Three Essays in Public Economics by Sarah Y. Siegel B.A. Mathematics Pomona College, 2000 SUBMITTED TO THE DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS INPARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY IN ECONOMICS AT THE MASSACHUSETTS INSTITUTE OF SEPTEMBER MASSACHUS'8 INSTUE TECHNOLOGY OF TECHNOLOGY 2006 SEP 2 5 2006 @2006 Sarah Y. Siegel. All rights LIBRARIES reserved. The author hereby grants to MIT permission to reproduce and to distribute publicly paper and electronic copies of this thesis document in whole or in part in any medium now known or hereafter created. Signature of Author: /_ .. , • Department of Economics • \ August 11, 2006 Certified by: Jonathan Gruber Professor of Economics Thesis Supervisor Accepted by: . Peter Temin Elisha Gray II Professor of Economics Chairman, Committee for Graduate Studies ARCHAVES Three Essays in Public Economics by Sarah Y. Siegel Submitted to the Department of Economics on August 11, 2006 in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Economics Abstract This thesis consists of three separate papers. In the first paper, using the Panel Study of Income Dynamics (PSID), which has measures of both risk preferences and religiosity along with measures of many risky behaviors, I investigate the implications of the correlations among risk preferences, religiosity and gender for the observed relationship of each of these variables with risky behaviors. I conclude that the correlations of risk preferences, religiosity, and gender with behaviors are all strongly robust to including the others in the regression; although they are correlated, they have independent relationships with risky behaviors. The second paper reports the results of a randomized field experiment to study the impact of choice in charitable giving; in this experiment half of the recipients of a newsletter from a Dutch NGO were able to choose what program area their donation would be spent on. There is no difference in either mean response rates or mean donation amounts between the treatment and control groups; I thus conclude that while most of the treatment group in this experiment did not value the choice that they were given, the choice also did not make them any less likely to donate. In the third paper, a coauthor and I develop a computer model in which individual agents choose a neighborhood based on preferences over the area's racial composition; this model of residential segregation is loosely based on the 1971 Schelling model. We find that both the strength of preferences for diversity, and historical segregation, have strong effects on equilibrium levels of integration. When we include contemporary discrimination in our model, however, we find that it increases segregation in an initially unsegregated model, but has no additional effect on segregation in an initially segregated model. Finally, we examine a simple social policy that encourages integration, and find that it is successful in creating diversity, making diversity-seeking agents better off. Thesis Supervisor: Jonathan Gruber Title: Professor of Economics Acknowledgments I thank my advisors Jonathan Gruber and Esther Duflo for their guidance and advice throughout the research process, their help was invaluable. I also thank Sendhil Mullainathan for his input and advice, and Xavier Gabaix for his guidance on Chapter 3. I thank the National Science Foundation Graduate Research Fellowship for providing primary financial support. I also thank the MIT Schultz Fund for the travel support required for Chapter 2. I thank David Abrams, Elizabeth Ananat, Jessica Cohen, and Guy Michaels, for providing a great arena for comments, criticism, support, and discussion, during the months when that was most needed. I also thank many friends and officemates who provided moral support, a great sounding board, constructive criticism, and help throughout the process. I especially thank Joanna Lahey for her advice, moral support, and proofreading skills, from the time I began to consider applying to graduate school in economics, during our senior year of college, through the present. And I thank David Schatten for providing so much support, encouragement, and humor during my final year of graduate school. I thank my mentors before graduate school, Gary Burtless, Cecilia Conrad, and Michael Kuehlwein, for showing me how great economics could be and encouraging me to pursue it. I thank ICS, especially Machteld Papegaaij and Els Hekstra, for their willingness to perform the experiment described in Chapter 2 and their work to make it happen; and I thank Jason Woodard, as well as the other participants at the Santa Fe Institute Complex Systems Summer School, for comments and suggestions on Chapter 3. And finally I thank my parents, Daniel and Ruth Siegel, for all of their support, advice, editing, and words of wisdom at so many times during the last five years. Chapter 1 The Interaction of Risk Tolerance, Religiosity, and Gender in Explaining Risky Behaviors 1 INTRODUCTION 11 2 BACKGROUND 12 2.1 Religiosity and Risky Behaviors 12 2.2 Risk Preferences and Risky Behaviors 13 2.3 Risk Preferences and Religiosity 14 2.4 Gender Differences 16 3 DATA 17 3.1 Risk Preferences 19 3.2 Religiosity 20 3.3 Risky Behaviors 21 3.4 Religious Density 22 4 EMPIRICAL APPROACH 23 4.1 Part 1: Relationships among the factors 23 4.2 Part 2: Comparison with the Barsky et al. results 24 4.3 Part 3: Risky Behaviors on Each Factor and Combinations of the Factors 24 4.4 Part 4: Religiosity Instrument 25 5 RESULTS 26 5.1 Relationships among the factors 26 5.2 Comparison with Barsky et al. results for risky behaviors 27 5.3 Risky behaviors on each factor individually and on all three together 28 5.4 Comparison with Barsky et al. results for investment choices 29 5.5 Investment choices on each factor individually and on all three together 30 5.6 Religious Density Instrument 31 6 CONCLUSION 33 REFERENCES 35 TABLES AND FIGURES 37 Chapter 2 The Effect of Choice on Charitable Contributions: A Field Experiment 1 INTRODUCTION 45 2 EXPERIMENT DESIGN 48 2.1 Design Issue 50 3 DATA 50 4 RESULTS 52 4.1 Targets chosen 52 4.2 Experiment donations 53 4.3 Experiment donations by group 56 4.4 Post-experiment donations 56 5 CONCLUSION 57 REFERENCES 60 TABLES AND FIGURES 62 Chapter 3 Schelling Revisited: Historic Discrimination, the Desire for Diversity, and Current Segregation with Elizabeth Ananat 1 INTRODUCTION 71 2 THE MAKINGS OF AMERICAN SEGREGATION 73 3 THE SCHELLING MODEL 75 4 OUR MODEL 77 4.1 Constructing neighborhoods 77 4.2 Constructing preferences 79 4.3 Constructing the simulation 84 4.4 Extension One : Historic Discrimination 84 4.5 Extension Two: Current Discrimination 85 4.6 Extension Three: A Policy Experiment 86 5 THE SIMULATIONS RUN 87 5.1 Main Simulations 87 5.2 Current Discrimination 87 5.3 Subsidy 88 5.4 Percent of each type of agent 88 5.5 Outcomes 89 RESULTS 89 6 6.1 Historical Discrimination 89 6.2 Controls 90 6.3 Current Discrimination 93 6.4 A Policy Experiment 94 7 CONCLUSION 94 REFERENCES 100 TABLES AND FIGURES 102 Chapter 1 The Interaction of Risk Tolerance, Religiosity, and Gender in Explaining Risky Behaviors 1 Introduction In this chapter, I look at three factors that have been shown to be strongly correlated with a person's likelihood of engaging in risky behaviors: risk preferences, religiosity, and gender. These individual relationships are well-studied; however, there are also strong correlations among these three factors: women are more risk averse, women are more religious, and people who are more risk averse are more religious. The gender differences have received a significant amount of attention, but the direct relationship between risk preferences and religiosity has received much less attention. I investigate the implications of the correlations among risk tolerance, religiosity and gender for the observed relationship of each of these variables with risky behaviors. The data I use are from the Panel Study of Income Dynamics (PSID), the only broadly representative dataset that contains measures of both religiosity and risk preferences. The measure of religiosity I use combines three factors: frequency of attendance at religious services, number of volunteer hours for religious organizations, and amount donated to religious organizations. The measure of risk preferences is based on a series of questions about a choice between a job that guarantees you income for life equal to your current total income and one that has a 50-50 chance of doubling your income and a 50-50 chance of cutting your income by some fraction. I also have detailed demographic and socioeconomic data, as well as information on a number of behaviors such as smoking, drinking, self-employment, and investment decisions. I show that even though risk preferences, religiosity, and gender are highly correlated, they each have independent correlations with risky behaviors; for instance, controlling for risk tolerance does not significantly lower the estimated correlation between religiosity and risky behaviors. This is true both when the relationship is measured using OLS and when it is measured using an instrument for religiosity based on religious market density, although the results from the instrument are only suggestive, as it is a relatively weak instrument. I find strong associations between each of risk tolerance, religiosity, and gender, and almost all of the risky behaviors I look at, in the expected directions. Religiosity, risk tolerance, and gender all seem to have comparable effects, so this research reaffirms both the power of religiosity to affect behavior and the validity of risk preferences as a measurement of some individual characteristic that is associated with a wide variety of risky behaviors, as well as the importance of gender in explaining behaviors even when many other factors are controlled for. This chapter is laid out as follows: section 2 discusses the background and reviews the literature; section 3 describes the data used; section 4 lays out the empirical approach; section 5 gives the results; and section 6 concludes. 2 Background 2.1 Religiosity and Risky Behaviors Iannaccone (1998) provides an excellent summary of the economics of religion literature; it includes two strains of research that are relevant to this paper: first, research on the consequences of religion, which includes many papers documenting a relationship between religion and a wide range of behaviors including drug use, school attendance, and criminal activity; second, research on the factors that cause a person to be more or less religious. Iannaccone summarizes research done before 1998 documenting a relationship between religion and risky behaviors. Since then, the literature has continued to develop, with the most recent contribution being Gruber (2005); he uses two facts to look at the effect that exogenous changes in religiosity have on outcomes such as education levels and income. The first fact is that if a higher fraction of a person's neighbors share that person's religion, that person will attend religious services more often; higher religious density causes more religious attendance. The second fact is that religious density of a neighborhood is partly determined by the ethnic mix of the neighborhood. The religious density of a neighborhood for a certain person can thus be exogenously predicted using the density of different ethnic groups in the neighborhood, not including the person's own ethnic group. Using these facts, he finds strong positive effects of religion on both education and income. 