doi: 10.1111/j.1420-9101.2007.01475.x SHORT COMMUNICATION One big, and many small reasons that direct selection on offspring number is still open for discussion A. M. SIMONS Department of Biology, Carleton University, Ottawa, ON, Canada Keywords: Abstract bet hedging; diversification strategy; life-history evolution; offspring size–number trade-off; risk spreading; stochastic environment. In a recent paper, I proposed that natural selection should act to increase offspring number when diversification bet hedging is favoured. The simple underlying reasoning is that a target diversification strategy is more reliably generated with increasing sample size. The intention of opening a discussion has been realized; recent criticisms of the idea argue that selection does not act to increase offspring number when population size is large or infinite. Here I agree that criticisms have merit; indeed they are largely confined to the caveats discussed in my original paper. The critique, however, implies a verdict of outright rejection of the idea of selection on offspring number, which would be erroneous. Contrary to the assertions of the criticism, then, the importance of selection acting directly on offspring number remains an open question. Introduction A foundational concept of life-history theory is that of the tradeoff:allocation of finite resources is partitioned among competing life-history characters such that fitness is maximized (Roff, 1992). Evolutionary tradeoffs result when selection favours a simultaneous increase in two (or more) characters in the presence of a negative genetic correlation between them. Perhaps because of its relative tractability, the tradeoff between offspring size and number (Smith & Fretwell, 1974) has become the standard theoretical and empirical example. The perception of this tradeoff has been limited to considerations of the selective consequences of offspring size under particular ecological scenarios whereas offspring number has been viewed exclusively as the fecundity resulting directly from the tradeoff. However, in an earlier paper (Simons, 2007), I proposed ecological situations in which parental fitness may be directly affected by offspring number. The reasoning is as follows. Environmental unpredictability is expected to select for bet-hedging (Slatkin, 1974) strategies: traits that appear to be suboptimal over short timescales, but maximize geometric mean fitness Correspondence: A. M. Simons, Department of Biology, Carleton University, 1125 Colonel By Drive, Ottawa, Ontario, Canada K1S 5B6. Tel.: (613) 520-2600 ext. 3869; fax: (613) 520-3539; e-mail: asimons@connect.carleton.ca 642 among generations (Seger & Brockmann, 1987). Diversification in the timing of seed germination (Cohen, 1966) is a classic example. An assumption not under dispute here, and one for which we have some empirical evidence (Simons & Johnston, 2006), is that individual offspring phenotypes represent random draws from, rather than individually programmed elements of a putative diversification strategy. Given the existence of an optimal diversification strategy – that is to say, one that maximizes long-term fitness – the realization of this diversification strategy improves with the number of offspring produced. I showed that sample variance approaches the ‘target’ variance with increasing sample size (see Fig. 1 of Simons, 2007). The clear intent of my original note was to propose the idea that, to the extent that environmental unpredictably favours diversification bet hedging, direct selection to increase allocation to offspring number merits consideration (Simons, 2007). I included a simulation model as a tentative illustration of the concept. As is stated explicitly, ‘the simulation results are meant only as a qualitative demonstration of the effect of offspring number on geometric-mean fitness’ (Simons, 2007); quantitative assessments of the importance of the concept are thus neglected, and open for future analysis. As anticipated, the original paper prompted discussion about the evolution of increased offspring number as a bet-hedging mechanism: discussion includes an extensive critique (Kisdi, 2007) published in this journal. ª 2007 THE AUTHOR. J. EVOL. BIOL. 21 (2008) 642–645 JOURNAL COMPILATION ª 2007 EUROPEAN SOCIETY FOR EVOLUTIONARY BIOLOGY Selection on offspring number Although it provides an excellent analysis of particular limitations of the idea, it leaves the reader with the mistaken impression that it has discarded the idea outright. Here I show that despite an acknowledgement that increased offspring number may evolve in small populations, the critique focuses almost exclusively on large