:- (UBfiARIES .H414 — ALFRED P. WORKING PAPER SLOAN SCHOOL OF MANAGEMENT ON INTERTEMPORAL PREFERENCES WITH A CONTINUOUS TIME DIMENSION II: THE CASE OF UNCERTAINTY by Ayman Hindy and Chi-fu Huang WP# 2105-89 March 1989 MASSACHUSETTS INSTITUTE OF TECHNOLOGY 50 MEMORIAL DRIVE CAMBRIDGE, MASSACHUSETTS 02139 ^241989] ON INTERTEriPORAL PREFERENCES WITH A CONTINUOUS TIME DIMENSION II: THE CASE OF UNCERTAINTY by Ayman Hindy and Chi-fu Huang WP# 2105-89 March 1989 JUL 2 4 1989 ON INTERTEMPORAL PREFERENCES WITH A CONTINUOUS TIME DIMENSION II: THE CASE OF UNCERTAINTY Ayman Hindy and School of Chi-fu Huang* Management Massachusetts Institute of Technology Cambridge, 02139 MA March 1989 Abstract This paper proposes a family of topologies on the space of consumption patterns time under uncertainty. continuous Preferences continuous in any of the proposed topologies treat con- sumptions at nearly adjacent dates The in cis almost perfect substitutes except possibly at surprises. topological duals of the family of proposed topologies essentially contain processes that are the sums for consumption come from the duals, consumptions of processes of absolutely continuous paths and martingales. prices except possibly at surprises. In particular, Brownian motion, the duals are composed of if when the information structure Ito processes. there are no arbitrage opportunities. our topologies on standard models of choice in if equilibrium prices at nearly adjacent dates have almost equal of long-lived assets in economies populated with agents topologies Thus We is generated by a discuss the properties of prices whose preferences are continuous We also investigate in our some implications of continuous time as well as on recent models of non time-separable representations of preferences. 'The authors are thankful for the helpful conversations with David Kreps throughout the years this paper was in preparation. Huang is also grateful for research support under the Batterymarch Fellowship Program. Introduction and 1 summary Mom, I can not eat any spinach now. my had I just dinner. Anonymous summary Introduction and 1 No "standard" economic agent could use the above convincing argument to delay his consump- tion. "Standard" economic models assume that very recent consumption has no effect on one's current appetite; an cissumption that each of us repeatedly violates. In addition, we frequently violate an important implication of the "standard models" con- cerning the prices of Eissets. be much higher than will If one knows for sure that the price of a certain asset tomorrow today then one would be willing to delay his consumption it is day and use the proceeds to buy such an else who is asset. Alternatively, willing to delay his consumption, pay him a the funds to realize the gain in the price of the asset. to increase and become very Our behavior would tomorrow. If new information might and use force today's price no one were willing to jump delay consumption for one day for a small fee, then a situation of a big periods in the absence of any one one could borrow from someone relatively low rate of interest close to the price of the asset for in prices over short prevail in equilibrium. In fact, this is a prediction of "standard" models in which continuous changes in prices are obtained mainly by We exogenously specifying continuously varying endowments. one develop a model ask: could of preferences for consumption over time under uncertainty that agrees with our economic intuition in of prices of the which past consumption has an is is on current and utility in which the continuity a phenomenon implied by continuity of preferences and independent of the nature endowments? This paper This effect is an attempt to address these the second part of a series of two papers. which we henceforth abbreviate as H&K, The first issues. Huang and Kreps part, addresses the following questions: How might (1987), one rep- what are the appropriate resent a consumption pattern in continuous time under certainty and topologies on the space of consumption patterns that capture the idea that consumptions at nearly adjacent dates are almost perfect substitutes? Moreover, rium prices take when individuals the in what form would the economy have preferences continuous in the equilib- appropriate topologies? "Standard" answers exist for the questions raised by U&iK: time interval, say is [0,1], is represented by a real-valued function the consumption "rate" at time functions in an 1/ A norm topology t. for Two some 1 c consumption pattern on a : [0,1] consumption patterns are close < p < oo. An — > if 5R+, where c{t) they are close as agent's preferences are represented by 1 Introduction and summary 2 j} u{c{t),t)dt, a time-additive functional of consumption rates, where, using the terminology of Arrow and Kurz p consumption pattern c y{t) is interpreted as the and a "felicity" function for consumption at time is come from L' with equilibrium prices at time zero of a (1970), u{c,t) + ^ = !> ^^^ topological dual of I/; that is, can be represented as /q c{t)y{t)dt, where y t. The the price is from L' time zero price of one unit of consumption per unit time at time t. H&K in argued that these standard answers are unsatisfactory for the following reasons. First, modeling consumption over time, one should allow consumption at rates as well as observed consumption behavior such as having meals the 1/ topology on the space of consumption rates is so strong along the time dimension that consumptions at nearly adjacent dates are perfect nonsubstitutes! the strong topology, the space of equilibrium prices is gulps - Second and more important, in gulps. is in too rich. As a consequence of includes, for example, It discontinuous functions of time and continuous functions of unbounded variation signifying that equilibrium prices for consumptions at nearly adjacent dates are either very different or, even though continuous, fluctuate The most general way in a nowhere differentiable manner. for representing a by an increasing^ and positive function on consumption pattern over time under certainty [0,1]. Let x be such a function. the accumulated consumption from time zero to time of time, The its t. If is x{t) denotes an absolutely continuous function derivatives exist almost everywhere and can be interpreted as consumption rates. discontinuities of x are the gulps of consumption. space of these consumption patterns, among i Then H&K Letting introduce a family of X be the linear span of the norm topologies on X so that, other things, consumptions at nearly adjacent dates are almost perfect substitutes. example of is this family of norm topologies is the L'' An topology on accumulated consumption, where the Z^-norm of a consumption pattern i is given by: {C\x{t)\^dt + ix(i)r)p. Jo HiiK also show that preferences continuous in any of the norm topologies can be represented by maximizing the time-additive functional of consumption rates only if the felicity functions are linear! The equilibrium in the "standard answers" prices basically come from absolutely continuous functions - prices of consumptions at nearly adjacent dates are almost equal and change over time in an almost differentiable manner. 'Note that one might expect equilibrium prices for consumption to fluctuate widely in an economy under uncertainty due to temporal resolution of uncertainty, however; see Huang (1985a, 1985b). ^Throughout this paper we will use weak relations: increasing means nondecreasing, positive means nonnegative, etc. When the relations are strict, we will say, for example, strictly increasing. 1 Introduction and summary 3 of this paper The purpose to develop topologies on the space of consumption patterns is under uncertainty that capture the notion that consumptions at adjacent dates are almost A perfect substitutes. under uncertainty is crucial distinction between an economy under certainty and an economy that in the latter the passage of time also reveals partially the true state of nature, or reveals information. In a world of uncertainty, the preferences of an individual over consumption patterns may be affected by the way uncertainty which any uncertainty for new is Thus dates, which it is is certainly different from a world which A world in is "sudden" and "full of unreasonable to require a priori that consumptions at nearly adjacent may be random, be almost perfect substitutes unless there are no "surprises" there. we would not expect the equilibrium Similarly, resolved over time. resolved gradually over time, with ample "warning" and "preparation" bits of information surprises". is prices to be continuous except at (random) times of no surprise. We introduce a family of topologies on the linear span of the set of consumption norm patterns under uncertainty, which is composed of processes with positive and increasing paths. This family of topologies are natural generalizations of the H<5iK topologies. they reduce to the H&K topologies when the true state of nature consumptions at nearly adjacent dates, where there almost perfect substitutes. (to be defined) in We is In particular, and revealed at time is no discontinuity of information, are then show that preferences continuous and uniformly proper any one of the family of topologies exhibit intuitively appealing economic properties. In general equilibrium theory, equilibrium prices Thus we come from the topological dual spaces. also characterize the topological duals of the suggested family of show that they are essentially functions. topologies and composed of processes which are sums of processes This continuous paths and martingales. the case of certainty the norm shadow is prices for a very natural result. consumption are Hence preferences that treat consumption H&K of absolutely have shown that in essentially absolutely continuous at nearly adjacent dates as almost perfect substitutes will give rise to nearly equal prices for consumption at nearly adjacent dates and these prices vary over time in an almost differentiable fashion; an intuitively attractive conclusion. In the case of uncertainty a new element, the pattern sample path properties of equilibrium nent of the price process. at surprises It is and can fluctuate prices. known that in a manner (due effect is captured a martingale can in the martingale compo- make discontinuous changes only nowhere differentiable fashion. Thus equilibrium prices consumption are continuous except possibly entiable This of information flow, affects the at surprises and can fluctuate to temporal resolution of uncertainty). in a nowhere for differ- This agrees with our economic Introduction and 1 summary 4 intuition. We also investigate properties of arbitrage-free price processes in a economy where an arbitrage opportunity ket from our family of topologies. It is shown securities between lumpvsum ex-dividend dates, price that, In particular, the information struc- if generated by a Brownian motion and accumulated dividend process of a security is absolutely continuous process, the ex-dividend price process for this security It is mar- defined using concepts of continuity derived is processes are continuous except possibly at surprises. ture dynamic is is an an Ito process. worthwhile to point out that earlier models of equilibrium using the standard repre- sentation of utility had to rely on exogenous factors in addition to preferences to characterize Huang the sample path properties of equilibrium prices; see Duffie (1986) and example, in the ceise of a lutely continuous Brownian motion filtration, accumulated dividend process endowment process is. the price process for a security with abso- will not be an Ito process unless the aggregate consumption In our setup, however, since For (1987). at nearly adjacent dates are almost perfect substitutes at times of no surprise, price processes of securities with absolutely continuous accumulated dividends will be Ito processes independently of the properties of the aggregate endowment process. As for the existence of an Arrow-Debreu equilibrium whose preferences are continuous in in one of our topologies, we have opens up a question about the existence of an equilibrium rest of this paper is and an information structure is F = [0, 1]. Taken £ [0, l]}i {Tt',t time 7 , Known economies of our type. eis primitive is specifies how a probability space (n, Q where each u E will consider, P) denotes a state of nature, P is the probability beliefs and F, an increasing family of 7 distinguishable events in 1, ,', are revealed from time to 1. A ing, fields of in the collection of distinguishable events at time about possible events held by the individuals we sub-sigma to report. organized as follows. Section 2 formulates the stochastic environ- ment under study with a time span 7, a sigma-field, little an equilibrium are not satisfied by our topologies. This sufficient conditions for the existence of The an economy populated with agents consumption pattern x = {x{t);t € [0,1]} and right-continuous sample paths which is is a stochastic process having positive, increas- consistent with variable x{t) denotes the accumulated consumption from time of consumption patterns and X so that We X be the linear span of X+. preferences continuous with respect to put forth a wishlist for a topology wishlist in Section 3. The agenda on our T it Our F or adapted to F. to time task is t. Let X-(- The random be the space to define a topology is on exhibit economically desirable properties. and introduce a family of topologies to wishlist T two-fold: First, an satisfy this economy under certainty ^ Introduction and 1 is sf>ecial case of a summary an economy under uncertainty where the true state of nature In such event, at time 0. 