2.2 Risk Preferences and Risky Behaviors Economists have long assumed that there is a stable, measurable characteristic called "risk preference" that can be used to predict people's behaviors across a wide variety of domains. It has also been quite widely assumed that a question which elicits a person's attitude toward financial risk can create a valid measure of this characteristic. There have been a number of recent attempts to take a closer look at these assumptions in a variety of ways. The paper I focus on is Barsky et al. (1997) because the questions used to measure risk preferences in this paper are almost the same as the ones in the PSID. Barsky et al. look at measures of risk tolerance, time preference, and intertemporal substitution that were all asked in wave 1 of the Health and Retirement Study (HRS) in 1992; the measure of risk tolerance I use from the PSID is based on the measure used in the HRS. In the risk tolerance section, Barsky et al. look at patterns of risk tolerance with respect to demographic characteristics such as age, sex, and race. They also look at the relationship between risk tolerance and various risky behaviors and find significant effects on variables such as smoking, drinking, home ownership, and investment choices. The most recent addition to this literature is Dohmen et al. (2005), who make several important contributions. First, they not only look at the financial risk question, but they also look at a question that asks people to say how willing they are, generally, to take risks, which is answered on a scale from 0 to 10. In addition, they compare the answers to these questions not only to other questions in the survey, but also to behavior in the context of a field experiment. They find that answers to the financial risk question have predictive power for many, but not all, of the risky behaviors they study, while the question asking about general attitude towards risk has predictive power for all behaviors. 2.3 Risk Preferences and Religiosity There are many reasons risk aversion and religiosity could be correlated. First, it could be that people who are more risk averse are more likely to be religious because religion provides insurance. Religion could be thought of as providing several different types of insurance: first, it can be thought of as providing "spiritual insurance." This idea goes back at least to the 17 th century French mathematician and philosopher Blaise Pascal. He developed an argument, referred to as "Pascal's wager," which suggests that you should believe in God (in the Christian sense,) and act as if you believe, because, if you can't be certain, denying God's existence is too risky. If you choose not to believe in God but it turns out God does exist, you will spend eternity in hell; on the other hand, if you believe in God and it turns out there is no God, you have not lost very much by believing, but if he does exist, you will spend eternity in heaven. Religiosity can thus be thought of as insurance against the possibility of going to hell. Two other types of insurance that may be provided by religion are consumption and happiness insurance. Dehejia et al. (2005) find evidence that some religious organizations provide consumption insurance and some provide happiness insurance, and Chen (2005) shows that people who were hit hardest by the Indonesian financial crisis became more religious. Clark (2005) also finds evidence, using two large-scale European datasets, that religion can act as happiness insurance in the case of unemployment and divorce. The causality could also, however, go in the opposite direction: religion could cause people to be more risk averse. This is slightly less intuitive because a person's risk preferences are generally thought of as a stable, exogenous characteristic; Stark (2002) discusses evidence that risk preferences have a physiological basis. However, risk preferences are not always assumed to be stable: Brunnermeier and Nagel (2004) study whether fluctuations in wealth might change a person's risk preferences. It is possible that in addition to discouraging particular risky behaviors, religion, by emphasizing responsibility and planning, for instance, could change a person's overall level of risk aversion. It must be noted that changing risk aversion is very different from changing certain behaviors; if religion causes people to be more risk averse, all risky behaviors will change, even ones, such as investing in stocks, that are not discouraged by religious leaders. This is very different from changing the behaviors that are regarded as vices and generally discouraged by religious leaders, such as smoking and drinking. Finally, it is possible that there is not, in fact, any causal relationship between risk aversion and religiosity; it could just be a spurious correlation caused by some third factor. In this paper I do not attempt to differentiate among these different relationships between risk preferences and religiosity; the different possibilities provide context for my work, and I am interested in the implications of this relationship for the effects of risk preferences and religiosity on behavior. I leave it to future work to tease out the causality. 2.4 Gender Differences Women are less likely to engage in risky behaviors than men are; they have lower rates of criminality, smoking, drinking, etc. (Byrnes, Miller and Schafer, 1999). They also have lower risk tolerance, on average (Dohmen et al., 2005). Finally, while the results on the relationships between religiosity and education and religiosity and age are unclear and not consistent, "the data are clear: women consistently demonstrate a greater affinity for religion than men," (Spilka et al., 2003). Miller and Hoffmnan (1995) argue, using a nationally representative survey of high school seniors, that controlling for risk tolerance attenuates the gender difference in religiosity. Stark (2002) also argues that the gender difference in religiosity is related to the gender difference in risk preferences. He takes it a step further than Miller and Hoffman, however, by arguing that there is a convincing body of evidence that the gender difference in risk preferences is physiological, and the gender difference in religiosity is caused by this physiologically based difference in risk preferences. 3 Data The data for this study come from the PanelStudy of Income Dynamics (PSID), specifically the 1996 & 2003 waves, because the module measuring risk tolerance was in the 1996 wave, while a good measure of religiosity was not available until the 2003 wave. The 2003 wave of the PSID is thus the first time that a large, representative survey has been available that contained good measures of both risk tolerance and religiosity for the same people. The only other large-scale survey that is now available containing measures of both is the Health and Retirement Survey (HRS), which includes both the same risk tolerance measure and a question about attendance at religious services. The HRS, however, is focused on people who were between the ages of 51 and 61 during the first wave of the study in 1992. The PSID is therefore the only dataset that allows one to look at the relationship between risk tolerance and religiosity among a broadly representative sample of individuals. The survey is asked at the household level, but many of the questions, such as those about smoking and drinking, are asked of both the head and the wife. I thus create individual-level observations, so for households headed by a couple I have two observations, one for the husband and one for the wife. Each observation will also have family-level data such as family income and wealth. The one variable that I have for at most one person per household is risk tolerance; the questions in this module were only asked of the survey respondent, who is usually the head of the household. This is also the only variable that does not come from the 2003 survey--I thus match the risk tolerance measure with the individual ID for the person who was the survey respondent in the household in 1996 and use this to merge the information into the 2003 data. This leaves me with 12,120 observations for most variables, but only 3,499 observations that include all variables, including risk tolerance. Table 1 shows the means and standard deviations of all of the variables used in the OLS regressions except for risk tolerance (whose distribution is shown in Figure 1.) Column 1 uses all of the data in the 2003 survey, while column 2 uses only the 3,499 observations that contain all data. Panel A shows the demographic variables; some of these values may appear to be too large, for instance an average family income of almost $70,000. This is because families headed by married couples have higher incomes than other families, and these families are counted twice in the data, because observations are at the individual level, rather than the household level. This means that there is only have one observation from each single parent household while there are two observations from each married household. The mean family income using one observation per family is $60,813, which is in fact below the value estimated from the CPS of $66,970.1 Comparing columns 1 and 2, the means are sometimes significantly different; there are two reasons for this difference. First, because the module measuring risk preferences was only used in 1996, this only includes people who were in the survey in both 1996 and 2003. This means that any families that were formed after 1996 or any people who moved into existing households after 1996 will not be included. It also means that none of the immigrant sample added to the survey to make it more representative in 1997 are included. (The survey was representative of the U.S. population in 1968, and since then has been following those same people and their offspring and spouses. That means that immigrants who arrived in the U.S. since 1968 are vastly underrepresented. An immigrant sample was thus added into the survey in 1997.) This explains why the percent Hispanic (and hence percent Catholic) is so much lower in the restricted data. Second, the risk tolerance module in only asked of respondents if they are employed, so the restricted data has higher income, education, etc. and fewer women. 'From http://pubdb3.census.gov/macro/032003/faminc/new07_000.htm 3.1 Risk Preferences The series of questions used to measure risk tolerance are the same as the ones that Barsky et al. use from the HRS; see Barsky et al. (1997) for the logic behind its development. The first question in the series is: Suppose you had a job that guaranteed you income for life equal to your current, total income. And that job was (your/your family's) only source of income. Then you are given the opportunity to take a new, and equally good, job with a 50-50 chance that it will double your income and spending power. But there is a 50-50 chance that it will cut your income and spending power by a third. Would you take the new job? A respondent who answers no is then asked about a 50-50 chance of income being cut by a fifth; a respondent who answers yes is asked about a 50-50 chance of income being cut by a half. So far, this is exactly the same as the module in the HRS. However, while the HRS questions stop at a fifth, in the PSID if a respondent answers no to income being cut by a fifth, the survey goes on to ask about a tenth; if the respondent answers yes to income being cut by a half, the survey goes on to ask about it being cut by 75%. Because of the phrasing of this question, it is only asked of individuals who are currently employed. This series of questions has the advantage of being about an amount of money that scales by income, so there shouldn't be much variation in the measurement of risk aversion by income level. (And I do not, in fact, find very much variation.) The HRS, like the PSID, is a panel survey, and the risk tolerance module was asked of everyone for wave 1, and repeated in wave 2 for 10% of the sample. Barsky et al. use the repeated sample to estimate the measurement error in the risk tolerance values and use that to generate a better estimate of risk tolerance. See Barsky et al. (1997) for the details; because the PSID question is so similar but is only asked once, the PSID uses the Barsky et al. calculations for the values of risk tolerance. This means that some information is lost, because the information from the questions about income being cut by a tenth or 75% is dropped and only the information from the questions about income being cut by a third and a fifth is used. This means I lose some variation (although I have the same number of observations); however, the results generated from using the corrected values are much more precise, so I use those data. Figure 1 shows the resulting values of risk tolerance; almost half of the sample (49%) chooses the lowest value, and the other half of the sample is very evenly divided among the other three values (16%, 16%, and 20%.) 