populations, a condition I pronounced in my original paper as less likely to result in selection for increased number. Furthermore, I reveal errors of logic in the criticism, including the unintended inference that a hypothesis should be rejected because it has not been tested. The most consequential problem is the hasty conclusion drawn, which propagates the impression that the proposal of selection on offspring number is ‘incorrect’, and that the issue is therefore closed. This is the one big reason that, properly framed, the critique in fact constitutes a valuable opening discussion. Large populations The critique (Kisdi, 2007) sets out to show that selection does not act directly on offspring number when population size is large, not that it never acts. The ‘large population’ qualification is expressly made in the critique’s title, is clearly stated in the Abstract, specified diligently again in the Introduction, and the main body of the critique falls under the heading, ‘Large populations’. The critique shows that, in large populations, the strength of selection on offspring number is weakened because average fitness for a genotype should be calculated not just for offspring of an individual parent, but over offspring of all representatives of that genotype. The criticism is compelling, and is valuable in that it shows that the potential for the evolution of offspring number is restricted when populations are infinite or large. My original paper, however, makes no specific claim about the applicability of direct selection for offspring number when populations are large, although this is what would be understood by reading Kisdi’s criticism. The statement in the critique’s Abstract, ‘Contrary to a recent article by A.M. Simons (2007; J. Evol. Biol. 20:813–817), I show that selection does not favour the production of many offspring just to reduce sampling variability when such mixed strategies are used in large populations’ carries the unfortunate implication that I restricted my discussion to large populations. Construed this way, an outright rejection of my proposal seems reasonable: ‘In this note, I set up a simple analytical model to show that Simons’ (2007) claim is incorrect and that in large populations there is no direct selection on offspring number due to sampling stochasticity’ (Kisdi, 2007). Because its application is restricted to the arena of infinite or large populations, Kisdi’s assertion – that my general claim is incorrect – is unwarranted. Furthermore, without going back to my original paper, the reader would not be aware that I agree; I state quite 643 specifically that selection on offspring number is more likely to occur in small populations: Diversification must be manifested at the individual level to confer a bet-hedging advantage to a genotype, and this is most obvious for small populations, or in cases where population size fluctuates widely among generations. Under such situations, in which a genotype is represented by only one or a few individuals, the possibility that diversification can be expressed collectively among individuals of the same genotype is reduced (Simons, 2007). The main point of the critique is thus weakened considerably when understood to mean that direct selection on offspring number is unlikely to apply under the conditions that I have specifically outlined as those under which it is less likely to apply. Note that I not only specify that selection on offspring number is expected to be stronger when population size is small, but also raise the point that it is influenced by demographic fluctuations. Real populations are not only finite, but are subject to demographic fluctuation. This is of paramount importance to the discussion most obviously because effective population size is smaller than census size but, more importantly, because of the negative covariance expected between population size and selection for bet-hedging strategies: it is a defining feature of bet-hedging traits that they confer nonzero fitness through strong selective episodes. The monocarpic plant I originally used to illustrate the concept, Lobelia inflata (Campanulaceae), also provides a good example here in that in 2005 an intense search turned up only five reproductive individuals whereas one hundred to several hundred were found in preceding (Simons & Johnston, 2003) and subsequent years. The model of infinite population size unavoidably ignores this point of critical importance to the evolution of offspring number in real populations. Finite populations The critique has shown that selection for offspring number is unlikely under assumptions of infinite or permanently large populations. The