which, if they were not facts, would not exist. Moore discusses this problem in Some Main Problems of Philosophy139. He sets out to refute the view that to hold a belief is to be related to an object of belief, or proposition. He argues that such an object of belief would have to be something which, if the belief were true, would be a fact140 and that there can be nothing of this sort. A true proposition cannot be a fact since, if the proposition were not true, the proposition would exist but the fact would not141. This argument rests on the assumption that if it is not a fact that lions are carnivorous, then the fact that lions are carnivorous does not exist. Consider a parallel and evidently invalid argument where the corresponding assumption is false. If Jones is the only man in his village with any skill with iron someone might argue: Jones cannot be the blacksmith, since if Jones had had no skill with iron 137 P.P., p. 123 P.P., pp. 121-3. 139 G. E. Moore, Some Main Problems of Philosophy, pp. 252-87. 140 G. E. Moore, Some Main Problems of Philosophy, p. 261. 141 G. E. Moore, Some Main Problems of Philosophy, p. 260. 138 97 Jones would have existed but the blacksmith would not. This premise is false: if Jones had had no skill with iron there would have been no blacksmith but the blacksmith would have existed. This is possible because the blacksmith could have existed without being the blacksmith; he might, for example, have been the shoemaker. Similarly, it might be argued against Moore’s premise that if the proposition that lions are carnivorous were not true, then the fact that lions are carnivorous would have existed but, of course, would not have been a fact. The correspondence theory of truth, by leading Russell and Moore to identify “It is a fact…” with “The fact that … exists”, led them to treat fact as a category, just as someone might treat physical object as a category. A property is a category if something which possesses it would not exist if it did not possess it. Russell says: “Time was when I thought there were propositions”142. What convinced him that there were no such things was the seemingly innocent observation that “you cannot say that you believe facts”143. In one interpretation this is obviously true. Since some beliefs are false, it cannot be that believing something implies believing something which is a fact. However, when Russell had believed in propositions he had not believed anything as silly as this. He had held that in belief a person believes something that, if true, is a fact. What he is denying by his seemingly innocent remark is that belief is ever a belief in fact. He denied this because, as we have seen, he had come to hold that something which was a fact would not have existed had it not been a fact. He had accepted propositions because he had held that relation in thought to them was at least relation to something which, if true, was a fact, and he now concluded that there were no such things. Therefore he took the next best thing and suggested that belief was a relation to parts which, if they make a whole, make a fact. In rejecting propositions Russell was rejecting entities which facts would be if they were not facts and which would be facts if they were true. He rejects them because he thinks that there is nothing facts would be if they were not facts. False 142 143 L.K., p. 223. L.K., p. 222. 98 propositions would, he now thought, be non-existent facts and hence non-existent. This explains why his reasons for supposing there are no such things as propositions are all reasons for supposing that there are no such things as false propositions. To suppose that in the actual world of nature there is a whole set of false propositions going about is to my mind monstrous. I cannot bring myself to suppose it. I cannot believe that they are there in the sense in which facts are there.144 It also explains why he treats the view that there are false propositions as no less absurd than Meinong’s view that there is such an object as the round square but it is not an actuality. To Meinong, of course, the view that there is such an object as the round square but it is not an actuality is no less sensible than the view that there is a proposition that lions are vegetarians but it is a false proposition. He made an identification which, in a way, was the opposite of that made by Moore and Russell. He identifies the proposition that the round square does not exist with the proposition that the round square is not an actuality. This leads him to treat actualities as entities which would exist even if they were not actual. He treated actualities as it is common to treat facts, while Russell and Moore treated facts as it is common to treat actualities. In the absence of propositions, Russell and Moore had to explain what it is that possesses the properties of being true and being false. The word “belief” may mean a proposition which someone believes, or it may mean someone’s belief in a proposition. When a belief is said to be false it is perhaps more natural to take the word in the former sense, but Russell had the idea of taking it in the latter. He suggested that when Othello believed that Desdemona loved Cassio it was not what he believed that was false, but rather his belief in it. His belief in the proposition was false because there was no fact to which it corresponded. According to this suggestion, it is not propositions but beliefs which are true and false. All that remained was to give an account, which did not invoke propositions of what it was for someone to believe something. 