5 necessitates that the we would norms of like H&K our topology to agree with the H<kK be used path by path is revealed This topology. by state) on a consumption (state pattern. For the L^ example mentioned above, the path-wise distance between x 6 X+ and is where i(a;, t) is in (1) p is the value of the random a function of the state of nature trade-off of consumption across time is when the variable x{t) the w - there same is state of nature time in may w. Note that no a priori reason to expect that the for all states. One Second, consider substitutability of consumption across states. a time in a particular event is unit of consumption at be a close substitute to one unit of consumption at the same another event for an individual. But there is no economic reason to expect that all individuals with continuous preferences consider consumptions in different events to be close substitutes. Thus the topology on X should not a priori build in substitutability of consumption On across states in an arbitrary manner. consumption in an event which is the other hand, it is quite intuitive that one unit of very unlikely to occur should be close to not consuming at all. With all these considerations in mind, a natural struction in the previous paragraph is way of aggregating the path-wise con- to just take expectation. Taking expectations embodies the notion that consumptions at two disjoint events are perfect nonsubstitutes except when both events are negligible in probability and thus the two consumption patterns are almost indistinguishable from zero. Taking expectations also embodies the notion that, at any time, the differences of preferences for consumption in two events with the decreasing function in the degree of overlap of the two events. We same probability is a here remind the reader that defining such a strong topology and considering continuous preferences certainly does not rule out preferences that actually consider consumptions across states to be close substitutes. They will be special cases of preferences continuous above, except now that p is in the "strong" topology. In is a standard U' same U' example nonrandom, the norm of a consumption pattern x G {^^j\x[t)ydt + which the \x[\)Y X+ is then (2) norm but on accumulated consumptions rather than on consumption rates. ^The reader may have noticed that (2) is not finite for attention to a subset of X-|. depending on the topology. every i € X.).. Thus we will have to restrict our 1 summary Introduction and we develop some In section 4 defined in Section ties of the 6 3. topological and uniform properties of the family of topologies The reader will see that the family of topologies inherit Hi:K topologies when those many proper- properties are properly "aggregated" across states by taking expectations. Basically, the family of topologies exhibit the desired economic property: consumptions at nearly adjacent dates where there are no discontinuities of information are almost perfect substitutes. Since uniformly proper preferences (see Mas Colell (1986)) have been needed for the general equilibrium theory, we also investigate properties of preferences that are continuous and uniformly proper. Section 5 characterizes the topological duals of the family of topologies under consideration. We show there that the topological dual spaces corresponding to our topology - spaces which contain the shadow price of consumption - consist of processes that can be decomposed into the sum of two components: an absolutely continuous part and a martingale part. We show that a topological dual space corresponding to each one of our topologies may a sublattice in known the order dual; a property further fail to be to be sufficient, together with other things, to guarantee existence of a Walrasian equilibrium in our model. In particular, in the case of Brownian motion information, the duals spaces are not sublattices of the order duals. Section 6 examines up. how standard models with time-additive utility functions fare in our set Similar to the results of HA:K, preferences represented by time-additive utility functions over consumption rates are continuous in any of our topologies In addition, we examine some consumption on current are not continuous in the sense that In section 7 curities in Bergman utility, we they are linear. (1985), Constantinides (1988), Heaton we examine the implications dynamic asset markets. Our In particular, most of them imply preferences that of our topologies on the prices of long-lived se- discussion under conditions of "no arbitrage." in section 5. find that we advocate. we show that is We show long lived securities inherit the properties of the tures, if and Sundaresan (1988). Although such representations have elements that capture the effect of pzist prices and only of the prevalent representations in the literature of "non time- additive" utility functions such as those in (1988), if along two lines. First, we examine that in this case the prices over time of shadow in the case of prices of consumption that we discuss Brownian motion information and absent any arbitrage opportunities, the prices of long lived securities continuous accumulated dividend processes will be Ito processes. This result by the continuity of preferences. Second, continuous trading in we asset struc- with absolutely is purely driven discuss similar issues in the case of markets with dynamic equilibrium, under the assumption that such an equilibrium exists. Section 8 contains concluding remarks. Formulation 2 7 Formulation 2 Consider an economic agent is who lives in a world of uncertainty from time a single consumption good available for consumption at any time modeled by a probability space w € n J,P). Each (fl, a complete description of one possible realization of time to time and at time 1 We This is / sigma-field There Uncertainty is represents a state of nature which is t [0,1]. exogenous sources of uncertainty from represents the collection of events which are distinguishable a probability meeisure on modeled by a is We P The 1. {CI, 7). take as given the time evolution of our agent's knowledge about the states of nature. fields of J; t. 1. all G to time that filtration T, '^ 7t ii s assume that T = 7i, F filtration is, F= {Tt; < Interpret that t. t E which \0,l]}, 7t an increasing family of sub sigma- is as the information that the agent has at time known 1, and the suppose that the information structure satisfies the true state of nature will be is, at time satisfies the following usual conditions: 1. F is complete in that 7o contains 2. F is right continuous in that /( we Besides these usual conditions, = all P-null sets; Tt+, where will further = 7t+ ^»- At<« a regularity condition, which almost always holds in applications. Before we do that, some definitions are in order. T Q— Definition 1 The function : [0,oo] is an optional time with respect {ujen:T{uj)<t}eTt An optional time can always be interpreted to be the condition be {wen: < T{oj) known whether a E t} certain event Definition 2 An optional time times {Tn} such that T„ Tn y T. Tt in < T The sequence {Tn} Intuition suggests that if T a.s. is the F if VtG[0,l]. first time a certain event happens. The the above definition then says that at any time happened or is to will not. said to be predictable and on t, it the set {T > if there exists a 0}, almost surely, sequence of optional Tn < Tn+i < T and said to announce T. first time an event happens is announced by the occurrence of a sequence of other events, then the event will not take one by surprise. This intuition turns out not to be correct for general information structures and information structure: is valid for a quasi left-continuous Formulation 2 An Definition 3 and its 8 F information structure quasi is left- continuous if for a predictable time T announcing sequence {T„} we have oo ^r V = ^T„ = 7t- , n=l where 7t is a sigma-field of events prior to Af]{T < We For example, the or a combination of the two is filtration 7® For each consisting of all events y is is quasi left-continuous. This Y{ui,-) fi, : a mapping [0,1] -> dt is to be adapted to constraint: F for each if E t [0,1], V n : x [0, 1] — to F that 9i 7 and life all /^-measurable. This is t consumption from time the Borel sigma-field of t F (-,«): fi -» !R The process Y is said G is [0, l], a natural information the processes to appear will be measurable and adapted is represented by a process x whose sam- and right-continuous with to time t We in state w. x{uj,t) denoting the accumulated denote the set of such processes by linear span of X-(., the space of processes having right-continuous sample paths, will only on a subset of preferences over "continuous." X+. and bounded variation be denoted by X. For technical reasons, which will be clear later, this subset for now by we £.^ will consider preferences defined The agent is assumed to have which are given by a complete and transitive binary relation > that £, Our X+. Denote made task is to define a topology, say T , is on C such that preferences continuous with respect to which exhibit desirable economic properties. This now measurable with cannot depend on the information yet to be time consumption pattern of an agent ple paths are positive, increasing, The Y{t) is unless otherwise mentioned. The is the subject to which we turn. *It has been shown by Meyer (1963) at predictable optional times (defined is > & sample path and for each the value of the process at time revealed in the future. For brevity, without much completed.^ is a random variable, which we will usually simply use Y{t) to denote. is is generated by a diffusion process, a Poisson process, S([0,l]), the product sigmarfield generated by we such that for allte\0,l]. 7t, F AE 7 quasi left-continuous once the filtration measurable stochastic process respect to [0,1]. e assume throughout our analysis that loss of generality. A t} T that any information structure generated by a process that with respect to its natural filtration) and has the strong is continuous Markov property quasi left-continuous. ^This subset in fact depends on the topology chosen. The reader can think of the the classical Banach space all the random variables and is "topology-dependent." example: L''(Q,7,P) certainly does not include A 3 A 3 norm family of topologies 9 norm family of Before proceeding, we will topologies review the family of first briefly H<kK norm This space, denoted by X, span of the space of consumption patterns under certainty. linear space An composed of functions on [0, 1] to time and A topology t. fi{oo) inverse of = in the oo that /i, r; : i € X+, H&K x{t) denotes the , = a an increasing, positive, and right- is accumulated consumption from time family corresponds to a function SR+ with f7(0) > X+ strictly increasing, continuous, is — !R+ If [0, 1]. is that are right-continuous and of bounded variation. element of the positive orthant of X, denoted by continuous function on topologies on the linear = oo r,{\x{t)\/a)dt + r,(|i(l)|/a) — St^. : and concave. r?