arguments for large populations, however, do not apply to populations in which number of offspring ‘cannot be considered to be infinite’ (Kisdi, 2007). In finite populations, the argument against selection on offspring number centres on the applicability of the geometric-mean principle. The contention that the geometric mean is ‘useless’ as a measure of fitness when population size n is finite (Kisdi, 2007) rests on the fact that if n is finite, there is a nonzero, positive probability of 100% mortality in any generation, and thus all strategies go to extinction with probability 1 given infinite time. In my simulation (Simons, 2007) I used finite population size, and did not allow infinite time. It is correctly pointed out that, as a result, at least some of the replicate ª 2007 THE AUTHOR. J. EVOL. BIOL. 21 (2008) 642–645 JOURNAL COMPILATION ª 2007 EUROPEAN SOCIETY FOR EVOLUTIONARY BIOLOGY 644 A. M. SIMONS runs of my model must have resulted in zero geometricmean fitness, and that this was hidden by the fact that I plotted only the average of 100 runs of the model to provide the best estimate of geometric-mean fitness associated with each value of offspring number. In response, I provide here the proportions of simulation runs that resulted in zero geometric-mean fitness (Fig. 1). However, as expected based on foundational bet-hedging theory (Lewontin & Cohen, 1969), these trends in the proportion of runs resulting in extinction corroborate the finding that increased offspring number may be under direct selection in small populations. Although true that all finite populations are destined for extinction under the assumption of infinite time, crucial information is overlooked: for all time less than infinity, bet-hedging strategies reduce the likelihood of extinction. It is the assumption of infinite time rather than the usefulness of the geometric-mean principle that causes the failure of the analysis for finite populations. Furthermore, regardless of the resolution of the issue of the usefulness of the geometric mean, a conclusion that my proposal (Simons, 2007) is incorrect is based on unsound logic. Specifically, it would be based on the notion that the absence of an analysis for finite populations in some way justifies a rejection of the idea of selection on offspring number in toto. % Replicate runs with zero GM fitness 100 80 60 40 20 0 0 5 10 15 20 25 Offspring number 30 100 Fig. 1 The effect of offspring number on the frequency of simulation runs for which geometric-mean fitness is zero for offspring numbers ranging from two to 100. A diversification strategy of SD = 12 days in the timing of seed germination or egg hatch is assumed, and the quality of the environment within a season varies randomly. The % runs of zero fitness is based on 100 estimates of geometric-mean fitness over 30 growing seasons for each offspring number. For a full explanation of the simulation model, which illustrated the effect of offspring number on geometric-mean fitness, see Simons (2007). Still, an important issue has been raised: what is the correct time scale over which to assess optimality of a bet-hedging strategy? Consider these relevant facts: life persists on this planet, life has evolved over a finite period, all populations are finite, and all extant life is a result of a process of reproduction that is inherently multiplicative. A deduction that follows directly from these facts is that extant life is a biased subsample that represents only and all those forms that have proven to have nonzero geometric-mean fitness. How do we reconcile this fact with analytical results that show all strategies are expected to have zero geometric-mean fitness? The answer lies not only in recognizing the difference between prior and post hoc probabilities and by rejecting the notion of infinite time, but also in considering the evolutionary dynamics of real populations. It becomes meaningless to calculate the fitness associated with a particular heritable trait over greater and greater periods of evolutionary time as mutation and recombination alter the identity of the ‘trait’ of interest (for a full discussion of the geometric-mean principle in hierarchical selection, see Simons, 2002). However, because biologically relevant environmental variance is thought to be characterized by 1 ⁄ f noise, or ‘reddened’ temporal spectra (Ariño & Pimm, 1995; Halley, 1996), use of too short a time scale certainly incurs a risk of overlooking a rare, severe event that might cause extinction. It is on the balance between these considerations that I chose to evaluate the geometric-mean fitness over 30 generations in my illustration. Because diversification