144 L.K., p. 223. 99 Russell accepted that facts had constituents and logical form just as propositions did. What is more he thought that had there been a fact that Desdemona loved Cassio that fact would have had just the constituents and logical form which he had formerly attributed to the proposition that Desdemona loved Cassio. These constituents would exist, of course, even if the fact did not, so he suggested that belief was a relation between a person and certain entities which, if the belief was true, were constituents of a fact. This suggestion preserved the essential feature of his realism – that thought is a relation to real entities – but sacrificed the view that it is a relation to something which, if true, would be a fact. A belief has real entities as constituents, just as it would have if it were a relation between a person and a proposition. There are certain puzzles made up of a number of pieces of wood which can be fitted together to form a single cube. If someone is busy trying to fit the pieces together he cannot be said to be related to the cube he is trying to make, since that does not exist. However, the person who is trying to do the puzzle is related to the separate pieces of wood. When Russell and Moore refused to accept that something which is a fact might have existed and not been a fact they were treating being a fact like being a physical object. When a physical object has been broken up it has ceased to exist, but its parts may still exist. They hoped to explain trying to do the puzzle as a relationship between a person and the pieces. Before considering this explanation, we must consider some other consequences of Russell’s rejection of propositions. Propositions had formerly had a place in Russell’s understanding of the principles of logic as well as in his views on belief and truth and falsehood. He had held that many principles of logic concern the implication of one proposition by another. Perhaps because it is less plausible to take beliefs (as distinct from what is believed) as the entities between which implications hold, Russell, in “The Philosophy of Logical Atomism”, took the principles of logic to concern implications between sentences. However, this view is difficult to square with his view that truth and falsehood belong to beliefs, for those entities which implications hold between must surely be the entities to which truth and falsehood belong. Russell admitted this inconsistency: 100 he says that in logic it is natural to treat sentences as the bearers of truth and falsehood, but that this is not appropriate in discussions of belief and knowledge.145 Evidently one of these attitudes must be considered as no more than a convenience. Presumably it is the view that implications hold between sentences. Russell found it convenient to alter his terminology and take the word “proposition” to mean “sentence in the indicative mood”. In this way he could retain many of the sentences in which he had expressed principles of logic, but these would now mean that some sentence implied another rather than that some object of thought implied another.146 However, he does not keep consistently to this new usage. When he declares that there are no such things as propositions he does not intend to say that there are no such things as sentences in the indicative mood. Whether it is beliefs or sentences which are to be true or false, truth and falsehood consist in correspondence with fact. Logical atomism is a doctrine which may form part of a correspondence theory of truth. It holds that much of the complexity of facts is only apparent: much complexity belongs to beliefs or sentences and not to facts. Logical atomism has two tasks. Both Russell’s theory and Wittgenstein’s147 succeed partially in the first, but neither can deal with the second. The first is that of showing how a complex belief may correspond, not to a complex fact, but in a complex way to facts. For example, both Russell and Wittgenstein held that there are no conjunctive facts. There is no fact that it is raining and it is snowing to correspond with someone’s belief that it is raining and it is snowing. Rather that belief is true if there exist both the fact that it is raining and the fact that it is snowing. If one or other of these two facts fails to exist, then the belief is false. Again, there are no disjunctive facts. The belief that either it is raining or it is snowing is true if the fact that it is raining exists, true if the fact that it is snowing exists, false if neither exists. A belief which corresponds in such a complex way as this was said to be a truth-function of the simpler beliefs that it is raining and it is snowing. Russell and Wittgenstein held that facts had one or other of a few simple 145 L.K., pp. 184-5. L.K., p. 185. 