(oo) and /i * !R+ with Defining rj = /i(0) = n~^ the , strictly increaising, continuous, is and Then convex. inf{a > /" : < 1} Jo defines a norm H&K the above norm. Two (1) x E X. Let > be a preference relation continuous for showed that the following properties are X > y and y > Xn for all (2) Sizable shifts in n — » is € X+ , n implies = inf{f ^ y for y > — |in(i) ij x{t)\ = then Xn 0, > : i{< + e) + e > y{t) > x{t - e) - e, t y for >: that y, and y uniformly proper is in >; in for all amount of time is all n implies insignificant: propemets will [0, l]}. n implies y >: If p(xn,x) — > as x. the direction X|m)> the indicator function of regarded negligible. This into the picture: definition of uniform, e [O, l].) the sense of Mais Colell (1986)^, shift of an increasingly large The formal > x. n implies x > all across a decreasingly small comes lim„_oo sup^giQ the Prohorov metric on the space of increasing functions on oo, then Xn 1], in if let Moreover, for [t, by >. consumption across small amounts of time are regarded as p{x, y) (This satisfied topology defined by patterns of consumption that have almost equal accumulated consumption at every point in time are close: for I, y in the be given later. amount is of consumption where the function /i 3 A (3) Let {x„} and {t/n} be two sequences of consumption patterns with the properties that norm family of topologies {i„(l)} and {y„(l)} are both Xn + Xt > Vn, Litereilly, where {in(l)} means (3) if aw;ross which consumption the sequences in (l) (3) and p(in,yn) < 1/", then for o{fi{n)) means lim„^oo amount of = 0. consumption shifted increases to and incresises to infinity n x„(l)//i(fi) if large n, all sufficiently infinity at a rate the decreasingly small time interval shifted goes to zero faster than 1/n goes to zero, then the shift is (2) are topological properties while (3) is a uniform property since the diverge rather than converge. With these above First, note that H<kK facts about the tions that determine a family of tainty. (ii) (i) terms of preferences. insignificant in Note that is and o(/i(rj)), is slower than the rate at which 10 norm degenerates to an HitK topology X is to two considera- X. a special case of an economy under uncer- to a case of the latter where the true state of nature at time 0. Therefore, a candidate topology time zero, the topology on we now turn topologies on subspaces of an economy under certainty The former corresponds ||x|| topologies in mind, when Jo is revealed under uncertainty should have the property that = 7i. That is, if the true state u> E. Q it were known at should be generated by the "norm:" =inf{a>0: / + <p{u,\x{u,t)\/a)dt ^{<^,\x{uj,l)\/a) < l), Jo for some creasing, tp{u,-) : 5R+ — 5R+ with <p[oj,0) > and convex. Note that n{u, •) = = and ^(a;,oo) (p{uj, •)~Ms a /i in = oo that is continuous, strictly in- HA:K that measures how fast shifts of consumption across time increase to infinity in property (3) above. (Here, however, depend upon the state of nature since every state of nature can be viewed under certainty and there time will be identical that an in is no a priori we expect >1 is is expect that the trade-off of consumption over of an i G X. P should be "close" to not consuming at from A except all. On no reason to expect that one unit of consumption at time a close substitute for one unit of consumption at the same time but disjoint economy that one unit of consumption at any time and in an event which negligible in terms of probability hand, a priori, there may each one of these different economies.) This consideration necessitates H<kK norm be used on a path Second, reeison to as a different /i when both A and in is the other t in event another event A' A' are negligible in terms of probability P, since in which case, both consumption patterns are "close" to These two considerations suggest that we use H&K zero. path-by-path and "pa^te" together these path-wise constructions by taking expectation according to P. This leads us to the notion of A 3 norm family of topologies 11 (Musielak (1983) a Generalized Orlicz space. is The a good reference.) following is a brief introduction. Consider the measure space (n x [0,1],0,P x A), where the sigma-field generated by P the Lebesgue measure on [0,1], and mapping on fJ X [0, 1] that that an optional process is F the processes adapted to all x A is the optional sigma-field - is having right-continuous paths, A P the product measure generated by meeisurable with respect to an optional process. is and It is A. is A known adapted to F; see Chung and Williams (1983). Denote the space of is optional processes with equivalence P x A almost everywhere by O. Note that X is a subspace of O. $ Let be the collection of functions ^ n : x !R+ — 5R+ meeisurable with respect to » J B(!R) with, almost surely, <p{u),0) = and = v'(a;,oo) oo, that are continuous, strictly increasing, convex, and integrable in that (p{ijj, / z)P{d(jj) < Vz > 0. for a, ^ > 0, x 5R+ — oo Jn A modular is (a) e(0) = (b) ^(i) = (c) e(-i) (d) ^{ax For <p a function ^ : O— + [0,oo] such that 0; implies i - + = 0; + ^(y) for x, y e(x); ^y) < ^{x) € ^ and for all i € O, ^(w, G O |i(a;, <)|) and : n » a 5R+ -h /? is = 1. measurable with respect to 7 ® S (5R) and ^W = In /o V>{<^, \x{uj,t)\)dtP{duj) + /n ^(u;, \x{uj, l)\)P{du) (3) ^E[l^cpi\x{t)\)dt is + r{\x{l)\)] a modular on O. The modular V The ^ defines the so called generalized Orlicz space, xeO-.E /V(7|x(t)l)dt + vp(7l^(l)l) U' where , as 7 -» 0-f- (4) set ^=\xeO:E f\{\xmdt + ^{\x{l)\) Jo < oo (5) , 3 A family of norm topologies 12 will be called a generalized Orlicz class. It O the smallest vector subspace of in Lq X that Lq The containing Lq. a convex subset of L'^ and is largest vector subspace of O L^ is contained is E^ = <x e O: E An known is € E^ Remark <p['j\x{t)\) dt 1^ + V7>ol. <oo <p[t\x{l)\) (6) said to be a finite element of L^. is 1 If x) (p{u!, = <p{x) is independent ofu, we say that Orlicz class, respectively. Also, in the case of certainty, there L"^ and Lq are Orlicz space no distinction between L^ is , and Lg, and Ef. We will henceforth restrict our attention to E'^ on which we define a norm: , Definition 4 Given the function = \\x\\^ it is E ^, we mL>0:E (For the fact that (7) defines a Here <p norm on E'^ As we mentioned earlier, X is , \\ = \z\'^ some for where • || || is 1 Proof. The first E'^. (if''',!! by \\-\\^ oo, then a proper subset of O, therefore £'^ contains processes whose (£''',11 • a ||^) is A P • ||,^) is a normed space Now = putting f '^ E'^ normed space with compact order f]^, the intervals, with norm-compact order intervals. proof of the second assertion • || ||^ peistes together the - as we envisioned earlier. is • || \\^ norm on a is provided in Appendix A. path-wise H&K E'^ and if^ is a I construction by taking expec- Henceforth, denote the topology on if '^ generated by T^. Denote the positive orthant of f '^ by f^ then a consumption pattern. The cone i,y e < p < equivalent to the standard 1/ norm. assertion follows from the fact that Note that the norm tation under 1 as defined in (7) but restricted to £'^. Proposition subspace of (7) L''(n X [0,1],0,P X A), sample paths are not of bounded variation or right-continuous. following proposition shows that on E'^ as follows: Vi G E'^ • \\ Musielak (198S).) see if <p{ijJ, \z\) L^ = L^ = E^ = in Definition 4 is norm l\[^-^)dt + ^{^-^) <l|. worthwhile to remark that and the norm defined define a S'^. We say x is S^ h <f^f|X+, which defines an order on f "greater" than y, denoted by i > y, if i - is ''' y a cone. in Each i € f^ is the following way: Let G f^. 3 A family of norm topologies For the analysis to follow, 13 we shall cissume that our agent's preferences > are defined on if ^ and are continuous with respect to T^. Using the terminology of general equilibrium theory, C^ and f^ A are referred to as the commodity space and the consumption set, respectively. natural question that arises from the above definition of commodity spaces The answer spaces and their corresponding topologies compare. is to such a question how is these given in the following proposition. Proposition 2 Let < <P2{<^, z) where h is (p{uj,z) — all is some It is Theorem the topologies {T^; T is all y? easily verified that, for all <tp{uj,\z\) random — a.e. strictly positive constants. <i''c fcz x X Then there is is a weakest one - the one generated by formally stated in the following corollary. e $. e ^, h{u>) PxA-a.e. Vz > The variable h on {Q,T,P)- assertion then follows from I 2. 2 // <p + The commodity space corresponding Remark ki, P I 8.5). G $}, ip weaker than T^ for positive integrable Proposition Q and and stronger than T^j. \z\ for Vz > h{u)) and denoted henceforth by T. This \z\ Corollary 1 Proof. + ki(pi{(jj,k2z) See Musielak (1983, Among satisfy: a positive integrable function on £fi c f'2, and T^, Proof. & ^ <pi,(p2 ipi written as: There and is <p2 ki,k2 are independent of > and zq (P2{z) Now that we > < = to <p{uj,z) ui, \z\ will be denoted by £. then the condition in Proposition 2 can be such that ki<pi{k2z) Vr > Zq. have defined a family of commodity spaces and their corresponding topologies, the next item on our agenda is to see whether continuous (and uniformly proper) preferences give rise to economically desirable behavior. 4 and uniform properties of T^ Tof)ological Topological and uniform properties of 7^ 4 In this section we whether the topology T^ gives economically reasonable sense will investigate f^ of "closeness" for consumption patterns in Tip 14 inherits many for all <p € ^. H<kK topology when those properties of a The reader will find out that properties are appropriately ag- gregated across states. In particular, consumptions at nearly adjacent dates where there no is discontinuity of information are almost perfect substitutes - a natural generalization of HiiK. We first record two facts about {S'^,T,p). Proposition 3 Suppose Then (f',7^) that [Cl,T,P) is separable. separable is a normed topo- logical vector space. Proof. Recall that [Q, such that for every A where 7 P) , > e is separable if whatever small and A T E. denotes the symmetric difference of two dense set of (f '^, T^) {Bn G there exists a countable set there exists Then sets. it is B„ such 7; n = 1,2, . . P{AABn) < that .} e, easy to see that a countable the set of right-continuous bounded simple processes that change their is values at rational time points, take rational values, and vanish except at finite subsets of {fin}. (A process [0,1], Y is simple there exists a finite subdivision if and random variables a,ai, Y{u;,t) = Remark a{u)x{o}{t) + E7:I . . . = C[0, l], J,P) is fact that this probability space An immediate consequence is < ti < • • < tn = I o{ I separable. For example, in the space of continuous function on generated by open sets defined by the sup to 7t_-measurable and bounded such that: a,- is Mu;)xit,.t.^,]{t).) 3 In most applications, (n, cial markets, CI ,a„_i, where = norm on C[0,l], and [0, 1], P is J many models is the of finan- the Borel sigma-field Wiener measure. The separable can be found, for example, in Billingsley (1968). of Proposition 3 is that any continuous preference relation > on separable (f^, T^) has a numerical representation; see Debreu (1954). Next we will examine preference relation in process, we First, will also we in HA^K what alternative forms the three properties satisfied by a continuous as reviewed in the beginning of Section 3 continue to hold. In the show that absolutely continuous consumption patterns are dense. give an example to show that two consumption patterns that have almost equal accumulated consumption at every point be close. in time and in almost every state of nature may not 4 Topological and uniform properties of 7^ Example as n —* pE^. 