reduces the probability of extinction (Fig. 1) in my model of finite populations, increasing this time period would in fact cause stronger selection for increased offspring number. The explicit intent of my simulation was to demonstrate the plausibility of the idea: ‘This optimality approach is a first step toward an understanding of the selective advantage of increased offspring number, and does not pretend to detail its evolutionary dynamics. For example, the rate of evolution toward the optimal balance between offspring number and size will depend not only on the magnitude of fluctuating selection, but also on the quantitative genetic basis of diversification and demographic properties of the population’ (Simons, 2007). In fact the critique acknowledges that, in principle, selection for increased offspring number can occur in finite populations, but that neither participant in the discussion so far has employed appropriate techniques (See references in Kisdi, 2007) to answer the question. Conclusions It would be premature to presume, from a demonstration that my original model does not apply under particular circumstances, that the discussion of direct selection on offspring number is closed. Rather, Kisdi’s critique, interpreted correctly, is encouraging in that it should be taken to mark the beginning of this discussion. The ª 2007 THE AUTHOR. J. EVOL. BIOL. 21 (2008) 642–645 JOURNAL COMPILATION ª 2007 EUROPEAN SOCIETY FOR EVOLUTIONARY BIOLOGY Selection on offspring number proposal that direct selection on offspring number alters the optimal balance with offspring size (Simons, 2007) is in essence qualitative; no quantitative claim of the importance of this effect relative to other influences on the tradeoff are made. Kisdi (2007) acknowledges the potential for ‘weak’ selection on offspring number, ‘but only in finite populations’. However, because this is an indefinite quantitative claim, the strength of the constraints on the general applicability of selection on offspring number remains unknown. Evidence that it is not universally applicable is not inconsistent with the proposal, but does make a valid claim constraining its applicability. If future research finds that diversification bet hedging is selected for predominantly in consistently large populations, we can conclude that the original proposal is universally unimportant. On the other hand, future analyses may show that selection for diversification accounts in part for the evolution of high propagule number in small populations or in populations subject to demographic fluctuations. The conclusion from my original note bears repetition here: the degree to which fluctuating selection influences the evolution of propagule number provides fertile ground for future study. Acknowledgments The author thanks M.O. Johnston and J.-G. Godin for helpful comments. This research is supported by an NSERC Discovery grant to A.M.S. 645 Cohen, D. 1966. Optimizing reproduction in a randomly varying environment. J. Theor. Biol. 12: 119–129. Halley, J.M. 1996. Ecology, evolution and 1 ⁄ f-noise. Trends Ecol. Evol. 11: 33–37. Kisdi, É. 2007. No direct selection to increase offspring number of bet-hedging strategies in large populations: Simons’ model revisited. J. Evol. Biol. 20: 2072–2074. Lewontin, R.C. & Cohen, D. 1969. On population growth in a randomly varying environment. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA 62: 1056–1060. Roff, D.A. 1992. The Evolution of Life Histories: Theory and Analysis. Chapman and Hall, New York. Seger, J. & Brockmann, H.J. 1987. What is bet-hedging? Oxford Surv. Evol. Biol. 4: 182–211. Simons, A.M. 2002. The continuity of microevolution and macroevolution. J. Evol. Biol. 15: 688–701. Simons, A.M. 2007. Selection for increased allocation to offspring number under environmental unpredictability. J. Evol. Biol. 20: 813–817. Simons, A.M. & Johnston, M.O. 2003. Suboptimal timing of reproduction in Lobelia inflata may be a conservative bethedging strategy. J. Evol. Biol. 16: 233–243. Simons, A.M. & Johnston, M.O. 2006. Environmental and genetic sources of diversification in the timing of seed germination: implications for the evolution of bet hedging. Evolution 60: 2280–2292. Slatkin, M. 1974. Hedging one’s evolutionary bets. Nature 250: 704–705. Smith, C.C. & Fretwell, S.D. 1974. The optimal balance between size and number of offspring. Am. Nat. 108: 499–506. Received 30 October 2007; accepted 8 November 2007 References Ariño, A. & Pimm, S.L. 1995. On the nature of population extremes. Evol. Ecol. 9: 429–443. ª 2007 THE AUTHOR. J. EVOL. BIOL. 21 (2008) 642–645 JOURNAL COMPILATION ª 2007 EUROPEAN SOCIETY FOR EVOLUTIONARY BIOLOGY