147 L. Wittgenstein, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, passim. 146 101 logical forms: the subject-predicate form and the various relational forms. Therefore they were forced to deny that there is a fact to the effect that if the Eiffel Tower were undermined it would fall down, since that fact has none of these forms. They recognised a belief that if the Eiffel Tower were undermined it would fall down but held that its truth depended solely on the existence or non-existence of the two facts – that the Eiffel Tower will be undermined and that the Eiffel Tower will fall down. Nor could they admit facts concerning beliefs, and they were hard put to it to present the truth of beliefs about beliefs as determined by facts which they did admit. The second task is that of giving an account of what it is for someone to hold a complex belief. Both Russell’s and Wittgenstein’s accounts of beliefs apply only to simple beliefs. It seems that complex belief should be explained in terms of simple belief, but neither Russell nor Wittgenstein attempts to do this. Instead they both fall back on stating what facts make them true and what facts make them false. This is either to accept propositions in Russell’s old sense, and explain complex beliefs by stating what proposition is believed to be true, or to identify a certain complex belief by stating that it is a belief which would be made true by certain facts, which does not tell us what it is to hold that belief. One might ask how, on Russell’s view of belief, it is possible to hold beliefs which are made true and false by these facts. The same problem arises for Wittgenstein’s explanation of thought as the construction of pictures. Although Russell does not appreciate this difficulty in “The Philosophy of Logical Atomism” he does do so in An Inquiry into Meaning and Truth. There he explains what belief-state of the speaker is expressed by uttering a sentence of what he calls the primary language, and goes on to ask what is expressed by a sentence in which two primary language sentences are joined by the word “or”. He is inclined to answer that such sentences express a state of hesitation.148 On this account, to believe either that it will rain or that it will snow is to hesitate between the two beliefs. The account, as Russell sees, is not entirely satisfactory. A person who holds such a belief may have no wish to decide whether it will rain 148 I.M.T., pp. 84-5, 210. 102 or to decide whether it will snow. He might be quite satisfied with his belief that one or other of them is true. Russell’s account is inadequate, but he did at least recognise the existence of the problem. The account of belief to which, as we have seen, Russell was led by his rejection of propositions is confronted by a serious difficulty. When Othello believed that Desdemona loved Cassio he was related, not to the proposition that Desdemona loved Cassio, but to Desdemona, to Cassio and to the relation loves. Now there are several propositions which have Desdemona, Cassio and the relation loves as constituents, so that the fact that Othello held some belief concerning these constituents does not determine what it was that he believed. He might have believed that Desdemona loved Cassio, that Cassio loved Desdemona, or that Cassio and Desdemona loved loving. Russell himself held that to specify a proposition it was necessary to specify not only the constituents but also the logical form and the manner in which the logical form relates the constituents. His account of belief ignores the latter two completely. He attempts to meet this difficulty with the suggestion that had Othello believed that Cassio loved Desdemona, he would have been related to the three constituents in a different way from that in which he actually was related to them in believing that Desdemona loved Cassio.149 However, in “The Philosophy of Logical Atomism”, he says that Wittgenstein has convinced him of the inadequacy of his account of belief and he seems to admit that his view cannot satisfactorily meet the difficulty we have been considering. On the analogy with the wooden puzzle, Russell’s account of belief would correspond to an account which identified trying to assemble the pieces into a cube as a relation between the person doing the puzzle and the pieces. The difficulty in finding such an account would be to find a relation between the person and the pieces, which would imply that he was trying to assemble them into a cube. Similarly, the difficulty of finding an adequate account of belief along the lines Russell suggests is that of finding a relation between a person and the constituents of a fact which implies that only a fact in which those constituents were related in a particular way by a particular 149 P.P., pp. 126-7. 