1 Fix and oo, the let Bn e T Let random 15 c B„ V such that B„+i be ¥„ > variable be n, such that P(B„) > and P[B„) -> 0, = n/P[Bn) (p[ijj,Yn{oj)) a.s. Consider the sequence of consumption patterns where XB„ That indicator function of the set Bn- ** the until time I, at ift< = Xn['^,t) which time = otherwise. Let x{t) 1; i„ provides for no consumption is, provides Yn units of consumption in the event it for all t. It is easy to see that lim sup = \xn{uj,t)\ Bn and nothing 0, a.s. "-'~«elo,il But E Note that ^ <p{xn{t))dt - ||i„ — x\\^ E i/ > f + ^{x„{l))^= and only - <p{-i{xn{t) <p{u;,Yn{uj))P{du;) j^ > for all 7 if + x{t)))dt = n oo as n oo. 0, >p{i{xn{l) - -> x{l))) as n-^ 00; .Jo Theorem see Musielak (198S, Xn >i y for In the n all 1.6, p. imply that x > to S). Thus ||i„ — as n —* 00 i||^ 7^ y. above example, x„ converges uniformly to zero pointwise. however, in(l) increeises to x, supj^rg vanishing probability. The ji l^nC'^, t) Along the sets {Bn}, such a way that (p[(jj,Xn{<^,i)) grows to infinity faster infinity in than the probability of B„ decreases to Xn to converge to and we do not expect ~ zero. Thus 2:(w,t)| a:„ does not converge to zero cannot grow too fast in T^. For even on sets of gradually following proposition gives an alternative form of property (1) of H&K. Proposition 4 Let x,y,Xn € and if there exists a supj^fQi] |i„(cti,t) implies y > Proof. By eis n — » - if' for all n. random x{ijj,i)\ < variable K{(jj) K a.s., // lim„_oo sup^gfo,!] |in(w,t) with the property that then in >: y for all - = x{ijj,t)\ E[^{X)] < a.s. such that 00, n implies x > y and y > Xn x. the continuity of 00. Recall >: from Example E 1^ with respect to T^, we only have to show that 1 <p{l\Xn{t) that - it suffices to X{t)\) dt + show for any 7 > ^(7|X„(1) - l(l)l) 0. ||in - x\\p —> , 4 Topological and uniform properties of T^ The 16 assertion then follows from the Lebesgue convergence theorem and the fact that (p[uj,z) continuous in z and = ip[(jj,0) is I 0. Second, we want to show that sizable shift of consumption within the "information con- enough straint" over a small here is One absent in H<JiK. advanced to time t — in the e interval regarded as insignificant. The information constraint is unit of consumption at time same event for f > t in an event however small, since A E A may may 7t not be not be a distin- guishable event in Tt-e and doing so will violate the information constraint that consumption On patterns be eidapted to F. the other hand, one unit of consumption at time can always be delayed to any time A. A > t event. Moreover, one unit of consumption Appendix following proposition formalizes these discussions, whose proof is contained in definition is Definition 5 Let needed. T and S be two optional times. The stochastic interval {T,S] {{u/,t) Let same in the advanced to an instant before by the nature of a surprise. at a "surprise" cannot be The s T< 5 an event in t be two optional times. : It is T(w) < known t < is the set S{uj)}. E that [T, S] and thus the process x{<^,t) =X[T.l]{<^,t), denoting a consumption pattern that provides for one unit of consumption at time T, and therefore adapted Proposition 5 Let an optional time for P{T = T an optional time. be Fix k > all n. 1} = Then kx\T,i\ all = and X kxiT+i.,1] is <^+ /"'' <ill = i'„ = >: as x„ for n and only if T all n implies y T+ predictable — and {Tn} x\\^ is — > as n — » >: x. On Tn < T, and on the kx[T„,i], is and ^ is also — CO. a sequence of optional times with ||i'„ if > kx\T,i]- Tn < T„+i < T. Putting k Then 0. n implies x > y and y hand, suppose that {Tn} ^ and put PX[r+i,il - *:Xir,i]L -* Thus x„ y y for optional (to F). Xn Suppose that is oo an announcing sequence. set the other {T > 0} 4 Topological and uniform properties of 7^ Proof. See Appendix A. 17 I Proposition 5 states that delaying the consumption of k units, even for large k, for a small period of time will be regarded insignificant by an agent with preference relation continuous in T^. However, advancing consumption over a small interval from an optional time to an earlier optional that is, time is regarded insignificant and only if if the optional time is predictable; consumptions at a random time and at random times instants before are almost perfect substitutes if and only instants before. It is there if no is left discontinuity of information at those worthwhile perhaps to any deterministic time recall that is random times predictable and thus consumptions at nearly adjacent deterministic times are always almost perfect substitutes! Discontinuity of information can only occur at Poisson process jumps Remark is an optional time except when With the T T T+ - is aid of Proposition 5, caveat. Under T— is, - we now show is Tn =T— time a is in general not ^. in the following proposition that the set of dense in certainty, one unit of if '^. This is the counterpart of a result consumption at time approximated arbitrarily closely by consuming at an average rate "around" X[i/2,il first deterministic. Thus an announcing sequence of a predictable is in general cannot he constructed by putting H<kK with one T an optional time whenever absolutely continuous consumption patterns in For example, the times. a surprise that happens at a random time. 4 Note that although optional time random t (. E (0, 1) can be For example, can be approximated arbitrarily closely by three sequences, -nit) = -(^-^ + ^)X|l-^,i.^,(0 + X(i,^„(0, (8) x4t) = n((-^ + (9) -n{t) = ^)x(i_i,ij{0 n(t-i)X|i,i + i](0 + + X(i,i](0. X(i + i,i|(0- (10) = The sequences above shift average rate. They all converge to consuming one unit at time 1/2 in any of the From Proposition 5, however, we know that consumption at nonpredictable optional times consumption around, before, and cannot be approximated by earlier consumption. Consumption at approximated by delayed consumption except at the time and creates no problem. This observation proof is contained in Appendix A. after is final date t t 1/2, respectively, at an H&K topologies. all times can nevertheless be = I, which is not a random formalized in the following proposition, whose Topological and uniform properties of T^ 4 Proposition 6 The 18 set of absolutely continuous consumption patterns in i'^ is dense with respect to the topology Tp. Proposition 5 also suggests a more general measure of "shifts" of consumption in the spirit of the Prohorov metric used by H<kK. € f^ and Let x,y = inf{e> pA^'V) The e define a Prohorov metric path-by-path: 0:i(t neighborhood of a path around x{uj, distance •) that is x{uj, f.w) + e > y{t,u) any other path •) is x{ijj,-) is within The of the total consumption under y at f idea here sizable shifts of less than pattern e in is that p^{x,y) if is t left say K , Hence in state uj, the c if y(w, •) ( within is a e totd consumption under some time no more than e away from t. across states of nature, then 5 implies that as we can allow p^[x,y) As it interval G £^ with — earlier to be large on a set of small probability. a sequence of consumption patterns (i„) 7 Let x,Xn f > 0, the e time since turns out, Puj[^,y) being uniformly small is counter example can be constructed along the lines of Example Proposition [0,1]}. and down and to the right any y that advances consumption to will not contain a.s. for > € width. Such shifts should not drastically change an agent's utility for the original too strong, and — e,u) -e,Vf that lives entirely within a "sleeve" uniformly smaller than that will violate the information constraint. A •) At nonpredictable times, however, Proposition x. Pu{xn,x) t/(w, - consumption at predictable optional times can only occur across a time neighborhood of x is x{t at every point {t,x{uj,t)). of x(a;,-) in the Prohorov sense, then at every time X > determined by moving up and to the each direction) from e in + too weak for \\xn (Note that - i||^ — » 0. 1.) the property that there exists an T -measurable function, such that ^ Pu.(in,x)<— and P-as. Y.\'p[K)\<oo. n Then \\xn — x\\p — > x. implies that y Proof. > as n — > See Appendix A. oo. Thus in ^ y for all n implies that x > y and y > Xn for all n I This proposition concludes our investigation into how continuous preferences behave with respect to "shifts" of consumption. shows the fact that (if', T^) Proposition 8 {S'^,Tp) is is With the aid of Proposition 7, the following proposition not a topological vector not a topological vector lattice. lattice. Topological and uniform properties of T^ 4 Proof. The sequence Proposition now Third, we consumption of sure consumption patterns Xli/2,1] But the 7. 19 converges to zero by X\{n+i)/2n,i\ positive part (or the negative part) obviously does not. consider how our topologies perform shifted over a decreasingly smaller is ~ amount being long as the increjisingly larger <p, amount amount increasingly larger of of time. Intuition suggests that as shifted goes to infinity slowly enough, the shift should be regarded as negligible. The meeisure of infinity is naturally related to when an I how slowly the amount of a shift increeises to the state-by-state inverse of which meeisures the same thing corresponding economy under certainty. in a We first put = /I <p~^, the inverse of ip state-by-state. and with n[uj,0) strictly increasing, continuous, concave, proposition essentially shows that if the amount = is eaisily It and ^(u;,oo) seen that ^l{u),) = The 00. is following shifted increases to infinity slower than /i grows to infinity state by state except possibly on a set of small probability, then the shift will be negligible. = Proposition 9 Let n and {yn(w, {x„{(jj, 1)} (p~^ and let {x„} and and 1)} are both o(/i(a;,n)) Pu{Xn,yn) < where n — K[ijj) is an 7 -measurable n be two sequences in f^ Suppose that . satisfy p-a.S., function such that E[^(ii')] < 00. Then - ||x„ y„||i^ —* as 00. Proof. See Appendix A. I The sequences {xn} and hope {«/„} in when > ^ Proposition 9 are both divergent and thus we could not for the validity of statements such as I* I* {t/n} 0, is example of a — and strict VnWip i„ for n sufficiently large >- j/„, (11) continuous and strictly monotonically increasing in the direction of i* G £^ with where W^n + >- is the strict preference relation derived from >. linear preference relation that violates (11). — as n » —+ 00, I* monotonicity of However, (11) is Definition 6 (Mas >: + 1„ - t/n may to conclude that lie outside of In The reason Appendix B we for this f^ and we cannot i'+i„-y„ y for large is give an that although use the continuity n and thus i' + i„ > y„. a property of uniformly proper preferences defined formally below: Colell (1986)) Preferences respect to T^ in the direction x' G f^ with the origin such that, for every x E f^, v x' eV , > on (f^ are said to be ^ if there exists a and scalar a > 0, x uniformly proper with T^ open neighborhood - ax' + av "^ x. V of 5 Duality 20 The uniform properness comes from the that X fact that x' — ax' + av >: i is a form of strong monotonicity. is V and The uniform must be chosen independently of allowed to fail x. part of properness important to note It is by virtue of the fact that x — ax' + av ^ £^ . Mas (See Colell (1986) for further details.) Proposition 10 Let the sequences {in} uniformly proper in the direction x' x' Proof. Rather than mimicking + Xn + 1„ — y„ is strictly preferred that x' + Xn > j/n for large n. if >: 1« Vn is we use a different argument. it !„ - t/„ + is 5 Duality lies inside this open it is a uniform property. for On an open ^ be the price at time be represented in the set con- continuous preferences. Since continuous preferences on an like Arrow-Debreu sort, equilibrium prices linear functionals continuous in the topology with respect to the topological dual spaced Let i/'(i) is and follows it come which agents' preferences are assumed to be continuous. This space of continuous linear functionals Then set satisfy (11). In standard general equilibrium theory of the from the space of Richard not a topological property of continuous preferences - there becomes a topological property f^, they is can be extended to an open extended preferences by continuity. Then for the continuous and uniformly proper preferences on S+ behave set containing Suppose that > OO. uniformly proper, exists continuous preferences that violate (11); open 9. I In the positive orthant, (11) taining S'^, however, (11) " ~* 9, for large n, i* to I* >- the proof of H<kK, By Proposition f^. {Vn} ^c as in Proposition Then . and Zame (1986) have shown that set containing <"*<' is called a continuous linear functional that gives equilibrium prices. of the consumption claim i. We will find out soon that \p can form ^{x)=-E\r f{t)dx{t) iGf^, Uowhere, roughly, / is a process that is decomposable into two parts: a process having absolutely continuous sample path and a martingale. one unit of consumption at time ^More is its formally, (f", T^) topological dual. ie t in state We tv. interpret f{oj,t) to be the time shadow price of Since a martingale can have discontinuities only a topological linear space and the space of continuous linear functionals on (£'*', T^) 5 Duality 21 at nonpredictable optional times (see consumption at nearly adjacent at surprises. It is known that a continuous martingale sumption can fluctuate widely structure time is is VI. 14)), we thus conclude that (random) dates have almost the same shadow prices except Thus when information variation. Meyer (1966, Theorem is either a constant or of revealed continuously throughout, a nondifiFerentiable in is shadow In particular, faishion. if unbounded prices for con- the information generated by a Brownian motion, the shadow price process for consumption over an Ito process. We now proceed to characterize the topological dual of (f *', T^), denoted by f '^ . We shall make use of the concept of complementary generalized Orlicz spaces for most of our analysis here. We provide some definitions. Definition 7 A function • lim^^o+ ^^^ = • limi_oo ^^''^ Remark 5 <p By = ^ E N -function € n. (p an Vcj convexity, for N -function, we can write v{uj,s) is the right-hand derivative of ip{uj,s) for a fixed Definition 8 Let v'{uj,a) = (p E ^ an be < sup{s: v{uj,s) if the following conditions hold: e Q; and V'^ oo said to be an is ct}, N -function, and (p{u;,\x\) = Jq v[(jj,s)ds, where uj. let v{uj,s) be as in the above remark. Let then <p*{oj,x)= v'{ui,a)da / Jo is said to be complementary to mentary to L'^ , Example 1. The generalized Orlicz space L'^ is then said to be comple- recall the definition of a generalized Orlicz space in (4). 