3.2 Religiosity The PSID contains 3 potential measures of religiosity: frequency of attendance at religious services, amount donated to religious organizations, and hours spent volunteering for religious organizations. Gruber (2004) used variation in tax rates to show that attendance and giving are substitutes, so combining them should give a more complete measure of religiosity. (Whether giving and volunteering are substitutes or complements, in general or in the religious context, remains an open question (Carlin, 2001), but including volunteering in addition to giving should create an even more complete measure of religious involvement.) Unfortunately, none of these measures of religiosity are distributed normally. Their distribution is much closer to lognormal, but there are many zeros in each of them, so using logs will cut the sample significantly. Figures 2 and 3 show this visually; they are kernel densities of attendance at religious services (times per year) and the log of attendance at religious services, respectively, neither of them including zeros, which are 27% of the observations. Figure 2 shows a distribution where the vast majority of the observations are clustered very close to zero and there is a very, very long tail; figure 3 gives a much clearer view of the distribution-the large peak is at attendance once a week, although there is still a fairly long tail. Also, combining these three separate measures into one index of religiosity requires measuring each of them in a comparable way. As a result, I have chosen to translate each one into a percentile; all zeros are given a percentile of .01 and the highest 1% are given a percentile of 1.0. The religious index is then the average of the attendance percentile, the giving percentile and the volunteering percentile. Translating each into a percentile allows me to keep all the observations without being concerned about outliers and at the same time allows me to combine the three measures of religiosity. The means of both the original variables and the percentiles are shown in Panel B of Table 1. The average of the percentiles are all well under .5; in fact the mean volunteering percentile is only 0.15. This is because there are so many zeros and they all have a percentile of 0.1. 3.3 Risky Behaviors I follow Barsky et al. in my choice of outcomes to examine in order to allow direct comparison to their results. As a result, the risky behaviors studied are whether individuals have ever smoked and whether they smoke now; whether they drink now and the number of drinks they have per day; the number of years of education they have completed; whether they are selfemployed; whether anyone in their family has had health insurance over the last 2 years; and whether they own their home. The number of drinks per day is not the exact number but a categorical variable where 1 represents less than 1 drink a day, 2 is 1-2 drinks per day, 3 is 3-4 drinks per day, and 4 is 5 or more drinks per day. I also follow Barsky et al. in looking at investment behaviors. The PSID questions divide financial wealth into four categories.: stocks, savings, etc., IRAs, and other assets. The stocks category includes "any shares of stock in publicly held corporations, mutual funds, or investment trusts-not including stocks in employer-based pensions or IRAs." The savings, etc. category includes "any money in checking or savings accounts, money market funds, certificates of deposit, government savings bonds, or treasury bills-not including assets held in employerbased pensions or IRAs." The IRAs category includes IRAs and private annuities. Finally, other assets includes "any other savings or assets, such as bond funds, cash value in a life insurance policy, a valuable collection for investment purposes, or rights in a trust or estate." The sum of these four categories is considered to be a family's total financial assets, and the outcome variables of interest are the fraction of financial wealth that is in each category. Panel C shows the means of all of these outcome variables. 3.4 Religious Density I use local religious density as an instrument for religiosity, following the approach of Gruber (2005) as well as is possible given my data. The PSID's ethnicity data are not as detailed as the ethnicity data in the survey he used, the General Social Survey (GSS)-the PSID categories are Western Europe, Eastern Europe, Africa, etc., which are much too broad to be used for this purpose. As a result, I use religious density directly rather than using ethnicity as a proxy; one's religious density is the fraction of people in one's state who share one's religion. Following Gruber (2005), I use the categorization of Christian denominations defined in Roof and McKinney (1987), but I combine categories that have fewer than 100 observations in my data, which leaves the categories Catholic, Jewish, Episcopalian, Presbyterian, Methodist, Lutheran, Christian (Disciples of Christ), Northern Baptist, black Methodist, black Northern Baptist, black Southern Baptist, Southern Baptist, Pentecostal, other Protestant, other Christian, unknown religion, and no religion. I measure religious density at the state level, and I drop all states for which I have fewer than 100 observations; this results in dropping 6.6% of my observations. I follow Gruber in using religious attendance as my measure of religiosity for this section, because the literature says (and my work supports) that higher religious density increases religious attendance (Phillips, 1998 and Olson, 1998), while it decreases charitable giving (Zaleski and Zech, 1995, and Perl and Olson, 2000). Even though I use attendance only for the instrument, I use the religiosity index for the OLS results; using attendance only would give very similar but less precise results. 4 Empirical Approach 4.1 Part1: Relationships among the factors The first step is to examine the relationship among the three factors by running these regressions : (1) REL, = P, + P 2R (2) RT = (3) REL, = P, + A 2F + A3X, + e 1 +f 2Fj + P3X, + + 3 Xi 6 + where REL5 is the religiosity of individual i, RTj is the risk tolerance of individual i, FJ is a dummy for whether the individual is female, and X, is my vector of controls. These are each of the possible pairwise regressions of each of the factors on each other and controls, to establish these relationships among the factors before looking at the relationships of these factors with behavior. The controls used are age (35-44, 45-54, 55-64, 65 and above), race (black, Hispanic, other), female, education (high school, some college, college, more than college), religion (Catholic, other Christian, Jewish, other, unknown, none) family income decile, family wealth decile (excluding home equity), and home equity decile. 4.2 Part2: Comparison with the Barsky et al. results The second step is to compare the results I find with the PSID to the Barsky et al. results using the HRS. For this section I repeat their regressions: (4) Yi =f + fl 2RTI + fl 3X, + Here, Yi is one of my measures of risky behaviors or investment choices, and X, contains only my controls for age, race, sex, and religion, as those are the controls used by Barsky et al. 4.3 Part 3: Risky Behaviors on Each Factorand Combinations of the Factors This section discusses regressions of the form (5) Yi = P +f 2Ri + Pf3Xi + e where Y. is one of my measures of risky behaviors or investment choices for individual i; R1 is either religiosity, risk tolerance, gender, or some combination of these factors; and X, is a vector of controls. The controls used are the same used in part 1: age, race, female, education, religion, family income decile, family wealth decile (excluding home equity), and home equity decile. First three separate regressions are run: one with risk tolerance and controls; one with religiosity and controls; and one with gender and controls. These are followed by three regressions that each contain a pair of the factors: one on risk tolerance, religiosity, and controls; one on risk tolerance, gender, and controls; and one on religiosity, gender, and controls. Finally, I run a regression on risk tolerance, religiosity, and gender combined. Following Barsky et al., the observations for the regressions of financial assets are limited in two ways: first, they are limited to those families who have at least $1000 of financial wealth. Second, because these variables are very much at the family-level, as opposed to the individual level, only household heads are used in these regressions. 4.4 Part4: Religiosity Instrument I look more closely at causation by instrumenting for religiosity. Of the three factors I study, religiosity is the primary one that may not be exogenous: gender is clearly exogenous, and risk tolerance is also generally considered to be a stable, exogenous characteristic, while the same things that change risky behaviors could change religiosity at the same time. Instrumenting for religiosity thus allows me to look more carefully at the causal effects of each of the three factors on behavior. The regressions I run are thus (2) Y, =/ 1 + f 2A, + 3X, + 4 reli + Areg, + E where A. is attendance, instrumented with religious density, X, are individual-level controls, rel, are religion dummies and reg, are region dummies. I have a dummy for each of the 17 religious categories that I calculate religious density based on, and 4 region dummies: northeast, north central, south, and west. (The final regional category is Alaska and Hawaii, but those states both have fewer than 100 observations, so they are both dropped.) As discussed in Gruber (2005), the choice of this instrument is based on a few studies which have found that higher religious density is associated with more religious attendance; however, he discusses several measurement issues that lead to concerns about the exogeneity of this instrument. The issue that will be of concern to me is that more religious people may be more likely to move to areas where there are more people who share their religion. Gruber is able to look at people who move and find that this would, in fact, bias against finding the positive effects that he finds. 5 Results 5.1 Relationshipsamong the factors Table 2 shows the relationships among risk tolerance, religiosity, and gender; it shows the results of the regressions described in equations 1, 2, and 3. Panel A shows the results of regression 1 (religiosity on risk tolerance) and panel B, columns 1-4 show the results of regression 3 (religiosity on female). Each column of columns one to four has a different measure of religiosity as the dependent variable; attendance, volunteering, donations, and the overall index. Looking at Panel A, the coefficient on risk tolerance is approximately -0.1 in each column. This means that, because the difference between the highest and lowest values of risk tolerance is 0.42, the least risk tolerant people have a religiosity index that is 4 percentage points higher than the most risk tolerant. This is larger than the difference between men and women of 2.9 percentage points, and as women's higher degree of religiosity is well established in the sociology literature, the fact that risk tolerance has as strong an association as gender indicates the importance of risk tolerance. Column 3, the regression of donations to religious organizations, stands out because it is the only one where the coefficients are not significant. I do not take this, however, to mean that there is in fact no relationship; rather, this is a data issue. While risk tolerance, gender, religious attendance, and religious volunteering are measured at the individual level, donations are measured at the household level; it is thus not surprising that the relationship is weaker with donations than with the other measures of religiosity. The final column, column 5 in panel B, shows that women are less risk tolerant than men, by .026, from a modal value, as seen in figure 1, of 0.15. 