103 logical form would constitute the truth of the person’s belief. It is not easy to see whether this can be done. Rightly or wrongly Russell concluded that this problem could not be solved and the attempt to find an account of belief which did not invoke propositions led him to abandon the realist view of thought which had characterised his philosophy for so long. According to the view of belief which he put forward in The Analysis of Mind and An Inquiry into Meaning and Truth, the fact that a person holds a certain belief no longer has as constituents either the proposition which he might be said to believe, the fact which would make his belief true, or the constituents of that fact. Holding a particular belief was identified with being in a particular mental state. In The Analysis of Mind,150 this state was characterised as one in which an image is present in the mind along with a belief-feeling, or feeling of assent. In An Inquiry into Meaning and Truth,151 it was characterised as one, perhaps a state of tension, upon which certain perceptions, if they occurred, would have a certain result, perhaps that of removing it. In coming to the former view, Russell was probably influenced by Wittgenstein’s theory that a person thinks by constructing pictures. In arriving at the latter he was certainly influenced by the behaviourist psychology. On these views of belief the constituents of the fact which would make the belief true are never constituents of the fact that a person holds a particular belief. Therefore, a person can hold a belief, even if he has no acquaintance with the entities which Russell would formerly have held to be constituents of the proposition he believed, and even if those entities do not exist. What the theory of descriptions explained no longer needs to be explained, so that the theory has become unnecessary and does not figure in these later works. The problems which led Russell to abandon his realist view of thought were in some ways artificial. His rejection of propositions arose from the identification of “It is a fact that…” with “The fact that … exists”, which has little in its favour. There is no more excuse for treating false propositions as non-existent facts – rather than 150 151 A.M., pp. 250-2. I.M.T., pp. 177-80. 104 treating facts as true propositions – than for Meinong’s treatment of imaginary things as beings – rather than as non-existent. But, however that may be, neither propositions nor facts have position in space and time, and someone with that vivid sense of reality which Russell held that every logician must have, might well reject both. 105 BIBLIOGRAPHY i. Books and Pamphlets German Social Democracy. London 1896. An Essay on the Foundations of Geometry. Cambridge 1897. A Critical Exposition of the Philosophy of Leibniz. Cambridge 1900; second edition, London 1937. The Principles of Mathematics. Cambridge 1903; second edition, London 1937. Principia Mathematica, vol. I, with A. N. Whitehead. Cambridge 1910. Philosophical Essays. London 1910. Principia Mathematica, vol. II, with A. N. Whitehead. Cambridge 1912. The Problems of Philosophy. London 1912; second edition, London 1946. Principia Mathematica, vol. II, with A. N. Whitehead. Cambridge 1913. Our Knowledge of the External Word. London 1914; third edition, London 1926. The Philosophy of Bergson. London 1914. War, the Offspring of Fear. London 1915. Principles of Social Reconstruction. London 1916. Justice in War-Time. London 1916. The Case of Ernest F. Everett. London 1916. Rex vs. Bertrand Russell. London 1916. Political Ideals. New York 1917. Mysticism and Logic. London 1917. Roads to Freedom. London 1918. Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy. London 1919. The Practice and Theory of Bolshevism. London 1920. The Analysis of Mind. London 1921. The Problems of China. London 1922. The Prospects of Industrial Civilization, with Dora Russell. London 1923. The ABC of Atoms. London 1923. Icarus or the Future of Science. London 1924. Bolshevism and the West. London 1924. 