2 (1) If<p{u;,x) (2) If'p{u;,x) The where we <p. = \x\''^''\l =e' -x-1, < p(a;) then 'p{uj,y) = < (1 oo, then <p'{uj,y) + y)/n(l + y) - = |y|«("), where :^ + ^= y. following proposition describes T^-continuous linear functionals on the space f'' in terms of elements of L'^ . Duality 5 22 Proposition 11 Let ip C^ : —* yt is <p G ^ N -function an be and with complementary function a and only a T^-continuou8 linear functional if f f with absolutely continuous sample paths, and with f 9{t)dx[t) & L'^ if , (p' Then . there exists an adapted process so that Vi€(f'^, (12) Jo- = where g[t) + f{t) rn(t), and m(0=E[-/'(l)-/(l)|7,] is a martingale, or equivalently, g[t) may continuous paths but Proof. An = /(() — — /'(I) VtG[0,l] /(I), which (13) is not be adapted. See Appendix A. I important special case of Proposition 11 when is <p{uj,z) = \z\'' case when p = The following proposition gives the duality result for this 1/ family, 1 is a process with absolutely not covered in Proposition 11, however, since with is |2;| 1 < p < not an whose proof oo. The A^ function. is left for the reader. Proposition 12 Let Then tp : 6'^ — (p{(xi,z) = \z\^, for alluj, with <p < 1 oo. Let q be a T^-continuous linear functional if 5R ts and only such that l/p+l/q if there exists = 1. an adapted process f with absolutely continuous sample paths so that rP{x) =E ViGf^, y^' g{t)dx{t) (14) where if'j'il)) g{t) = f{t) + e L'(n X [0,ll,O,P X E[-/'(l)-/(l)|J,l a martingale, or equivalently, g{t) continuous paths but Note that that are sums in the is ip is = f{t) - /'(I) - V<€[0,1] /(I); which (15) is a process with absolutely not necessarily adapted. above proposition, when p = 1, the dual space of processes with Lipschitz continuous paths and Another important when L'(n,7,F), m{t), and m(0 = is A) X ceise of the function sisymptotically linear, in that for (p which some a; is is composed of processes bounded martingales. not covered in the above propositions G n, we have limi_oo ~^ = a > 0. is In the Duality 5 23 HiiK have shown that case of certainty, Lipschitz continuous functions. We the space of shadow prices in this case is the space of obtain a similar characterization for the case of uncertainty under the assumption that the function "integrably asymptotically linear." This result ip is is recorded in the following proposition. Proposition 13 Ltl there exists a the function random K, variable ip with the property that E[v?(/if)] (p{oj,x) < ax + In this case, we have the equivalence £'^ and T are the consum.ption space, and = £ , € yx> and T^ Proof. In See Appendix A. H&K, and < is the same C^ is T as where we , the is = |i| sum recall that t for all bounded martingale. I is represented by a process of an absolutely continuous process and a martingale. A It is known nearly random adjacent dates F is 7; that is, structure AE revealed if then follows that prices for consumptions at when P{A\Tt) = is Thus when F prices of consumption is continuous is if and only if all An there are no "surprises." E[x/i|/t] is information a continuous process for the posterior probability of any event evolves continuously. (1985a). a martingale It are almost equal said to be continuous information structure if is that the martingale can have a discontinuity only at nonpredictable optional times; see, example, Meyer (1966, Theorem VI. 14) for E n. of a process with sample path properties of a martingale are determined by the way information over time: u) a continuous linear functional can be represented essentially by an absolutely sum the 0, (16) continuous function. Here, however, a continuous linear functional that > oo, such that the topology constructed using <p{x) a e K{(jj) a.s. In particular, this shows that an element of the dual space to Lipschitz continuous sample paths any be integrably asymptotically linear, in that for It is all known that an optional times are predictable; see Huang continuous, the dual of f*' consists only of continuous processes and at nearly adjacent random dates continuous on a stocheistic interval, variation there (Fisk (1965)). are almost equal. it is It is also either a constant or of Hence there are cases where prices for known that unbounded consumption at nearly adjacent dates are almost equal but fluctuate widely in a nowhere diff"erentiable fashion. This comes about because of uncertainty. When there prices for is no uncertainty, the martingale part of the consumption disappears and prices degenerate to absolutely continuous functions of time. An important special case of continuous information structure Brownian motion. is is when F is generated by a In this case, the dual space only contains Ito processes. This characterization given in the following proposition: 5 Duality 24 Proposition 14 Let F be generated by a Brownian motion and the dual spaces characterized in Propositions 11, 12 g{t)= where f is to time, where f* Jo and is a IS, then g is an ltd process: Jo Brownian motion and where I g be an element of any of f'{s)dB+ f9{sfdw{8), a process with absolutely continuous paths w let \9{t)f dt and denotes /' 9 is adapted to < oo F derivative with respect its and satisfies: a.s. Jo Proof. From Propositions 11, 12, and 13, absolutely continuous process and rn{t) fact that a martingale is we know An example The a martingale. adapted to a Brownian motion an Ito integral (see Clark (1970, Theorems 3 and process jumps. That a discontinuity only at a "surprise" which occurs we Before general ples. fail The we show below leave this section, when is Q— {wi,W2} o^rid We the filtration be {n,0} j ^'-\ Assume ceise, is a martingale shadow obtained by may have a price process can have the Poisson process jumps. demonstrate this by showing two exam- example uses a very specialized information structure, while the second 3 Let an can always be represented as when information the is, context of a Brownian motion information structure, which Example is that the dual spaces characterized above in to be sub-lattices of their order duals. first m{t), where / I 4)). observing the realizations of a simple Poisson process. In this when the Poisson + f{t) assertion then follows from the filtration of a discontinuous information structure discontinuity only = that g{t) {{a;i},{a;2},n,0} is is in the the case of prevalent applications. composed of vte VtG [0,1/2), [1/2,1]. that each of the two possible states has a strictly positive probability of occurrence. Define two processes with absolutely continuous sample paths as follows: Vwen /i(<^,t) 4((-l/2) -4{t-l/2) 1 -1 t/a; te [0,1/2) = wiVtG [i Vw G 2t 5), ./a;=a;2Vte[|,|), t/a; = wiVtG[|,l], t/w =a;2Vt G [f,l]. f2{u,t) ^ [ I l-4(t-l/2) 1 fi t G [0, 1/2) i/a;=a;iVtG[i,l], j/w = a;2Vt G [i,l]. Note that -/(.,.)-/!«.,.)={-' ;^:::;; -/,k.)-/;k.)={a :^:=:;: 25 Duality 5 = verified that gi{t) It is easily fi{t) Propositions 11, 12, and IS for i = — E[/,(l) + /,'(l)|/tl '»«« "» the dual spaces characterized in Note that the order dual of C^ 1,2. processes g that are measurable with respect to T® is composed of positive B{[0,1]) so that the integral •1 E / 9it)dx{t) .Jois well-defined for x that is, dual of < gi f^ E C^ < g2 ifgi{'^,t) as The order generated by . From Proposition g2{u),t) a.e. 11, this example, we can think of g,{uj,t) the pointwise minimum of gi = fi{u,t) and - 3, as - fi{i^,l) f'ii^A)- g^ is -1 t/w 4(t-l/2)-l ifuj -\+2t ifu t/w A?2(w, ?l(w, t/u; On [0, the interval must 1) we can think of the topological composed of processes not necessarily adapted but with absolutely continuous sample paths. In Then the order dual is then the pointwise order; [0, j), gi A be a constant, ^2 'i'** impossible to write gi it is absolutely continuous paths different derivatives along and a martingale A and thus 52 it = a;i tG [0 i), = uxte\\,\), = uite\\,\], = W2 «G [0, i), = a;2 te[|,l]. wi and ^^s a sum ui^- Since a martingale on of an adapted process with cannot be an element of the topological dual of S'^. The next example Example 4 is in the context of a filtration. Let the filtration be a Brownian motion filtration. that the dual contains only Ito processes. is a Brownian motion generalized ltd process in that it It is can be well known that the From Proposition I4 we know minimum of two Ito processes decomposed into two parts: a continuous process with bounded variation sample paths and an Ito integral (see Harrison (1985),^6). taking the pointwise may have minimum That is, by of two Ito processes, one creates a process whose time trend part a singular component. Thus the space of Ito processes is not a lattice. We note, in contrast, that the space of generalized Ito processed is indeed a lattice. A generalized Ito process is a continuous process with bounded variation sample patlis plus an Ito integral. , Comparison with standard models 6 26 Comparison with standard models 6 In this section we will see how the standard models fare in the context of our current model. Using a standard model, one assumes that an agent maximizes his exp>ected utility of the following form U{x) for absolutely tion. -E\f\{x'{t),t)dt\, continuous consumption pattern, where u{z,t) (17) is a time-additive "felicity" func- This model does not permit gulps of consumption. This creates no major problem. Recall from Prop)osition 6 that the We = set of absolutely continuous can therefore follow HA:K consumption patterns is dense in f ^. the expected utility of a consumption pattern involv- in defining ing gulps to be the limit of the expected utilities of a sequence of approximating absolutely continuous consumption patterns. The above procedure what in follows that Our proof linear. and the fact that a ;9 : : f^ — [0, 1] -» 5R is !R jointly continuous then is nonrandom consumption u{z,t) : 3f+ x [0,1] continuous in T^ only such that u{z,t) Proof. See Appendix The converse HiiK identical to that of Proposition 15 Let U u{z,t) if is work provided that U{x) will A. = a{t)z in 9? > U{x) ceise is T;^ We show, however, continuous only if u[z, t) is of certainty by using Proposition 7 6e jointly continuous. if there exists + 7^-continuous. certainly feasible in a world of uncertainty. is — the is The continuous functions a utility : [0, l] function — » !R and l3{t). I of the above proposition is a direct application of the duality results in Sec- tion 5. Proposition 16 Let where oc'{t) is is sition 11. a. a{t)z + 0{t). Then U of (17) is continuous in T^ if a' e L'^' that 1/(1):= U = the derivative of a(t). Proof. Observe Thus u{z,t) e[/" a{t)x'{t)dt + I 0[t)dt linear functional plus a constant. =Ef/" Then the a{t)dx{t)+ f ^{t)dt . assertion follows directly from Propo- I The above analysis reveals that the standard representation of utility as the expectation of the integral of felicity of current consumption fails (except in a very special case) to produce 6 Compeirison with standard models 27 The problem preferences continuous in our topologies. is that the additive form of how current consumption implies that consumption at an earlier date, no matter has no effect on current This satisfeiction. recent it is, with our concept of preference in direct conflict is felicity of continuity in which consumptions at nearby dates are close substitutes if there is no discontinuity of