5.2 Comparison with Barsky et al. resultsfor risky behaviors Next I examine the relationship between risk tolerance and a variety of risky behaviors. Table 3, Panel A shows my regressions of equation (4) replicating the Barsky et al. results in the PSID, while Panel B shows the original Barsky et al. results. My results are generally very similar to the Barsky et al. results, and so serve to validate this measure of risk tolerance, as it is strongly correlated with many risky behaviors; the effect of risk tolerance is significant at the 1% level on a dummy for drinking, number of drinks per day, a dummy for self-employment, a dummy for someone in the household having health insurance.2 2 Ideally, for comparison purposes, I would limit my sample to the same age range as in the HRS; however, this cuts the sample so much that the coefficients are no longer significant and the standard errors are too large to generate any useful insights. My results are broadly similar to the Barsky et al. results. One significant difference is that Barsky et al. find that more risk tolerant people are more likely to smoke now and to have ever smoked, while I find no significant effects and the point estimate on smokes now is negative, though insignificant. Although this is inconsistent with Barsky et al., it is consistent with Dohmen et al. (2005), who find no relationship between current smoking and the response to their financial measure of risk preferences but find a strong, positive relationship between current smoking and their general measure of willingness to take risks. I also find a strong, significant relationship with self-employment, whereas Barsky et al. did not. I also find slightly larger effects on drinking and self-employment, and smaller effects on home ownership; my results are stronger in some cases and weaker in others, but broadly similar, and upholding the conclusion that risk tolerance is associated with a broad range of risky behaviors. 5.3 Risky behaviors on each factor individually and on all three together The columns of Table 4 are the same as in Table 3; the heading of each one gives the risky behavior that is the dependent variable of the regressions whose results are listed in that column. Panel A is almost exactly the same as Panel A of Table 3, the only difference being that these regressions use my control variables, which are a somewhat broader set than those used in Barsky et al, encompassing income, wealth, and education in addition to race, sex, age, and religion. The coefficients remain very similar, although with the additional controls risk tolerance now does have a significant, positive effect on whether a person has ever smoked; the coefficient in the "smokes now" regression, however, remains small, negative, and insignificant. More risk tolerant people are more likely to have ever smoked, to drink now, to have more drink per day, to be self-employed, and to lack health insurance, and less likely to own a home. Panel B shows these same dependent variables on religiosity and controls, and Panel C shows these same ones on gender. The coefficients on religiosity are always the opposite sign of the coefficients on risk tolerance, as long as both are significant. This means that more religious people are less likely to behave in risky ways-the only exception to this is self-employment, which is not significantly related to religiosity. The coefficients on the female dummy, however, are all significant and all in the opposite direction from risk tolerance-women are less likely to engage in all of these risky behaviors. Panel D uses the same observations used in panels A-C and risk tolerance, religiosity and gender are all combined into one regression. The coefficients all remain very similar to what they were in panels A - C, although all coefficients which were significant in panels A - C decrease slightly in absolute value in panel D. (Because the results in panel D are so similar to those in panels A-C the results of the regressions on each pair of factors are not shown; they are each very similar as well.) Looking at the magnitudes of the coefficients, we can see that religiosity is the factor with the strongest correlations with behaviors. For instance, consider whether a person drinks now. The most risk tolerant people are 7.9 percentage points more likely to drink than the least risk tolerant people, while people at the 9 0 th percentile of the religiosity distribution are 18.9 percentage less likely to drink than the people at the 10th percentile of the religiosity distribution, and women are 10.7 percentage points less likely to drink than men; although these are all quite large effects, the religiosity effect is certainly the largest. 5.4 Comparisonwith Barsky et al. resultsfor investment choices In Table 5 I again run regressions that can be compared with the Barsky results, but now with investment choices. Unfortunately, the questions about investments are quite different in the PSID and the HRS, so that it is more difficult to directly compare the two sets of regressions; nevertheless, my results are broadly similar to the Barsky et al. results. The categories that are the same across the two samples, stocks, and IRAs, have very similar results; the coefficient for stocks is about 0.09, while the coefficient for IRAs is very close to zero and insignificant. The category of savings, etc. in the PSID includes bonds, savings, checking, and t-bills, and the coefficient on this category is within the range set out by the coefficients on these categories by the Barsky et al. results; it is not surprising that this one is not significant at 5%because it combines such disparate categories, some of which have a positive and some a negative relationship with risk tolerance, so the resulting standard error is large. 5.5 Investment choices on eachfactor individually and on all three together In table 6, the dependent variables are the fraction of financial wealth in each of four different categories: stocks; savings, etc.; IRAs; and other assets. In Panel A the regressions are run on risk tolerance and controls, in Panel B they are on religiosity and controls, and Panel C on gender and controls. In Panel D the regression is run on all three together. Once again, combining the three together in one regression changes the coefficients very little. These regressions are slightly less straightforward to interpret than the ones of risky behavior, because financial wealth is measured at the family level, while the variables of interest are at the individual level. Because I only use family heads, this looks at the effects of characteristics of the family head. The results for risk tolerance are as expected: more risk tolerant heads put more of their wealth into stocks, the riskiest investment, and less into savings, the safest. While in the context of other risky behaviors, religiosity had the opposite effect from risk tolerance, here it is more complicated; both more risk tolerant and more religious people put less in savings accounts, but while risk tolerant people put that money into stocks instead, religious people put it into IRAs. Finally, families with female heads, controlling for everything else, have less in savings and more in "other assets." This is difficult to interpret because this is not an effect of gender but the effect of the gender of the household head, and it is unclear what the other assets are here. The only variable here that risk tolerance, religiosity, and gender are all significantly associated with is the fraction of the household's financial wealth that is in savings and checking accounts and other relatively safe assets. Comparing the coefficients in column 2 of panel D, we see that the percentage of financial wealth in these safe assets is 5.4 percentage points lower for the most risk tolerant people than the least risk tolerant people, 4.9 percentage points lower for people at the 9 0th percentile of the religiosity distribution than people at the 10th percentile, and 6.1 percentage points lower for women then men. So here, the magnitudes of the effect are very comparable, and are all a little more than a 10% change from a mean of 46%. 5.6 Religious Density Instrument As discussed earlier, the instrument may not be perfectly exogenous; as a result, the instrumented regressions are merely suggestive. Table 7 shows the first stage results, and columns one to three show, as found in earlier results, that religious density is quite strongly positively related to religious attendance, and while it is also related to religious donations and volunteering, attendance is the strongest. These results support Gruber's use of attendance as a measure of religiosity, so in the following IV results I use religious density to instrument for religious attendance. In columns 5, 6, and 7, I add in controls. Column 5 adds in income controls, column 6 adds region dummies, and column 7 adds in state dummies. The first stage is strongest in column 6, using all controls other than the state dummies, so I run the instrumental regressions using this specification. Table 8, Panel A shows the regressions of all of the risky behaviors on instrumented attendance.3 The coefficients are somewhat larger here than in the OLS results, but the standard errors are so much larger as well so I cannot reject the hypothesis that the coefficients are the same as in the OLS regression. However, despite the large standard errors, some of the effects are significant, and all of the significant ones go in the expected direction. Instrumented religiosity decreases the likelihood that one currently drinks and the number of drinks per day and increases the likelihood that one owns a home; these effects are significant at the 5%level. Table 8, Panel B shows the regressions on instrumented attendance using only observations that have observations for risk tolerance. This drastically cuts the number of observations, and the standard errors increase enough that only one coefficient is now significant; religiosity now seems to decrease self-employment, which is surprising, as this is one of the few results that was not significant in the OLS results. Panel C shows these regressions where risk tolerance and gender are also included, and once again, the coefficients on attendance stay quite similar when these variables are included. Table 9 shows the instrumented regressions for investment behavior. Here, none of the coefficients are even significant at 10% even using all observations. Especially when the sample is limited, in panels B and C,to only observations containing risk tolerance values, even using the strongest specification the instrument is simply too weak to uncover the effects on financial wealth, with standard errors at least 0.26 and expected effect sizes (judging by the OLS results) of no more than 0.1. 3 Ideally, I would use state dummies so that I would be identified only off of religion*state interactions. However, using state dummies soaks up much of my variation in religious density; my results are much more precise if I only control for region. 