106 The ABC of Relativity. London 1925. What I Believe. London 1925. Why I am not a Christian. London 1927. The Analysis of Matter. London 1927. An Outline of Philosophy. London 1927. Selected Essays of Bertrand Russell. New York 1927. Sceptical Essays. London 1928. Marriage and Morals. Lonson 1929. The Conquest of Happiness. London 1930. Has Religion Made Useful Contributions to Civilization? London 1930. The Scientific Outlook. New York 1931. Education and the Social Order. London 1932. Freedom and Organization 1814-1914. London 1934. In Praise of Idleness. New York 1935. Which Way to Peace? London 1936. Determinism and Physics. Newcastle-upon-Tyne 1936. The Amberley Papers, with Patricia Russell. London 1937. Power: a New Social Analysis. New York 1938 An Inquiry into Meaning and Truth. London 1940. Let the People Think. London 1941. A History of Western Philosophy. London 1945. Human Knowledge: its Scope and Limits. London 1948. Authority and the Individual. London 1949. Unpopular Essays. London 1950. The Impact of Science on Society. Columbia 1951. New Hopes for a Changing World. London 1951. Satan in the Suburbs. London 1953. Nightmares of Eminent Persons. London 1954. Human Society in Ethics and Politics. London 1954. Logic and Knowledge. London 1956. Pertraits from Memory. London 1956. Common Sense and Nuclear Warfare. London 1959. My Philosophical Development. London 1959. The Wisdom of the West. London 1959. Fact and Fiction. London 1961. Has Man a Future? London 1961. Unarmed Victory. London 1963. 107 Political Ideals. London 1963. War Crimes in Vietnam. London 1967. Autobiography 1872-1914. London 1967. Autobiography 1914-1944. London 1968. Autibiography 1944-1968. London 1969. ii. Articles. NOTE Throughout his life Russell has written a great many aritcles on a wide variety of subjects. This Bibliography includes only articles on philosophy and of those, with very few exceptions, does not include ones re-published in books already listed. “The A Priori in Geometry”, in Proc. Aristotelian Soc. 1896. “The Logic of Geometry”, in Mind 1896. “On the Relations of Number and Quantity”, in Mind 1896. “Les Axiomes Propres à Euclide sont-ils Empiriques?”, in Rev. de Métaphysique et de Morale 1898. “Sur les Axiomes de la Géométrie”, in Rev. de Métaphysique et de Morale 1899. “L’Idée d’Ordre et la Position Absolute dans l’Espace et les Temps”, in Congrès int. de philosophie, logique et histoires des sciences 1901. “On the Nature of Order”, in Mind 1901. “Is Position in Time and Space Absolute or Relative?”, in Mind 1901. “Sur la Logique des Relations avec des Applications à la Théorié des Séries”, in Rev. de Mathématique 1902. “On some Difficulties in the Theory of Transfinite Numbers and Order Types”, in Proc. London Math. Soc. 1906. “The Theory of Implication”, in Amer. Journal of Mathematics 1906. “Les Paradoxes de la Logique”, in Rev. de Métaphysique et de Morale 1906. “On the Nature of Truth”, in Proc. Aristotelian Soc. 1906-7. “‘If’ and ‘Imply’”, in Mind 1908. “The Philosophy of William James”, in Living Age 1910. “Some Explanations in Reply to Mr Bradley”, in Mind 1910. 108 “La Théorie de Types Logiques”, in Rev. de Métaphysique et de Morale 1910. “The Basis of Realism”, in J. of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Method 1911. “The Philosophical Importance of Mathematical Logic”, in Monist 1911. “Definitions and Methodological Principles in Theory of Knowledge”, in Monist 1914. “Sensation and Imagination” in Monist 1915. “On the Experience of Time”, in Monist 1915. “Philosophy of Logical Atomism”, in Monist 1918; reprinted in Logic and Knowledge. “Philosophy of Logical Atomism II”, in Monist 1919; reprinted in Logic and Knowledge. “Meaning of Meaning”, in Mind 1920. “Introduction” to L. Wittgenstein, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. London 1922. “Physics and Perception”, in Mind 1922. “Doctor Schiller’s Analysis of the Analysis of Mind” in J. of Philosophy 1922. “Logical Atomism” in Contemporary British Philosophy: Personal Statements. London 1924. “Introduction: Materialism: Past and Present”, in F. A. Lange, A History of Materialism. London 1925. “On Non-Euclidean Geometries”; “Theory of Knowledge”; “Philosophical Consequences of the Theory of Relativity”, in Encyclopedia Britannica, thirteenth edition 1926. “On Order in Time”, in Proc. Cambridge Phil. Soc. 1936. “On Verification”, in Proc. Aristotelian Soc. 1937. “The Relevance of Psychology to Logic”, in Proc. Aristotelian Soc. 1938. “On the Importance of Logical Form”, in International Encyclopedia of Unified Science, vol I, Chicago 1938. “Living Philosophy, Revised”, in I Believe, ed. C. Fadiman. New York 1939. “Dewey’s New Logic”, in the The Philosophy of John Dewey, ed. P. A. Schilpp. Chicago 1939. 109 “The Philosophy of Santayana”, in The Philosophy of George Santayana, ed. P. A. Schilpp. Chicago 1940. “My Mental Development”; “Reply to Criticism”, in The Philosophy of Bertrand Russell, ed. P. A. Schilpp. Chicago 1944. “Whitehead and Principia Mathematica”, in Mind 1948. “Ludwig Wittgenstein”, in Mind 1951. “Philosophical Analysis”, in Hibbert Journal 1955-6. “Logic and Ontology”, in J of Philosophy 1957. “Mr Strawson on Referring” in Mind 1957. “What is ‘Mind’?”, in J of Philosophy 1958. 110 ABBREVIATED TITLES BY WHICH RUSSELL’S WORKS ARE CITED A.M. I.M.P I.M.T. L.K. M.P.D. O.K.E.W P.L. P.M. P.O.M. P.P. The Analysis of Mind. Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy. An Inquiry into Meaning and Truth. Logic and Knowledge. My Philosophical Development. Our Knowledge of the External World. A Critical Exposition of the Philosophy of Leibniz. = Principia Mathematica. = The Principles of Mathematics. = The Problems of Philosophy. = = = = = = = 111