information. The standard model also fails to capture our economic intuition we deal with the single perishable consumption good case that of durable goods. One could purchaise of durable good in situations different here. Take from example the case for interpret the consumption plan x{t) as the level of accumulated up to time only a few times over the horizon t. A durable [0, 1]. good is most often acquired in single units, and However, the owner of the good receives a continuous flow of services from the earlier acquired durable goods. His level of satisfaction from owning the good at any time should reflect his enjoyment from the services provided by the good, in spite of the fact that the We would like to the standard model, topologies. good was purchased in the past. propose an alternative representation of is mathematically tractable, and gives To achieve this objective, standard model. However, the but also on consumption we rise to preferences will express utility as felicity at time Our construction goes in the "recent past." u>, which is differentiable in bounded over u. An example of such a process e{u;,t) Now using the process 6, in our felicity as in the depends not only on consumption t t, is and whose is first spirit of continuous an integral of a consumption plan. Consider an adapted process 6{uj,t), which the states of nature which keeps the utility, at (, as follows; let x(w,t) be uniformly bounded across derivatives are uniformly the Gauss-kernel given by: ^^e^. = time (18) construct from x another process i which gives a path-by-path weighted average of recent past consumption. In other words, put x{ui,t)=[ 0{oj,s)dx{tThe new process x will model. Let u{x,t) be a X. s). (19) be the element over which preferences are expressed using the standard felicity function which is state-independent, continuous and concave in Let U{x) = E[/ u{x,t)dt]. (20) Jo The fact that our topologies under these conditions, the is utility function given in (20) is recorded in the following proposition. continuous in any of 7 and general equilibrium Issues related to arbitrage Proposition 17 Let the averaging process 6 and 28 the felicity function u satisfy the conditions described above. Let U{x) be constructed as in (SO). Preferences represented by in U are continuous any T^. Proof. See Appendix A It is I important to point out that many authors have attempted to capture the effects of the time complementarity of consumption using functional forms that appear to be similar to It (20). turns out, however, that there is a crucial difference. In our proposed representation of utilities, the felicity function u depends only on the "smoothed" consumption process x and time. In contrast, most "non time-additive" formulations in the literature posit a felicity function, say v, which takes as arguments the current consumption "rate" x'{t) together with the "smoothed" earlier consumption x{i). V{x) = Thus one represents preferences by: -E[l\{x',x,t)dt\. (21) Jo Notable examples of such representations include Bergman (1985), Constantinides (1988), Heaton (1988), and Sundaresan (1988). Inclusion of the "smoothed" recent consumption in the instantaneous utility function v captures the effect of past consumption on one's current satisfaction. However, including current consumption of preferences in the sense We cases. defined in (21) — ?R is and 7 One x v(c, 2, (): !R^ [0, 1] be continuous in T^ only ^: 5R+ x — [0,1] measure such that v{c,z,t) Proof. for in this paper except possibly for uninteresting special record this fact in the following proposition. Proposition 18 Let [0,1] we argue in the felicity function destroys the continuity See Appendix A. — !R, » a{z, t)c and + jointly continuous. if there exists jointly a subset ^{z, t) for all z of ^+ G A. utility function V^: £^ — » 9? continuous functions a: 9?+ x with a strictly positive Lebesgue I Issues related to arbitrage of the central topics in A The modern and general equilibrium financial theories concerns properties of security prices there are no arbitrage opportunities. Using a similar when commodity space and a Mackey topology generated by the space of bounded and continuous processes and barring arbitrage opportunities, Huang (1985b) has shown optional times when there are no that security prices over time are continuous at predictable lump-sum dividends. In particular, price processes will be and general equilibrium Issues related to arbitrage 7 29 lump-sum ex-dividend dates generalized Ito processes between if the information structure is generated by a Brownian motion. However, requiring the dual space of the commodity space to have only continuous processes a bit too strong. is implies that consumption at nearly It adjacent dates are almost perfect substitutes even at times of surprise. norm economically more reaisonable all Huang (1985b) the results of N in the following which are available securities eiccumulated dividend process i„ G time is, there 1 is is zero. Assume that trading strategy 6 is we assume in [0, 1]. Security There separable. is n is denoted by that Xn(0) = n and Sn(l) for all = and the ex-dividend price of a security its 0; at an A'^-dimensional process that prescribes the portfolio Without getting strategy for the traded securities. (if^,T^) Let 5„ denote the ex-dividend price process for security S'^. no accumulated dividend at time A get essentially manner. any time for trading n. Since securities are traded ex-dividends, that we topologies discussed in previous sections, Take the commodity space to be (f',T^)are Using the family of into technical details, we shall only allow agents to use simple trading strategies - strategies that are adapted, bounded, left-continuous, marketed if non-random time m{t)-m{O) = 0{OyS{O)+ [ 9{sydS{s)+[ there is at a finite by-path; alternatively, consumption patterns. is points.^ shall say E f '^ is we x{t) say that It is — {xi{t),. m is clear that a simple free lunch if . . ,Xf^{t))^ financed by M is 6. a linear ^(0)^5(0) < , and the integrals are defined path- M denote the space of marketed subspace oi An element m G M Let S'^. m£ 0, ^(s)^di(s), (f^, and m^ 0. Barring simple free M has a unique price at time m(0) + ^(0)^5(0), where we can define a linear functional on M by 7r(m) = m(0) 6[0)^m{0). lunches, each m a strategy $ so that where ^ denotes "transpose," financed by ^ number of and change their values mE 0, 9 finances m, and 4- Now we shall show that the market does not admit {(m„, Xn) € MX <f *'; n linear functional free lunches, = 1,2, . . .} m„ - tt has a nice representation a concept due to Kreps (1981). and a bundle i„ e S^ Vn, /: € f + with k ||x„ - < 0. ^ A free if lunch the securities is a sequence such that k\\^ -> 0, and liminf„7r(m„) To consider more general than simple strategies, we will first need to discuss how general stochastic which we do not want to do here. Interested readers should consult Huang (1985b) for a strategies intergals are defined, discussion in a context similar to our setup here. , 7 Issues related to arbitrage and general equilibrium Suppose that there are no there exists an extension of r to and X ^ Let tp, , that and Huang (1986) shows that of Duffie strictly positive in that ip{x) is > if x G £^ 0. (p some oi S'^ all satisfy conditions of Propositions 11, 12, or 13, then =E V-Cx) for Theorem A.l free lunches. 30 strictly positive process g, ViGf-^, [1^' 9{t)dx{t) which the is sum of a martingale and a process of absolutely continuous sample paths. Let Sm{t) be the ex-dividend price at time from Proposition 5.1 of Huang (1985b) E Note that the first S^ predictable optional times m if m is € M. in is a martingale and thus the properties suppose that In particular, be continuous at between discontinuities of m, Sm also continuous there and, is S^ must For example, a natural way. F is generated by a an absolutely continuous process. Since a martingale then can be continuous process, the numerator of (22) is an implies that Sm is an Ito process. is is The denominator Ito process. plus a process of absolutely continuous paths and thus lemma follows ^''^ represented by an Ito integral and the second term in the numerator of (22) positive, Ito's It m can have discontinuities only at surprises. Brownian motion and m - !^9{s)dm{s) [j^ 9{s)dm{s)\Tt] term of the numerator of (22) of g translate into those of of that = '-^'^ t an Ito process. These are all is an absolutely a martingale Since g is strictly economically appealing properties of price processes for securities over time. As for the existence of an Arrow-Debreu equilibrium space if^ equipped with the topology T^, however, an empty formly proper, among lattice, then an equilibrium proper, there exists an equilibrium; see is Mas a topological vector lattice nor former recall is an economy with a commodity to offer. Since little two ensured Proposition an Arrow-Debreu equilibrium in 8; for its Colell its dual if order dual and is if (f '^, Tp) agents' preferences are uniif, if among other things, the preferences are uniformly and Richard (1987). Unfortunately, neither is the latter see our economy {£^,T^) has possibilities. First, other things; see Meis Colell (1986). Second, topological dual of {S'^, T^) were a sublattice of for the we have interior, existing general equilibrium theories offer were a topological vector (f'^jT^) in a sublattice of Example 3 and its 4. order dual in general; Whether there exists an open question. However, provided that there exists an Arrow-Debreu equilibrium, one can implement the Arrow-Debreu equilibrium by continuously trading a few long-lived securities as in DufTie (1986) 8 Concluding remarks DufiRe and Huang 31 (1985), and Huang (1987) and thus establish the existence of a dynamic equi- librium with dynamically complete markets. In Duffie (1986) and sp£ice is the patterns is Huang commodity (1987), the space of consumption rates and the sense of closeness between two consumption defined by the standard Z/ norm on consumption rates as functions of (w,t). no surprise. at nearly adjacent dates are perfect nonsubstitutes even at times of consumption As a consequence, the shadow properties of prices for consumption over time Thus in a pure ex- change equilibrium depend crucially on the properties of the aggregate endowment process. For example, in the case of a Browni2in motion filtration, the price process for a security with absolutely continuous accumulated dividend process will not be an Ito process unless the aggre- gate since endowment process is. This does not conform with our intuition. In our setup, however, consumption at nearly adjacent dates are almost perfect substitutes prise, price processes of securities no sur- with absolutely continuous accumulated dividends will be Ito processes independently of the properties of the aggregate 8 at times of endowment process. Concluding remarks we have advanced a family In this paper of topologies defining closeness between consumption patterns over time under uncertainty that capture the intuitive idea that consumptions at nearly adjacent dates are almost perfect substitutes we have tried to formalize is if there are no surprises there. certainly not new. Our contribution and, more important, characterizing the topological dual spaces. topologies is is We The intuitive idea topologizing this idea feel that our choice of the natural one that conceptualizes the aforementioned idea for the following two reaisons. First, in the degenerate ccise where the true state of nature is revealed at time 0, we reach the conclusion that the shadow prices of consumption are absolutely continuous functions. Hence, preferences continuous in our topologies give rise to equilibrium prices in which the price of consumption at adjacent dates are almost equal and in which prices change smoothly in a differentiable manner. We believe that this is an intuitively attractive result. Second, in the nondegenerate case, the topological duals are the natural generalizations of those under certainty. In this case, prices are processes that can be decomposed as the sum of two components: a process of absolutely continuous sample path and a martingale. In the case of uncertainty a new element, properties of equilibrium prices. price process. It is Thus equilibrium the pattern of information flow, affects the sample path This effect is captured in the martingale component of the known that a martingale can make discontinuous changes only prices for at surprises. consumption are continuous except possibly at surprises. This is 9 References 32 also an intuitively appealing result which holds independently of the nature of the endowment process. The proposed family properties ical known of natural topologies, however, does not give rise to certain to be sufficient for the existence of an mathemat- Arrow-Debreu equilibrium. The resolution of this issue should be of high priority. References 9 1. K. Arrow and M. Kurz, Public Investment, the Rate of Return, and Optimal Fiscal Policy, Johns Hopkins Press, Baltimore, 1970. 