6 Conclusion There is a large literature showing a strong association between religiosity and the level of risky behaviors, between risk tolerance and the level of risky behaviors, and between gender and the level of risky behaviors. However, literature on the relationships among religiosity, risk tolerance, and gender is highly speculative; I use the fact that I have measures of risk tolerance, religiosity, gender, and risky behaviors to look carefully at these relationships. It has been suggested that higher risk aversion causes more religiosity; I find that risk preferences are correlated with religiosity, although I cannot speak to the causality. It has also been suggested that women's higher level of religiosity is caused by the fact that women are more risk averse. I find that this is not true: the gender difference is in fact even larger when risk preferences are controlled for. In general, I conclude that the effects of religiosity, risk tolerance, and gender on risky behaviors are in fact completely independent; adding the other two variables as controls does not affect the coefficient on the third. I find that risk tolerance, as measured in the PSID, is correlated with many types of behavior, including drinking, health insurance coverage, and investment decisions, which validates this measure of risk preferences as measuring a personal characteristic that has predictive power in many different contexts. Similarly, religiosity is correlated with these behaviors as well, and controlling for risk aversion does not lower the coefficients on religiosity; this reaffirms that religiosity itself is correlated with behaviors, through a channel that is independent of risk aversion. Finally, even when risk aversion and religiosity are controlled for, the gender differences in behavior remain; these gender differences must thus be caused by other factors. Instrumenting for religiosity provides suggestive evidence that the effects of religion are causal, although the instrument is too weak to make strong conclusions. Many risky behaviors, such as smoking and drinking, can have negative externalities, and are therefore of concern to policy-makers. However, we do not have a good understanding of what determines a person's likelihood of engaging in risky behaviors; as a result, we cannot confidently predict the effects of policies on these behaviors. My results further our understanding of these behaviors by showing that risk preferences, religiosity, and gender each have powerful and independent correlations with risky behaviors; this implies that it is important to include them all in studies of these behaviors whenever possible. In addition, they show that even though women are more religious and more risk averse, controlling for religiosity and risk preferences increases the estimated impact of gender on risky behaviors, rather than lessening it. This implies that there is another difference between men and women that accounts for their different behaviors, and understanding this gender difference could provide insight into what causes people to engage in risky behaviors. References Azzi, Corry and Ronald Ehrenberg (1975). "Household allocation of time and church attendance," JournalofPoliticalEconomy 83: 27-56. Barsky, Robert B. et al. (1997). "Preference Parameters and Behavioral Heterogeneity: An Experimental Approach in the Health and Retirement Study," QuarterlyJournalofEconomics, 112 (2): 537-579. Byrnes, James P., David C. Miller and William D. Schafer (1999). "Gender Differences in Risk Taking: a Meta-analysis," PsychologicalBulletin, 125 (3): 367-383. Carlin, Paul S. (2001). "Evidence on the Volunteer Labor Supply of Married Women," Southern Economic Journal,67 (4): 801-824. Chaves, Mark and Philip Gorski (2001). "Religious Pluralism and Religious Participation," Annual Review of Sociology, 27: 261-281. Chen, Daniel (2005). "Economic Distress and Religious Intensity: Evidence from Islamic Resurgence During the Indonesian Financial Crisis," mimeo, University of Chicago. Clark, Andrew (2005). "Deliver us from Evil: Religion as Insurance," mimeo, PSE. Dehejia, Rajeev, Thomas DeLeire and Erzo F. P. Luttmer (2005). "Insuring Consumption and Happiness Through Religious Organizations," mimeo, Harvard University. Dohmen, Thomas et al. (2005). "Individual Risk Attitudes: New Evidence from a Large, Representative, Experimentally-Validated Survey, " IZA DiscussionPaperSeries, No. 1730. Donkers, Bas, Bertrand Melenberg, and Arthur van Soest (2001). "Estimating Risk Attitudes using Lotteries: A Large Sample Approach." JournalofRisk and Uncertainty, 22 (2): 165-195. Ellison, Christopher (1991). "Religious Involvement and Subjective Well-Being," Journalof Health and Social Behavior, 32: 80-99. Francis, L. J., S.H. Jones, C.J. Jackson, and M. Robbins (2001). "The feminine personality profiles of male Anglican clergy in Britain and Ireland," Review of Religious Research 43:14-23. Gruber, Jonathan (2004). "Pay or Pray: The Impact of Charitable Subsidies on Religious Attendance," Journalof PublicEconomics, 88: 2635-2655. Iannaccone, Laurence (1998). "Introduction to the Economics of Religion," Journalof Economic Literature, 36: 1465-1496. Levin, Jeffrey S. (1994). "Religion and Health: Is There an Association, Is it Valid, and Is It Causal?," Social Science and Medicine, 38: 1475-1482. Miller, Alan S. and John P. Hoffman (1995). "Risk and Religion: An Explanation of Gender Differences in Religiosity," Journalfor the Scientific Study ofReligion 34: 63-75. Miller, Alan S. and Rodney Stark (2002). "Gender and Religiousness: Can Socialization Explanations Be Saved?," American JournalofSociology, 107 (6): 1399-1423. Phillips, Rick (1998). "Religious Market Share and Mormon Church Activity," Sociology of Religion, 59: 117-130. Roof, Wade C. and William McKinney (1987). American Mainline Religion: Its Changing Shape andFuture. New Brunswick and London: Rutgers University Press. Sherkat, Darren E. and Christopher G. Ellison (1999). "Recent Developments and Current Controversies in the Sociology of Religion," Annual Review of Sociology, 25: 363-394. Spilka, Bernard et al., (2003). The Psychology of Religion: An EmpiricalApproach. New York: Guilford Press. Stark, Rodney (2002). "Physiology and Faith: Addressing the 'Universal' Gender Difference in Religious Commitment," Journalfor the Scientific Study ofReligion, 41 (3): 495-507. Wallace, John, and David Williams (1997). "Religion and Adolescent Health-Compromising Behavior," in J. Schulenberg, J.L. Maggs, and K. Hurrelman, eds., Health Risks and Developmental TransitionsDuringAdolescence. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 444-468. Figure 1: Risk tolerance values 2nnA O 00U0 - i 1500 - •-1000 '- 0 0 500- E z 0 0.15 0.15 I I 0.35 0.28 value 0.28tolerance 0.35 Risk - 0.57 Risk tolerance value Figure 2: Kernel density of attendance at religious services CO O - CO oO 0- oI 5000 I 10000 Attendance at religious services I 15000 I 20000 Figure 3: Kernel density of log of attendance at religious services C -1 CD - 01 (0 Nu- 0- · · · I 6i I 24 of attendance at religious 6 services Log 38 · 8 I1 10 Table 1: Means (with standard errors) of all variables (1) All data (2) Restricted Data PanelA: Demographics Female Black Hispanic Other Race Catholic Protestant Other Christian Jewish Other Religion Unknown Religion No religion Education (years) Age Family income ($1,000s/year) Wealth, excluding home equity ($1,000s) Home equity ($1,000s) 0.54 (0.007) 0.095 (0.003) 0.069 (0.003) 0.14 (0.005) 0.27 (0.006) 0.54 (0.007) 0.016 (0.002) 0.037 (0.003) 0.068 (0.003) 0.017 (0.002) 0.052 (0.003) 13.19 (0.037) 47.64 (0.21) 0.46 (0.011) 0.10 (0.006) 0.019 (0.004) 0.067 (0.006) 0.23 (0.010) 0.60 (0.011) 0.017 (0.003) 0.040 (0.005) 0.038 (0.004) 0.0063 (0.002) 0.061 (0.006) 13.82 (0.051) 47.33 (0.25) 67.67 (1.35) 78.56 (1.98) 208.45 (13.68) 86.87 (2.12) 253.48 (27.05) 39.98 (3.58) 22.60 (2.40) 915.78 (42.08) 0.42 (0.004) 38.74 (5.06) 26.50 (4.90) 96.08 (3.38) PanelB: Religiosity Religious attendance (times/year) Religious volunteering (hours/year) Religious donations ($/year) Religious attendance percentile Religious volunteering percentile Religious donations percentile Religiosity index percentile 0.15 (0.005) 0.38 (0.006) 0.32 (0.004) 980.42 (55.56) 0.41 (0.007) 0.17 (0.008) 0.40 (0.009) 0.32 (0.007) Panel C: Outcome behaviors Ever smoked 0.47 (0.007) 0.49 (0.011) Smoke now 0.20 (0.006) 0.21 (0.009) Drink now 0.62 (0.007) 0.68 (0.010) Drinks per day 0.81 (0.011) 0.91 (0.018) Self-employment 0.11 (0.004) 0.14 (0.008) No health insurance 0.064 (0.003) 0.047 (0.004) Home ownership 0.71 (0.006) 0.78 (0.009) Fraction in stocks 0.17 (0.006) 0.17 (0.008) Fraction in IRAs, etc. 0.23 (0.007) 0.27 (0.010) Fraction in savings, etc. 0.50 (0.008) 0.46 (0.012) Fraction in other assets 0.10 (0.005) 0.10 (0.007) Observations 12,120 3,499 Weighted individual means, dollar figures are in 2002 dollars. Restricted data includes only those observations that have non-missing values for risk tolerance. The final four variables are calculated only on family heads with at least $1,000 of wealth, so only use 4,764 (all data) or 1,759 (restricted data) observations. Table 2: Relationships Among the Factors (1) Attendance (2) Volunteering (3) Donations Panel A: Religiosity regressed on risk tolerance Risk -0.106 -0.106 -0.078 Tolerance (0.031)** (0.036)** (0.040) (4) Religiosity index (5) Risk tolerance -0.100 (0.028)** Panel B: Religiosity and risk tolerance regressed on gender Female 0.059 0.038 -0.016 0.029 -0.026 (0.010)** (0.012)** (0.013) (0.010)** (0.005)** Standard errors in parentheses. Regressions include controls for age, race, religion, income, education, wealth, and home equity; only the coefficient for sex is shown. The regressions of attendance and the religiosity index have 3,499 observations and volunteering and donations have 3,550. Dependent variables in columns 1-4 are percentiles which vary from 0.01 to 1. * significant at 5%; ** significant at 1% Table 3: Risky behavior on risk tolerance, comparison with the Barsky et al. results (3) (2) (1) Ever Smokes Drinks smoked now now Panel A: PSID (author's calculations) Risk 0.068 -0.055 0.218 Tolerance (0.052) (0.043) (0.048)** Panel B: HRS (Barsky et al. calculations) Risk 0.092 0.068 0.099 Tolerance (0.030)** (0.028)* (0.030)** (6) No health insurance (7) Home ownership (4) Drinks per day (5) Selfemployment 0.335 (0.083)** 0.102 (0.035)** 0.071 (0.027)** -0.127 (0.045)** 0.256 (0.053)** 0.021 (0.020) 0.196 (0.031)** -0.153 (0.024)** Standard errors in parentheses. Regressions include controls for age, sex, race, and religion. Every regression in panel A uses 5,012 observations. All dependent variables except for drinks per day (a categorical variable described in the data section) are dummies. Panel B are the results from Barsky et al. (1997) using the HRS. Each regression in panel B has 11,707 observations except health insurance, which only has 8,642. * significant at 5%; ** significant at 1% Table 4 : Risky behaviors on each factor, and then all three (1) Ever smoked (2) Smokes now (3) Drinks now (4) Drinks per day (5) Selfemployment (6) No health insurance (7) Home ownership Panel A: Risk preferences only Risk 0.128 -0.036 Tolerance (0.052)* (0.043) 0.238 (0.050)** 0.422 (0.089)** 0.101 (0.035)** 0.087 (0.026)** -0.113 (0.041)** Panel B: Religiosity only Religiosity -0.197 (0.030)** -0.206 (0.023)** -0.252 (0.029)** -0.495 (0.046)** 0.022 (0.021) -0.033 (0.011)** 0.141 (0.022)** Panel C: Gender only Female -0.075 (0.017)** -0.042 (0.014)** -0.118 (0.017)** -0.337 (0.029)** -0.038 (0.011)** -0.034 (0.008)** 0.038 (0.013)** Panel D: Risk preferences, religiosity, and gender together Risk 0.093 -0.066 0.188 0.299 0.095 0.076 -0.091 Tolerance (0.052) (0.043) (0.049)** (0.085)** (0.035)** (0.026)** (0.041)* Religiosity -0.188 -0.205 -0.236 -0.457 0.029 -0.028 0.135 (0.030)** (0.023)** (0.029)** (0.045)** (0.021) (0.011)* (0.022)** Female -0.068 -0.038 -0.107 -0.317 -0.036 -0.031 0.032 (0.017)** (0.014)** (0.016)** (0.028)** (0.011)** (0.008)** (0.013)* Standard errors in parentheses. Regressions include controls for age, race, religion, income, education, wealth, and home equity. Dependent variables are dummy variables except for drinks per day, which is categorical. There are 3,499 observations. * significant at 5%; ** significant at 1% Table 5 : Investment behavior on risk tolerance, comparison with the Barsky et al. results (1) Stocks (2) Bonds (3) Saving, Checking (4) T-bills Panel A: PSID (my calculations) Risk 0.086 tolerance (0.040)* Panel B: HRS (Barsky et al. calculations) Risk 0.097 0.015 tolerance (0.029)** (0.008)* (5) Savings, etc. -0.094 (0.054) + -0.128 (0.041)** -0.055 (0.024)* (6) IRAs (7) Other assets 0.038 (0.048) -0.030 (0.037) -0.006 (0.037) 0.076 (0.025)** Standard errors in parentheses. Regressions include controls for age, sex, race, and religion. Every regression in panel A uses 1,833 observations. All dependent variables except for drinks per day (a categorical variable described in the data section) are dummies. Panel B are the results from Barsky et al. (1997) using the HRS. Each regression in panel B has 5,012 observations. +significant at 10%; * significant at 5%; ** significant at 1% Table 6: Investment behavior on each factor, and then all three (1) Fraction in stocks (2) Fraction in savings, etc. (3) (4) Fraction in IRAs Fraction in other assets Panel A: Risk preferences only Risk 0.072 -0.097 Tolerance (0.041) + (0.056) + 0.040 (0.049) -0.015 (0.038) Panel B: Religiosity only Religiosity -0.013 (0.022) -0.057 (0.031) + 0.065 (0.028)* 0.005 (0.022) Panel C: Gender only Female -0.002 (0.016) -0.060 (0.024)* 0.026 (0.021) 0.035 (0.018)* Panel D: Risk preferences when religiosity and gender are controlled for Risk 0.071 -0.108 0.050 -0.012 Tolerance (0.041) + (0.056) + (0.049) (0.038) Religiosity -0.010 -0.061 0.067 0.005 (0.022) (0.031)* (0.028)* (0.022) Female -0.001 -0.061 0.027 0.035 (0.016) (0.024)** (0.021) (0.018)* Standard errors in parentheses. Regressions include controls for age, race, religion, income, education, wealth, and home equity. The dependent variables are shares of assets in total financial wealth. There are 1,759 observations. +significant at 10%; * significant at 5%; **significant at 1% Table 7: First stage for religious density instrument (7) (6) (5) (3) (2) (1) Attendance Donations Volunteering Attendance Attendance Attendance Religious 0.258 0.169 0.061 0.265 0.323 0.290 Density (0.034)** (0.045)** (0.036) (0.033)** (0.035)** (0.038)** Basic controls Yes Yes Yes Yes Yes Yes Income controls No No No Yes Yes Yes Region dummies No No No No Yes No State dummies No No No No No Yes Robust standard errors in parentheses .There are 10,985 observations in columns 1 and 4; 11,263 in columns 2 and 3; and 10,176 in columns 6 and 7. Basic controls are age, race, and religion. Income controls are income education, wealth, and home equity. * significant at 5%; ** significant at 1% Table 8 : Instrumented regressions of risky behaviors (3) (2) (1) Ever Smokes now Drinks smoked now Panel A: Attendance only, using all observations Attendance -0.295 -0.201 -1.197 (0.381) (0.314) (0.476)* (4) Drinks per day (5) Selfemployment -1.494 (0.711)* -0.169 (0.245) Panel B: Attendance only, using only observations with risk tolerance Attendance -0.265 -0.196 -0.380 -0.933 -0.515 (0.344) (0.274) (0.323) (0.581) (0.260)* (6) No health insurance (7) Home ownership 0.230 (0.213) 0.309 (0.143)* 0.173 (0.144) 0.104 (0.256) Panel C: Attendance, risk preferences, and gender together Attendance -0.242 -0.210 -0.341 -0.859 -0.507 0.196 0.081 (0.350) (0.280) (0.328) (0.583) (0.265) + (0.149) (0.261) Risk 0.083 -0.087 0.141 0.190 0.035 0.086 -0.101 Tolerance (0.060) (0.049) + (0.058)* (0.098) + (0.045) (0.030)** (0.048)* Female -0.058 -0.026 -0.092 -0.276 -0.009 -0.044 0.027 (0.025)* (0.021) (0.024)** (0.043)** (0.019) (0.011)** (0.019) Standard errors in parentheses. Regressions include controls for age, race, religion, income, education, wealth, and home equity, and region dummies. Dependent variables are dummy variables except for drinks per day, which is categorical. There are 10,176 observations used in panel A and 3,247 in panels B and C. +significant at 10%; * significant at 5%; ** significant at 1% Table 9: Instrumented regressions of investment behavior (1) Fraction in stocks (2) Fraction in savings, etc. (3) Fraction in IRAs Panel A: Attendance only, using all observations Attendance -0.213 0.969 -0.895 (0.359) (0.620) (0.548) (4) Fraction in other assets 0.139 (0.351) Panel B: Attendance only, using only observations with risk tolerance Attendance 0.043 -0.188 0.048 0.097 (0.368) (0.278) (0.351) (0.254) Panel C: Attendance, risk preferences, and gender together Attendance 0.057 -0.227 0.069 0.101 (0.285) (0.379) (0.360) (0.261) Risk 0.051 -0.133 0.075 0.008 Tolerance (0.050) (0.070) + (0.063) (0.048) Female -0.011 -0.042 0.014 0.038 (0.018) (0.027) (0.025) (0.020) + Standard errors in parentheses. Regressions include controls for age, race, religion, income, education, wealth, and home equity. The dependent variables are shares of assets in total financial wealth. There are 4,029 observations used in panel A and 1,635 in panels B and C. +significant at 10%; * significant at 5%; ** significant at 1% Chapter 2 The Effect of Choice on Charitable Contributions: A Field Experiment 1 Introduction Economists and policy makers have long been interested in the determinants of charitable giving. Economists have, in recent years, performed many field and laboratory experiments on this topic. Some of these experiments look at the importance of social distance and anonymity (Soetevent, 2004; Breman and Granstrom, 2005), and of empathy (Batson et al., 1995; Fong, 2004) in the donation decision. Some test the effect of changing the "appeals scale," the list of suggested donation amounts (Desmet and Feinberg, 2003) or the extent of crowding out (Eckel, Grossman, and Johnston, 2005). Several compare the effects of different sorts of subsidies, including matching grants, seed money, and rebates, on fundraising (List and Lucking-Reiley, 2002; Eckel and Grossman, 2003; Falk 2004; Eckel and Grossman, 2005; Meier, 2005; Karlan and List, 2006). Landry et al.(2005) tests the effect of a lottery incentives in door-to-door fundraising. Variation in the extent of choices available to potential contributors, however, has not been investigated in the literature. This is surprising because existing theory and evidence generate ambiguous predictions for the effects of the availability of choice on the welfare of potential contributors, as well as their willingness to donate. Economic theory generally considers choice to be welfare enhancing, and extensive psychology research has focused on enumerating the beneficial effects of choice (e.g. Cordova & Lepper, 1996); however, recent research has cast doubt on the idea that choice is invariably positive (e.g. Iyengar and Lepper, 2000). This paper is a first attempt to fill this gap: using a randomized field experiment, it tests the effect on donations of having an expanded set of options. A randomly selected half of the recipients of a newsletter from a Dutch NGO had the option of choosing what program area their donation should be spent on: health, education, or wherever most needed. (Health and education are this charity's major program areas.) There are two reasons to expect an increase in donations from this experiment. First, there is the rational reason: people who are given the opportunity to donate to something they care more about will be more likely to donate, and will donate more. A person who values health much more than education will have a higher marginal utility of donations to health than of donations to the organization as a whole, and thus will be more likely to donate and/or will donate a larger amount. Second, there is the psychological explanation. Psychologists have repeatedly found that people have greater "intrinsic motivation" when they are allowed to make choices for themselves, and this is true even when the choice is fairly indirectly related to their goal ( e.g. Lewin, 1952; Deci, 1981; Deci and Ryan, 1985; Cordova and Lepper, 1996). Charitable giving depends strongly on intrinsic motivation, as there are unlikely to be any strong external forces pushing a person to make a donation; much of the psychology research would thus lead one to predict an increase in donations. Recent research, however, has produced ample evidence that in certain cases, choice can in fact be demotivating (Shafir, Simonson, and Tversky,1993; Redelmeier and Shafir, 1995; Iyengar and Lepper, 2000; Bertrand et al., 2005; Roswarski and Murray, 2006). Iyengar and Lepper (2000) performed a field experiment in a grocery store where jams were put on display for sampling, and found that while 30% of the people who stopped to look at a display of 6 different jams bought some of that jam, only 3% of the people who stopped to look at a display of 24 jams bought any. Bertrand et al. (2005) performed a field experiment that involved sending out mailings advertising a variety of loans. They found that potential loan recipients who saw a simple table of loan choices were much more likely to respond to the advertisement than those who were shown a more complete display of their options; the size of the table was unrelated to the number of options that were in fact available, which were described in the text of the letter. These papers show the potential negative effects of choice; they indicate that when a choice seems complicated or difficult, people may postpone choosing or may end up not choosing at all. Although the choice of where to target the donation is not very complicated, it is more complicated than the usual decision a donor faces; it is thus easy to imagine a donor seeing the choice and thinking to himself or herself "Oh, I can choose where I want my money to go. Interesting. I wonder what I should do? I will have to think about that later, when I have more time." The donor will then put the donation form back in his or her pile of things to do, and may or may not ever return to it. This could be expected to decrease the response rate among the treatment group; however, it should not change the donation amount conditional on giving, except through compositional effects. There is also evidence that an experiment which has direct effects on donation rates can have intertemporal effects (Meier, 2005). There are several ways this could occur: if the experiment increased the response rate, it could increase future donations, by drawing more people into becoming regular donors. If it increased donations by generating positive feelings towards ICS, among the donors, because they appreciate the chance to target their donations, this could carry over into the future, and thus increase future donations. In addition, if it increases either the response rate or mean donation in the experiment, that could also decrease future donations, if it causes intertemporal substitution. If the experiment decreases donations, however, any of these effects could occur in the opposite direction; a lower response rate could reduce the number of future donors, choice could generate negative feelings towards ICS that carry over, and there could be positive future intertemporal substitution. Based on previous research and the experimental design, there are thus reasons to expect the donation rate and donation amount conditional on donation to increase or to decrease. In this case, the provision of choice seemed to have zero impact: both the donation rate and amount are remarkably similar between the treatment and control groups. This is not because the recipients did not understand that they had the opportunity to choose; over half of the people in the treatment group did take the opportunity to make a choice. However, a striking result is that 80% of those choose "wherever is most needed" rather than targeting the money to a particular target area. This suggests that choice was not particularly valued by those recipients, which may explain the absence of and effect; the option of not choosing remained a natural 'default' option which allowed them to avoid thinking about the issue. The remainder of this chpater is organized as follows: section 2 describes the experiment design; section 3 discusses the data used; section 4 gives the results; and section 5 concludes. 2 Experiment Design This project entailed modifying one of the regular mailings sent out by International Child Support (ICS). ICS is a Dutch charity that provides aid programs, focused on children, in five developing countries in Africa and Asia. They were founded over 25 years ago and in 2005 they received donations totaling almost C2 million. Although international aid makes up only 2% of the philanthropic sector in the U.S., it is one of the largest areas of philanthropy in the Netherlands; the Dutch gave C5.2 billion to charity in 2003 (1.1% of GDP), and 12% of this went to international aid organizations such as ICS (AAFRC, 2003; Geven in Nederland, 2003). Figure 1 shows the newsletter ICS sent on Sept 14, 2004 to 19,122 of the people on their mailing list; it describes some of their projects in Africa, and on the final page it discusses the retirement of one of their employees, and the crisis in Darfur, Sudan. ICS used their standard process to determine who to send this newsletter to: they mailed it to their regular donors who receive every newsletter and then added a few other subsets, who receive the mailings less often. The newsletter recipients were then divided into treatment and control groups using a randomization based on their unique IDs. ICS then sent this mailing to the entire list; the newsletters were identical for the treatment and control groups, so that the sole difference between the mailings received by the two groups was on the donation form. Figure 2 shows the donation form; this is the standard form used to make a donation in the Netherlands. Instead of writing a check, donors use this form (which already has the account number of ICS written on it), write in their account information and send it to their bank. The bank then transfers the money from the donor's account to the charity's account. The control group received this standard form, and for people in the treatment group, there is a slight addition: in the upper right comer of the form (the bottom right comer of figure 2, because the picture is rotated 90 degrees) there is text asking what program area they want their money to go to: health, education, or wherever is most needed. When the donations were received, ICS also received the donation forms of the donors who were able to target their donations, and the donors' choices were recorded. 2.1 Design Issue Because the choice was presented in small print on the donation form only, and was not discussed elsewhere in the newsletter, many people may not have noticed it. Also, as many donors likely did not look at the donation form until they were filling it out, they may not have noticed the choice until after they had decided to donate. The intervention would thus have possible impacts on donations on the intensive margin, but the extensive margin would not be affected. 3 Data The analysis makes use of two donation databases. The first one lists the 303,928 potential donors; it includes names and addresses as well as other administrative information and calculations such as the total amount donated each of the past 4 years. A quarter of the people in this database have donated at least once, and 1.5% of them participate in the child sponsorship program (KAP), meaning they donate £20.50 each month. This database also identifies addresses that are churches or schools, regular donors who receive every newsletter, and cold rentals (meaning addresses that, although they may have received mailings from ICS in the past, have never donated.) The second database lists each donation ICS has received from January 1 1996, until September 16, 2005, almost 1.2 million donations in total. For each donation this database says who it is from, the date, the amount, what newsletter or other donation request it was donated in response to, whether it was given as part of the child sponsorship program, and some other administrative data. I use these data to create three variables: the total donations since 2001; the donations given in response to the experimental newsletter; and the donations given after the experiment. Total donations since 2001 is the total amount donated between Jan 1 2001 and Sept 14, 2004, the day the experimental newsletter was mailed; donations given after the experiment is the total donations given after the day the experimental newsletter was sent out that were not given in response to the newsletter. I use the Statistics Netherlands urban/rural definition and merge their list of municipalities in urban regions and with the donor list; by this definition 56% of the Dutch population lives in urban areas. The Netherlands also has an area that is more religious than the rest of the country called the bijbelgordel, or bible belt. I define this area using zip codes based on a list given to me by ICS; approximately 25% of the Dutch population lives in the bijbelgordel. Finally, I can determine gender for a limited number of people on the mailing list; this is, unfortunately, not entirely straightforward, because one difference between the Netherlands and the U.S. is that they are more likely to use first initials rather than names. This is partly, I believe, because they use more names, so the database has first initials and last name, for example T. M. J. de Graaf. This means I cannot use names to determine donors' gender. I can assign a gender to those names that have the title Mr. or Mrs., but that leaves me with only 44% of my sample. Table 1 shows summary statistics for the treatment and control groups. The randomization was successful; there are no significant differences between the two groups in pre-experiment characteristics. The first variable here is total post-experiment donations-the mean is E50, although the mean of the log is only 1.69, which is the log of 65.42. The next variable is whether the prior donations since 2001 are above zero, and this shows that 46% of the sample has donated since 2001. The sample is 31% urban, 31% in the bible belt; this is much more rural than the overall Dutch population and slightly more likely to live in the bible belt. 12% are churches or schools, 0.08% take part in the child sponsorship program, 30% are regular donors and 44% are cold rental addresses. 4 Results Figure 3 shows a kernel density graph of the donations in the experiment without zeros. Even without zeros, the donations are heavily concentrated at numbers under £100 but there is a very long tail, with very few donations above €100 but one observation at £1,000. Figure 4 then shows the distribution of the log of the donation amount; this is much closer to a normal density with the one difference that there are large spikes at certain numbers; the largest ones occur at €log(5) and Clog(10). This is because many people donate round numbers such as £5 or £10 but fewer donate anything between those two amounts. Table 2 shows the basic results of the experiment: the donation amounts and response rates for the treatment group and the control group. It shows that whether you look at donation amount, response rate, the amount donated, log of donation conditional on giving, or the log of post-experiment donations, there are no significant mean differences between the treatment and control groups. The response rate is 11% and the mean log donation amount conditional on giving is 2.11 (which is the log of £8.25.) 4.1 Targets chosen Table 3 shows the choices made by the treatment group. The first three rows show the number of people who chose each of education, health, and wherever most needed, and their average donation amounts. Out of the over 1,000 people in the treatment group who made donations, only 59 of them chose education and 29 chose health, while over 400 chose wherever is most needed. Overall, of those in the treatment group who made a donation, there are more who made some choice (495) than who didn't make a choice (404); this means that despite the inconspicuousness of the choice, most people did notice it. The mean donation to education is significantly higher than the mean donation to health, but row 5 shows that if health and education are combined together, their mean donation is almost exactly the same as "wherever most needed", and because the number of people choosing education and health are both so low, the difference in donation amounts among the people choosing each of these are not economically significant. However, row 7 shows the average donation amounts of those who made any choice, and comparing these numbers to those in row 4 shows that those who made a choice donated more than those who did not make a choice, and this difference is highly significant (t = 4.18) for log donations. Comparing these numbers to row 3 of table 2 shows that while those in the treatment group who made a choice donated about the same amount as the control group, those who failed to make a choice donated less than the control group. This implies that not only did people not value the choice, but some donors, those who did not make a choice, may have disliked having the choice, and donated less as a result. 4.2 Experiment donations The first specification is (1) D, = P, + P2 + P3 P + 4 4 PG, + PSX, + E, where D, is the donation amount given by donor i, T is a dummy variable that is equal to one for donors in the treatment group, JP is the level of previous donations since 2001 of donor i,, PG, is a dummy variable that is equal to 1 if P, is greater than zero and Xi is two controls: bible belt and urban. This specification is shown in the second column of table 4; the first column is simply the donation amount regressed on the treatment dummy. In both of these regressions, the coefficient on the treatment dummy is very small and insignificant. Also, the r-squared of the regression with only choice is 0.00, while adding in the other variables increases it to 0.2; the treatment dummy does not seem to explain any of the variation in donation amounts, although the controls do. In the second specification, I add in an interaction term between choice and prior donations, and an interaction term between choice and the non-zero prior donations dummy, to begin to see whether there may be distribution effects even though there are no mean effects. (2)D i = , +• 21T +33 3 + P4Ti *P+ flPGi +f6Ti *PG, +/ 7Xi +,•i This specification is shown in column 3 of table 4. This shows a very large, positive, interaction effect with prior donation amounts and a significant negative interaction effect with the positive previous donations dummy. In column 4, however, just one observation, the donation of C1,000, is removed, and the results change very significantly. Although the main effects of choice, previous donations, and the positive previous donations dummy are all very similar, the interaction effect with previous donations is now only about one-fifteenth as large and the interaction effect with the previous donations dummy is only one-eighth as large as they were in column 3. Column 5 shows this same regression using a log specification, as I demonstrated above that this was the more appropriate approach. These regressions use the log of both the experimental donation amount and the previous donations, except the zeros are left in as zeros. (There are 6 observations where either the experimental or the previous donation amounts were between zero and one; these were replaced with zeros.) Both the main effect of choice and the interaction effects are insignificant and very close to zero in this regression. I have also ran this regression transforming both the previous donations and the experimental donations into percentiles, and the results are similar to the results with logs. The apparent effects in columns 3 and 4 thus are most likely a result of the larger donations having an unduly large impact on the results, because of the lognormal distribution of donations. Table 5 takes a closer look at different sections of the donation distribution, to determine if choice has different impacts at different parts of the distribution. The specification here is: (3) COU = , 1 + f 1T 2 + 83 log(P) + ,84T. * log(Pi) + S 5PG1 + f6T * PG, +P7X, + ,6 where CO i is a dummy for whether individual i donated an amount above the given cutoff, Ci is again a dummy variable that is = 1 for donors in the treatment group, log(PD 5 ) is the log of the prior donations of person i, including zeros, and NZ, is a dummy variable indicating whether the prior donations of individual i are nonzero. The cutoffs I use are response (whether the donor responded to the newsletter, i.e. had a donation amount greater than zero), at least C5, at least £10, at least £15, at least £20, and at least £25. This reinforces the conclusions from the previous regressions. Although previous donations strongly predict donation amounts, the main effect and interaction of choice are both almost always zero. The is one significant interaction effect, however-the interaction is negative in the regression of whether the donor gave at least £10. The results remain very similar if these regressions are run as probits instead of linear probability regressions. 