2. Y. Bergman, Time Preferences and Capital Asset Pricing Model, Journal of Financial Ekonomics, Volume 14, No.l, 1985. 3. P. Billingsley, Convergence of Probability Measures, John Wiley and Sons, Inc., New York, 1968. 4. G. Constantinides, Habit Formation: A Resolution of the Equity Premium Puzzle, mimeo. University of Chicago, 1988. 5. K. Chung and R. Williams, An Introduction to Stochastic Integration, Birhkauser Boston Inc., 1983. 6. J. Clark, The Representation Annals of Mathematical 7. of Functionals of Brownian Motion by Stochastic IntegraJs, Statistics, 41, 1970, pp. 1282-1295. G. Debreu, Representation of a Preference Ordering by a Numerical Function, In Decision Processes. Edited by R. Thrall, C. Coombs, and R. Davis. John Wiley & Sons, New York, 1954. 8. C. Delleicherie and P. Meyer, Probabilities and Potential A: General Theory, North Hol- land Publishing Company, 9. New C. Dellacherie and P. Meyer, Probabilities and Potential B: Theory of Martingales, North Holland Publishing Company, 10. York, 1978. New York, 1982. D. Duffie, Stochastic Equilibria: Existence, Spanning Number, and the "No Expected Gain from Trade" Hypothesis, Econometrica 54, 1986, pp. 1161-1184. 9 References 11. 33 D. Duffie and C. Huang, 1985. Implementing Arrow-Debreu Equilibria by Continuous Trading of Few Long-lived Securities, EA:onometric& 53, 1985, pp. 1337-1356. 12. D. Duffie and C. Huang, Multiperiod Security Markets with Differential Information: Martingales and Resolution Times, Journiil of Matbem&tic&l Ek:ononiics 15, 1986, pp. 283303. 13. D. Fisk, Quasi-martingales, Tr&ns. Amer. Math. Soc. 120, 1965, pp. 369-389. 14. M. Harrison. 1985, Brownian Motion and Stochastic Flow Systems, John Wiley Inc., 15. J. Sons York, 1985. Heaton, The Interaction between Time-nonseparable Preferences and Time Aggrega- tion, 16. C. New &c mimeo. University of Chicago, 1988. Huang, Information Structure and Equilibrium Asset Prices, Journal of Economic Theory 35, 1985a, pp. 33-71. 17. C. Huang, Information Structures and Viable Price Systems, Journal of Mathematical Economics 14, 1985b, pp. 215-240. 18. C. Huang, An Intertemporal General Equilibrium Asset Pricing Model: The Case of Diffusion Information. Econometrica 55, 1987, pp. 117-142. 19. C. I: 20. L. Huang and D. Kreps, On Intertemporal The Case of Certainty, MIT mimeo, Preferences with a Continuous Time Dimension 1987. Kantorovich and G. Akilov, Functional Analysis, Pergamon Press, 1982. 21. D. Kreps, Arbitrage and Equilibrium Journal of Mathematical Economics 22. A. Mcis Colell, The in Economies with Infinitely Many Commodities, 8, 1981, 15-35. Price Equilibrium Existence Problem in Topological Vector Lattices, Econometrica 54, 1986, pp. 1039-1053. 23. A. Mas Colell Lattices, and S. Richard, A New Approach to the Existence of Equilibrium in Vector Harvard University mimeo, 1987. 24. P. Meyer, Probabj/ity and Potentiais, Ginn 25. P. Meyer, Decomposition of Supermartingales: The Uniqueness Theorem, of Mathematics, 7, 1963, pp. 1-17. (Blaisdell), Boston, 1966. Illinois Journal 9 References 34 26. J. Musielak, Orlicz Sp&ces and Modular Spaces, Lecture Notes in Mathematics, Springer- Verlag No. 1034, 1983. 27. S. Richard and W. Zame, Proper Preferences and Quasiconcave Utility Functions, Journal of Mathematical Economics 15, 1986, pp. 231-247. 28. H. Schaefer, Topological Vector Spaces, Springer- Verlag, 29. D. Strook, An New York, 1980. Introduction to Integration Theory for Analysts, unpublished class notes, M.I.T., 1987. 30. S. Sundaresan, Portfolio Choice with Intertemporally Dependent Preferences. tions for Consumption Smoothing and Asset of Financial Studies. Volatility, 1988, forthcoming in the Implica- Review Appendix A Proofs Appendix 35 A Proofs PROOF OF Proposition Proof. without Let i' i: > i. be elements of £*' and let / denote the order interval [i,,i*]. Assume = 0, since our topologies are linear. We will show that / is and closed and therefore compact; see Schaefer (1980, p. 25). loss of generality that i. bounded To show that / is totally bounded it suffices to show that number of elements of /, {i„; n = 1,2,..., A^(e)} such that totedly for any e > there exists a finite n=l where O^ is a T^-neighborhood of i, with we know • diameter ||^ || less than e. Fix > e From 0. N[€) > such that Pu{^,y) ^ 2;*(a;, 1)/A''(f) implies there exists Proposition 7, ~ Construct N[e) processes with right-continuous, nonnegative, y||^ < f/2 for x,y G C^ ll^^ and nondecreasing sample paths in the following fashion. For each state uj, begin first by building a Prohorov sleeve around i'(w,-) with Prohorov distance x'{ijj,\)/N{e). Let ii(a;,-) be the function prescribed by the lower boundary of that sleeve. Formally, let . ii(a;,( + = i*(a;, 1)/A^(e)) max{i*(a;,«) where we have used the convention that x'(w, = t) - i*(w, \)/N{e),Q} if < < 0. Vt G 5R, Next we define !„ recursively as follows: i„+i(w,t + = i*(w,l)/7V(e)) max{i„(a;,0 - x'{uj,\)/N[t),0) Vt e 3t. Note better that the processes i„ constructed may not be adapted. By construction, p^^{xn,in+i] < i*(w,l)/iV(e) and thus ||i„ - i„+i||^ < e/2 V n = 1,2,. ..,N{t) - 1. Suppose for the time being that the processes i„ are adapted. Let Ol„ It is = {zef^:||i-i„||^<e/2}. then clear that N(e) n=l and thus / is totally bounded. Now if i„ are not adapted, pick any element x„ £ 0\ and put 0',^^{xeEt:\\x-x^\\^<e), we claim that 0% C 0\ . 11^ ~" To see this, let i ^"llv — II''' ~ G Ol ^nllv ' . I!'''" Then ~ if. ^nllip '^ o 9 ^ ^' We thus conclude that / is totally bounded. Next we want to show that 7 is closed. Let x„ G I and ||in - x\\^ — as n — oo X G f^. Then there exists a subsequence of (i„) that converges P x A-a.e. to x. The X G I follows from arguments similar to those in the proof of Proposition 1 of H(5iK. by triangle inequality. » > for some fact that I Appendix A Proofs 36 Proof of Proposition Proof. First, we show 5: that ^X[T,il ^ ^ C^ for all optional 'P{')kX\T,i]{t))dt time T and all Jt > 0. Note that <Y.\^[lk)\ <c», where the first inequality follows from the faict that ip is strictly increasing and the second inequality follows from the hypothesis that (p is integrable. T + Second, the fact that is ^ an optional time whenever T is can be seen by directly checking the definition; [uen-.T + - <t) = {ujen-.T <t- -)e n Third, the hypothesis that lim n—•oo E /^ 'p{iKx[T.i]{t) n f is 7._x c 7t>ite [0,1]. r^ integrable and Lebesgue convergence theorem imply that = E - X[T+i,i](0))^ = E J^ ^(7*Jim(xiT.il(0-X|T+i,il(0))<^' =0. where the second and the third equalities follow from the fact that 'p{uj^ z) is continuous in z and is zero at z = 0, respectively. Thus, by the continuity of >:, i„ >: y for all n implies x > y and y > Xn for all n implies that y > x. Fourth, suppose that {T„} is a sequence of optional times with Tn < T, and T^ < T and This implies that Tn < Tn+i on the set {T > 0} and that fcx[T„,i] ~* ^X|T,il m lim n—>oo E 7 > 0. This implies that subsequence {T„^} such that for all I filHxiTAlit) - kx[T„,l] ~* ^XfT.il in /* nji^oo^l^-.'^l^'^''^ which implies that Tn^ The proof — T a.s. Proof. The proof ~ and thus for the last cissertion Proof of Proposition X[T„.l]{t)))dt is X[T,i](<^,0 T is oo x A-measure, and hence there exists a = P X A - a.e., predictable. just the reverse of the above paragraph. I 6: of Proposition 3 essentially implies that the set of right-continuous, and bounded processes that change their values at a finite number of optional times is dense in (f'^.T^). It then suffices to show that one unit of consumption at an optional time can be approximated arbitrarily closely by a sequence of absolutely consumption patterns. We will show here that consumption at a predictable time can be approximated by consuming at "rate" instants before. The rest of the proof is left for the reader. Appendix Let that T T > A Proofs 37 be predictable and {T„} be its announcing sequence. Assume without loss of generality a.s. (On the set {T = 0}, we can shift consunnption to the right at rates.) Putting 5„^E[T|JrJ, it can be verified that 5„ know Sn > Tn is an optional time by checking the definition. Since T> T„ a.s., we Define a.s. X{t) = X\T,l]{t) ^n{t) = - Tn ^X[T„,S„l(0+X(S„,l)(0'->n ~ -in t Note that !„ is an absolutely continuous consumption pattern. One can verify that i„ Proof of Proposition Proof. Note again that E I ||i„ - i||^ — » 0, if let and only + <p['l\Xn{t)-x{t)\)dt 1.6). Note that P({p(i„,a:) > For any integer m, > 7: Theorem see Musielak (1983, — N{m) for if any 7 > <p['l\Xn{l)-x{l)\) e[/)(i„, x)] -> 0, then if ^0 -}) as n > ^ be such that P(lp{xn,x) ^ 00. [) < ^, for all n > N{m). Next write: E j for n ^{l\x4t) - x{t)\) dt + v?(7|i„(l) - i(l)l) + '1 '2 ' > N{m), where ^"'" = L, . ^\f\{tMt)-x{t)\)dt + p{'iMi)-x{i)\) ^ ^ ^ \ P{du;), •'{p(»n,l)>^}L-'0 7^" = / , We will show that both \ f\Uxn{t) - x{t)\) dt integrals converge to zero, as + J-rMi) - m (and hence n) x{l)\) — > P{dco). 00. First consider /J"'". Since ^ <p{l\xn{t) - x(f)i) dt< j <p{i{x„{l) + x{t))) dt < <p{l{x„{l) + 1(1))) Vw e n, i in A Appendix Proofs 38 we have <p[i\x„{t)-x{t)\)dt I + <p['j\x„{l)-x{l)\) < 2^(7(i„(l) < 2<p{i{K + — or i(l))) 2x{l))) But since E[^(A')] < oo and x G f^, it then follows that /["'" Lebesgue dominated convergence theorem. Now consider /^'". Note first that for w G {Pui{xn,x) < ^}, we have |i„(l)-x(l)|<- + eis m,n — oo, by <p(i\x„{l)-x{\)\)<J^). Thus ^(7|x„(l)-i(l)|)p(cfo.)<E[^(^)' / Next consider the integral part. For any w G — }, we {p(in,i) < can bound the inside integral by: mm — ^<P\'^\^^'^{^{^-,—)^^n{^-,—)') - min{i(a;, m But since rrj \ ^ for precisely those sample functions p(a;„,i) < max{i(a;,(),i„(u;,()} < ),in(w, m — we i(ai,t H m ) m )}) ' . j have H m and min{i(a;,f),i„(u;,t)} so the summation above is is a:(<^,f m ) m m ) {k-2) - <^. m )-!)) convex, equal to zero at zero and increasing, this — <p\l2_^ , bounded by: m^^ \\ Finally, as y? > \x{uj,—-—)-x{uj, {k-2) 2 ^ m m j in turn is bounded < ^v^(7(3x(w,l) + Therefore, [':p(iMt)-x{t)\)dtP{duj)<-E f C'" < and /^'" — as m,n — » -E m ¥p(7(3i{l) oo, proving our result. + 2)) I v^(7(3i(l) +E ^(^) + 2)) 2)). by: Appendix A 39 Proofs Proof of Proposition 9: Proof. For any ui E Q, and for any 7 Proposition 7, we get: ^(w,7|a:n(w,t) - -^<p{uj,i{Sxn{u;, 1) / > using the 0, y„(a;,t)|) dt + same arguments v?(<^,7|x„(a;, l) - as in the proof of ya(<^, 1)1) Jo IT < n The second term on + 2)) + 2<p{<jj, 7|x„(w, - 1) y„(a;, 1)|). the right-side of the inequality vanishes for any 7, since ir |a:n('^, 1) - yn(w,l)| < —^• < Pu,{Xn,yn) n It then follows from Lebesgue convergence theorem, continuity of the hypothesis that E[v?(if )] < 00 that E The first term vanishes 2y.(7|x„(l)-y„(l)|) ^0 Hence, for any 6 however small, there WnyNs: <p{u), •) — ^[^,0) = 0, and 00. since, i„(u;,l)/M(a;,n) Applying n as 92(0;, 2) in z, to both sides of the thus is A'^^, 7(3i„(w, + 1) 2)//i{a;, n) -> 0. such that: i{ix„{uj,l) + 2) < 8^i{u,n). above relation, and using the shape of <p, for all 5 1, we 00, we < conclude that: K -^¥'c.(7{3xn(w,l) n + 2) K K n n < ^^'p^[8^i[uj,n)) < -^6<p^{^[oj,n)) < K^8 n > NsNoting that by Jensen's inequality, y?(E[ii']) < E[v7(^)] < 00 and since I conclude that ||i„ — yn|L ~* 0, by Lebesgue convergence theorem. for all Proof for Proposition Proof. E[v2(ii^)] < ii: Integration by parts path-by-path gives fP{x) =E 'lo'-9{t)dx{t)] =E =E 'Jlf{t)dx{t) =E '-J^x{t)f'{t)dt-x{l)f '{!)], + Jlm{t)dx{t)] 'f{l)x{l)-j^x{t)f'it)dt + (23) m{l)x{l]] Appendix where A 40 Proofs denotes the derivative of / and we have used the fact that /' E[ /' m{t)dx{t)] = E[ f m{l)dx{t)] = E[m(l)i(l)] (24) Jo- Jo- and Meyer (1982, VI. 57)). Musielak (1983, Corollary 13.14, p. 87) shows that (23) is a linear functional continuous This is the sufficiency part. T^ if f € L'^ in the third equality (see Dellacherie in . Now he a, T^o-continuous linear functional. By the can be extended to be a continuous linear functional on the whole of Hahn-Banach theorem, E'^, of which we recall the definition from (6). Let * denote this extension. We first show that consider the necessity part. Let xp £'*' : t/* * : E'^ —* 5R can be represented in the form: ^{x) for some y E {i„} G L^ is L"^ = Ey\{t)y{t)dt + For this, we . E /^ <p{lMt) - modular x(t)l) dt The sequence {in} € L^ converges E 1^ <p{lMt) - see Musielak (1983, Theorem (25) A consider the notion of modular convergence: first said to converge in ^xeE^ x{l)y{l) in + to x, X{t)\) dt + to x, if for i(l)l) and only some 7 > 0. if ^(7|ln(l) - 1(1)1) Norm 1.6, p. 3). - y?(7|x„(l) norm sequence if for all 7 > 0; convergence of x„ clearly implies modular con- vergence. Musielak (1983, Theorem 13.17, on (p p. 88) shows that (25) is true under the additional restriction that <p{u), Vio > there exists > c such that x) > c for i > iq Vcli G n. Musielak (1983, Theorem 13.15, p. 87), however, shows that this restriction is required to guarantee that a norm continuous linear functional on L'^ is also modular continuous. In our formulation, we do not need this restriction, since we do not deal with the generalized Orlicz space L^. We only consider the subspace E'^, and on this subspace norm convergence and modular convergence are equivalent; Musielak (1983, 5.2.B, p. 18). We therefore conclude that restricting our attention to £"^ allows us to relax the above described condition. The interested reader can eaisily verify this by consulting Musielak (1983, Theorems 13.15 and 13.17). Now define f{u,t) = - f Jo y{uj,s)ds Vte{0,l]ujeQ, which is clearly adapted and path-wise absolutely continuous. Denoting the derivative of f{u), t) with respect to t by f'{uj,t), it is clear that f'{t) = —y{t). Reversing the arguments in deriving (23), we prove the necessity part. I Appendix A Proofs 41 Proof of Proposition Proof. p of £ is , Let then it 13: be integrably asymptotically linear. We will first also an element of t'^. Note the following: IkL = nj^ show that ¥'(ix(OI)X{|x(e)|<A-}dt + V5(|x(l)|)x{x(i)<K}] + E[|^ ¥'(|x(OI)X{|i(0|>A-}dt + ¥'(|a:(l)|)X{x(i)>iC}] < 2E [<p{K)\ + oE f |i(t)|dt+|i(l)| +2e < if i is an element oo. Jo an element of f ^. is weaker than T^, we only need to show that convergence in T implies convergence in T,p. Consider a sequence of elements {in} that converges to i in T. This implies that {xn} converges in the product measure generated by P and Lebesgue measure to x. Consider now Hence i Since is T E[[j '0 + E[y E[^ < + aE <P{\Xn{t) - x{t)\)X{\x„{t)-z{t)\<K} dt + <p{\Xn{l) - l(l) |)X{x„(l)-x(l)<if }] <p{\Xr,{t) - x{t)\)x{\z„{t)-x{t)\>K} dt + <P{\X„{1) - l(l)|)X{x„(l)-x(l)>/f}] filxnit) - x{t)\)x{\x4t)-z[t)\<K} dt + <p{\xn{l) - a:(l)|)X{x„(i)-x(i)<A-}] - x{t)\dt + 2e. y \xr,{t) + \xn{l) - x{l)\ I The first term on the right-hand side of the inequality converges to zero by Lebesgue convergence theorem. The second term goes to zero as n —» oo by hypothesis. Since e is arbitrarily small, \\xn — x\\^ — » as n — OO. Proof of Proposition I 15: Proof. Suppose that u is not linear. Then there exists two scalars r,f and t € [O, l] such that u(r,0/2 + u(f,«)/2. Without loss of generality, assume that u((r + f)/2>0 > i^ u(r, t)/2 + u(f,t)/2. By joint continuity, there exists e > and some interval / containing ( such that ui^r + r)/2, s) - e > u(r, s)/2 + u(f s)/2 for all s € /. Consider a sequence of nonrandom absolutely continuous consumption patterns constructed cis follows: Off of /, consume at rate 1 in each !„. On /, subdivide / into 2n equal sized intervals, and consume at rate r on the even subintervals and f on the odd. This sequence of consumption patterns converges in the Prohorov metric to the consumption pattern x that has x\s) = 1 off / and x\s) = (r + f)/2 on /. By Proposition 7, i„ —» i in T^. But U[x) > C/(i„) + eA(/), where A(/) is the Lebesgue measure of /. Thus U is not continuous in T^. I u{{r + f)/2,t) , Appendix A Proofs 42 Proof of Proposition Proof. T^. 17: Fix a topology T^. Let i„ be a sequence of consumption plans that converge to x in loss of generality, that sup„ ||vV„|| < oo. We will first show that u{xn,i] Assume, without converge to ti(i,t) in the product measure i/ = P x A, where P is the probability measure on (n,7), and A is the Lebesgue measure on the Borel sigma-field on [0,1]. First observe that if i„ — i in T^, then i„ — i in T. Hence, » » jjm^Eiy |i„(0-i(OI'i« + This implies that i„ converge to i in the = 0. (26) product measure v, and that /q linCO ~ ^(01 ^^ con- verges to zero in P-measure. Therefore, for any > k}) < i, and P[l^ |x„(0 - |2:n(l)-i(l)|] m, we can find A'^(tti) such that I'fKw, t): |z„(w,t)- > ^] < ^, for all n > N{m). Now consider i„(w, t) - x{uj,t) = /q 0{uj,s) dxri{u>,t - s) - dx{u, t — s). Integrating by and using the assumption that 9[ijo,k) vanishes, we get: ^KOI Xn{oJ, t) - x{u, t) = - (i„(o>;, t) - x{t)\dt i(u;, t)) 0{u,O) - where 6,[u),s) denotes the partial derivative of and its derivative are uniformly bounded over Mi\xn{uj,t) From - this x{uj,t)\ + we can , Milfg \x„{<jj,t) — (i„(a;, j 6[uj,s) uj, x{<jj,t)\dt], t - s) - x{uj, t with respect to - s. s)) 9,{u, s) ds, (27) But the left-hand side in (27) where Mi and M2 parts, is since both 6 bounded by are two constants. easily conclude that i^({{oj,ty.\xr.{uj,t)-x{uj,t)\> > + -{Mi m Mi)}) ' <m Vn>Ar(m). (28) in ^-measure to x. Now consider the convergence of u(xn). First, assume uniformly continuous in x. Since the felicity function u is state-independent, and uniformly continuous in i, it then follows that if |i„ — i| < ci then |u(in) ~ "(i)l < ck^i, where a is independent of w, and x. We use this assumption of uniform continuity, together with (28) to conclude that u{x„) converges in iz-measure to u{x). By Jensen's inequality, we Hence f„ converge that u is have sup„E[/q u{xn)dt] < sup„u(E[/q Xndt]) < 00. It then follows by Lebesgue dominated convergence theorem that U{x„) converge to U{x). Next consider the ceise when u is merely continuous in x. For every integer m, define Um(^) = "(^)X(J-<i<ml- ^°^ a fixed m, the function u^ is uniformly continuous in x, and hence the arguments in the previous paragraph defined exactly as U{x), except that u to u[x) as m— » 00. show that [/„(!„) converge to Um{x), where Ujn{x) is substituted by u^- But Um(i) converge monotonically Applying the monotone convergence theorem, we conclude that lim U(xn) n —»oo This shows that the is = lim Um{xn) m,n —oo utility definition given = Hm tn—^oo Um.{x) = U(x). by (20) gives preferences continuous in T^. I Appendix B Example of a 7^ continuous preference that violates (11) Proof of proposition Proof. Suppose not. By 43 18: joint continuity, there exists two scalars r,f and + r)/2, z, i) ^ t;(r, z, i)/2 + u{f, z, t)/2 for all values of z. Without that v{{r + f)/2,z,i) > v[r,z,t)l2 + v(f,z,t)/2. By joint continuity and some interval / containing t such that v((r + f)/2,z,s) - e > t G [0, 1] such that loss of generality, v((r assume again, there exists e > v{r,z,s)/2 + v{f,z,s)/2 for all s E I. Consider a sequence of nonrandom absolutely continuous consumption patterns constructed as follows: Off of /, consume at rate 1 in each in- On /, subdivide / into 2n equal sized intervals, and consume at rate r on the even subintervals and f on the odd. This sequence of consumption patterns converges in the Prohorov metric to the consumption pattern x that has x'{s) = 1 oflf / and x'{s) = (r + f)/2 on /. By Proposition 7, i„ —» i in Tp. Proposition 17 shows that lim„_oo = dt /o v{x',Xn,t) /q v{x',x,t) dt. / v{x',x„,t)dt> f Jo But for v{x'„,Xr„t)dt any i„, we have: + eX{I). Jo Taking limits of both sides as n / — > v(x',x,t)dt= lim oo, Hence V(i) > lim„_oo y{xn) I continuous in To. Appendix B + get: v(x',Xn,t)dt> lim / v(x',Xn,t)dt "^°oJo / "-'°°Jo Jo we (^^{I)i Example where A(/) is + the Lebesgue measure of €X(I). /. Thus V is not of a 7^ continuous preference that violates (11) We first show that any linear preferences with the marginal utility being the optional projection of a continuous and uniformly bounded process are continuous in all of T^ for all tp G ^. f-.Q x [0,1] — adapted, with the the properties that Proposition 19 Let f{u>,.)EC[0,l] 5R 6e and an J x B{^) -measurable where C[0, l] denotes the space of continuous functions on by: of f denoted , < esssup^ max/(u;,t) [0,1]. process, not necessarily oo, Define the optional projection f /•(a;,0 Note that by construction, the process f is = E[/(t)|7/. adapted. Preference relations which are represented by: x>y if E C r{t)dx{t) >E f r{t)dy[t) Jo Jo are continuous in TL, , Vi.yef^^ Appendix B Example of a T^ continuous preference that violates (11) Proof. Given Tn.i e f^, and E lim n—»oo we show that |i„(l)-i(l] = /* as in the hypothesis, f |i„(t)-i(0|(it + 44 if: 0, (29) Jo then lim n—'oo C r{t)dxr,[t)~ Jof r{t)dx{t) £ 0. (30) Jo is continuous in T and thus in 7^ for all v? € $ since, by Corollciry 1, T is weaker than any T^. To prove this, we will use the fact that since /' is the optional projection of / then Then > E f r{t) Dellacherie and Therefore, for any pf |x„(0 - VI.57). Now x{t)\ dt + (29) implies that: |x„(i) - m > 0, choose N{m) |xn(0 - + (3i: ( ;J;|) such that for x{t)\ dt = > i(i)|] I [f^ P{[ [[ Write (30) Jo Meyer (1982, Theorem Jim Vi„ G f ^i f f[t)dx^[t) dXr.it) Jo |x„(l) n > N[m): all - > :r(l)|] < 1. 1 1j as: r fit) diXr.it) -X{t)) + 1 Jo '2 > where C" = /-" = / [' fi<^,t)diXr.iu,,t)-xiu,t))Pidu) r fiu,t)diXr.iuJ,t)-xiuj,t))Pidu), [ Jn'r-"Jo and where n;"'" n; We now show = LG n: \j' |i„(0 <w e n: I - i(0| + |i„(l) |x„(f)-x(t)|d< + li„(l)-i(l)| that both /["'" and /^'" converge to zero First consider /|"'". Assume - df to begin with that /(w, bls .) i(l) m G < -\,n>Nim), m >M.n>^(H l], on [0,l]. oo. the space of continuously This implies that fticjj,t) < K^ < oo J-measurable function K, where we use /( to denote dfi(jj,t)/dt. differentiable functions — (and hence n) C^[0, for t G [0,1] for some Appendix B For Example G D^'", einy a; of a T^ continuous preference that violates (11) consider /q /(w, t) <i(i„(a;, t) - 45 x{uj,t)). Integration by parts gives / f{uj,t)d{xn{'^,t)-x{u;,t)) Jo = (i„(a;, 1) - x{u, - 1)) /(a;, 1) (i„(a;, 0) - - x{oj, 0)) /(a;, 0) [i„(a;, t) ^ - x{u, t)]ft{oj,t) dt Hence / Jo f{uj,t)d{x„{uj,t)-x{uj,t)) < -/(a;,l) + (x„(0)-i(0))/(a;,0) + m By and the the right continuity of the sample functions of {in} and x are constants, we have lim In(0) —'u^j m.n—'oo K^ I - l{0) fact that in(0) and x[0) 0. Tri,r( Thus, as m— » oo, we get lim r fit)d{xr.{t)-x{t)) = o But U ^^ Vo/efl ^ ni.n—*oo J r\ ' m ' n^'". n>N{m) if lim r f{u;,t)d{xr,{u,t)-x{uj,t))^0 V/(a;, .) e C^O, l] Vo; G f] (J Q^'", m n>N(m) " jim r/(a;,0d(2:„(u;,0-^{'^,0) = V/(a;, .) £ C[0, l] Va; G Q n>Af(ml U "^"1 »" see Billingsley (1968, Theorem In addition, since for all 7.1, p. 42). wG fij"'" we have: f{u;,t)d{xr,{u,t)-x{u;,t))<A[j j d{{xr,{t) - x{t))] < A{Xr.{l) - where A= sup sup \f{(^,t)\, wentelo.i) and since from (29) we have that I^n(l)-X(l)| it as n — > oo, then follows from Strook (1987, Exercise III. 3. 19) that 7^'" — Now consider T^*'"- Since P(n^'") — from (31), and since as n —+ > [' fit)d{x„{t)-x{t))<A{x4l)-x{l)) Jo therefore /j ' — » as n, m— > oo by Lebesgue convergence theorem. I oo. x{l)), Appendix B Example Proposition 20 There Proof. for all It suffices I € £!^ 46 of a T^ continuous preference that violates (11) > on f^ continuous exist preferences to provide an example. Let = ^ and ip~^ in 6^, that do not satisfy (11). i* let € C^ be such that x-\-x' >- x Define the continuous function: . /(w,() = QyJl/tx{l/t) + a > a' = E^f f [t) where 1 dx' (t) . Let = E a^l//i(l/0+l /•(a;,0 and define preferences on f^ by x>y E /'/•di >E f'f'dy if Jo Jo By construction and by Proposition 19, sequences =E Cr.(w,0 It is clear that both sequences nces and y/m(")]xo, continuous is >: in =E y„(a;, <) T^. Next consider the two y'^(n) Xi/n- satisfy the requirements of Proposition 9. However, and w: e[I^ fit) d{x„[t) + x'{t))] = + e[^/^' a* and J f{uj,t)dy„{u;,t)= [l + ayJl/n{uj,n))B[y/^)]. Hence B[iy'{t)dy„] = e[\/^] +aE[y^]E[-yi/M(n)] > Q+ E[y^], where we have used Jensen's Inequality and the E r f'{t)dx^{t) =E / fact that f{t)dx^{t) Vi„ G f ^; Jo Dellacherie and Meyer (1982, Theorem VI. 57). Hence for r f'{t)d{x4t)+x'{t)) <E Jo any rr{t)dy4t) Jo and therefore: lim In n—•oo which proves that >: violates (11). h^k'I U59 I - I* lim ^ n— »oo n: y^, for every n Date Due FBI. 8 1994 Lib-26-67 MIT 3 TOflD LIBRARIES DUPL 1 DD5b7M30 1