4.3 Experiment donations by group There are two unique subgroups among the newsletter recipients; 12% of them are schools and churches, and 44% are cold rental addresses. Table 7 shows how different these two groups are from the other largest category, the regular donors. While the churches and schools, and the cold rental addresses, both have response rates under 1%, the regular donors have a response rate of 31%. Table 8 shows the same specifications shown above without the churches and schools and the cold rentals; this results in dropping many of the zeros, and it also drops all of the observations who had zero previous donations. The results are very similar; the previous donations remain the only highly significant variable, and neither choice or the interaction term are ever significant. The results thus do not change when the less involved newsletter recipients are dropped from the analysis. This means that the more involved donors do not seem to behave significantly differently from those who are less involved; it also means that it is probably not all the zeros that are driving the results, because dropping over 60% of the zeros does not change the results. 4.4 Post-experimentdonations Table 9 is the same as table 4, (the specifications from equations 1 and 2), except now the dependent variable is post-experiment donations; these are the donations sent by donors who were in the experiment sample, in the year following the experiment. The conclusions from this are the same as the conclusions from table 4: looking at the regressions in levels with the interaction term, in columns 2 and 3, there appears to be a treatment effect, but when the regressions are run in logs instead, these results disappear. Table 10 is the same as table 5 but with post-experiment donations; it uses the specification of equation 3, but the cutoff points have been shifted somewhat, as the donation totals are higher here. The regressions are all quite similar to the ones in table 5; again, one of the 12 interaction effects is significant. One difference, however, between tables 9 and 10 and the earlier results, is that the rsquareds are much higher here. The final regression of table 9 has an r-squared of 0.47, while the final one in table 4 is only 0.22; in table 10 the r-squareds range from 0.1 to 0.42, whereas they ranged from 0.04 to 0.21 in table 5.This may be because the total donations over several previous years are an even better predictor of the total donations over the year than they were of the donation amount given in response to one particular newsletter. 5 Conclusion In this paper I discuss a field experiment that studies choice in charitable giving. Half of the recipients of a charity's regular newsletter were given the opportunity to target their donation to either health, education, (the two major program areas of the charity,) or wherever it was most needed. It was a priori unclear, from the psychology and economics literature, what effect this intervention would have on donation rates and amounts. A first glance at the mean donation rates and amounts of the treatment and control groups indicates that the experiment, in fact, had no effects; more careful examination of interactions and the distribution of donations support this conclusion. There are several ways of explaining this zero effect. One possibility is that the sample size was simply not large enough; the power of this experiment is such that a 5%change in either donation rates or donation amounts would have been detectable at the 95% confidence level in the simple comparison of means. This appears to be significant power as many charitable giving experiments have found much larger effects than that from their manipulations, e.g. Karlan and List (2006) increase the donation rate by 20%, Landry et al. (2005) increase it by 100%,, and Soetevent (2005) increases total donations by 10% . Another explanation is that the choice was simply not salient enough for donors to notice it or respond to it; however, the majority of donors in the treatment group did select one of the three choices, and the average donation of those who made a choice was the same as the average donation of the control group. The final explanation is that the donors did not value the choice given, which is supported by the fact that 80% of the people who made a choice picked "wherever is most needed." More evidence for this comes from the fact that the people who made no choice donated less than either the control group or the people who made a choice, which implies that they may have been put off by the offer of a choice. Why would these donors fail to value this choice? Why did so many of the people who took the time to make a choice choose to leave the decision to ICS? One possibility is that much of the literature regarding choice comes from experiments performed on Americans, and the Dutch may be different from Americans. Americans place a particularly high value on choice, independence, and personal control, so it is possible that the results would have been different if this experiment had been done on Americans. Alternatively, maybe it is the particular choice provided that was not valued. This could be because people realized that the money was quite fungible, so where their personal money went would have no effect on the overall services provided by ICS, which made it essentially a meaningless choice. Or it could be because they trust ICS to choose where their money should go and do not want to make the choice themselves. Finally, it could be because it simply doesn't matter to them which projects ICS spends the money on; what is important to them is giving money to ICS, and the exact work it goes towards is unimportant. More research is needed to distinguish among these competing explanations. References AAFRC Trust for Philanthropy (2003). Giving USA 2003. Indianapolis, IN: Author. Batson, Daniel C. et al. (1995). "Empathy and the Collective Good: Caring for One of the Others in a Social Dilemma." JournalofPersonalityand SocialPsychology, 68 (4): 619-631. Bertrand, Marianne et al. (2005). "What's Psychology Worth? A Field Experiment in the Consumer Credit Market." Working paper, Harvard University. Breman, Anna and Ola Granstrom (2005). "Altruism without Borders?" Working paper, Stockholm School of Economics. Cordova, Diana I. and Mark R. Lepper (1996). "Intrinsic Motivation and the Process of Learning: Beneficial Effects of Contextualization, Personalization, and Choice." Journalof EducationalPsychology, 88 (4): 715-730. Deci, Edward L. (1981). The psychology of self-determination. Lexington, MA: Heaths. Deci, Edward L., and Richard M. Ryan (1985). Intrinsic motivation and self-determination in human behavior. New York: Plenum Press. Desmet, Pierre and Fred M. Feinberg (2003). "Ask and Ye Shall Receive: The Effect of the Appeals Scale on Consumers' Donation Behavior." Journalof Economic Psychology, 24: 349376. Eckel, Catherine C. and Phillip J. Grossman (2003). "Rebate versus Matching: Does How We Subsidize Charitable Contributions Matter?" JournalofPublic Economics, 87: 681-701. Eckel, Catherine C., Phillip J. Grossman, and Rachel M. Johnston (2005). "An Experimental Test of the Crowding Out Hypothesis." Journalof PublicEconomics, 89: 1543-1560. Falk, Armin (2004). "Charitable Giving as a Gift Exchange: Evidence from a Field Experiment." Working PaperSeries, Institute for Empirical Research in Economics. University of Zurich. Fong, Christina M. (2004). "Empathic Responsiveness: Evidence from a Randomized Experiment on Giving to Welfare Recipients." Working paper, Carnegie Mellon University. Geven en Nederland (2005). "Kemcijfers 'Geven in Nederland 2005."' www.geveninnederland.nl Iyengar, Sheena S. and Mark Lepper (1999). "Rethinking the value of choice: a cultural perspective on intrinsic motivation." Journalof Personalityand Social Psychology, 76: 349-366. Iyengar, Sheena S. and Mark Lepper (2000). "When Choice is Demotivating: Can One Desire too Much of a Good Thing?." Journalof Personalityand Social Psychology, 79: 995-1006. Karlan, Dean and John List (2006). "Does Price Matter in Charitable Giving? Evidence from a Large-Scale Natural Field Experiment." Working paper, Yale University. Kingma, Bruce R. (1989). "An Accurate Measurement of the Crowd-out Effect, Income Effect, and Price Effect for Charitable Contributions." Journalof PoliticalEconomy, 97 (5): 1197-1207. Landry, Craig, et al. (2005). "Toward an Understanding of the Economics of Charity: Evidence from a Field Experiment." Working paper, University of Maryland. Lewin, Kurt (1952). "Group decision and social change," in Guy E. Swanson, Theodore M. Newcomb, and Eugene L. Hartley, eds., Readings in socialpsychology. New York: Henry Holt, 459-473. List, John and David Lucking-Reiley (2002). "The Effects of Seed Money and Refunds on Charitable Giving: Experimental Evidence from a University Capital Campaign." Journalof PoliticalEconomy, 110, 215-233. Madrian, Brigitte C. and Dennis F. Shea (2001). "The Power of Suggestion: Inertia in 401(k) participation and savings behavior." QuarterlyJournalofEconomics, 116: 1149-1187. Meier, Stephan (2005). "Do Subsidies Increase Charitable Giving in the Long Run? Matching Donations in a Field Experiment." Working paper, University of Zurich. Redelmeier, Donald A., and Eldar Shafir (1995). "Medical Decision Making in Situations that Offer Multiple Alternatives," Journalof the American Medical Association, 273: 302-305. Roswarski, Todd Eric and Michael D. Murray (2006). "Supervision of Students May Protect Academic Physicians from Cognitive Bias: A Study of Decision Making and Multiple Treatment Alternatives in Medicine." MedicalDecision Making, 26(2): 154-161. Sethi-Iyengar, Sheena, Gur Huberman, and Wei Jiang (2004). "How Much Choice is Too Much? Contributions to 401 (k) Retirement Plans" in Olivia S. Mitchell and Stephem P. Utkus (Eds.), Pension Design and Structure: New Lessons from Behavioral Finance. Oxford University Press, New York, NY pp.83-95. Shafir, Eldar, Itamar Simonson and Amos Tversky (1993). "Reason-Based Choice." Cognition, 49, 11-36. Soetevent, Adriann R. (2005). "Anonymity in Giving in a Natural Context-a Field Experiment in 30 Churches." Journalof PublicEconomics, 89: 2301-2323. Figure 1: The Newsletter WV•L Dapn * c~~r h~ighb~smiwH Ilrili n* bq,,,wild I "o JK+* Ortdorwis In K*W idWr * ~8r lu kL~ Ho. 1v,4-ift.A. moo Voa~truao*r)O ~ &V,L, At4,*, ~~hc~r Výflý 4gkýW-kotv,* D"wbtomtmijý m·b4UtgE * k~opMI·k~lrMI DrJ .k~ -A 0,4".uslp E~i~r S-k- -,Ov*J~phot m-ocHýIL dm* ý" " bwo!l d*4- 554( wk1,A4-n k..hwý4. W -r anýkut 04- iiaaQ~5rnoCBLFLý,iu:-:: AUW X1. "Wdomn .. Oketn 7O: tO. ~OS Figure 2: The donation form :: I a r C .i 4 C 1 r:i it t ii- iCl C H £5~ Sti I Figure 3: Distribution of donations (kernel density) 00 Co 0- (D o- O- 200 400 600 donation amount Figure 4: Distribution of log donations (kernel density) -2 0 Log of Donation Amount 800 1Idoo Table 1: Newsletter recipient pre-experiment characteristics (variable means) (1) (2) Prior donations (since 2001, in 1,000s) Log (prior donations since 2001) Prior donations greater Control 0.053 (0.002) 1.71 (0.021) 0.46 Treatment 0.054 (0.002) 1.74 (0.021) 0.47 than zero (dummy) (0.005) (0.005) 0.27 (0.007) 0.31 0.27 (0.007) 0.31 (0.005) (0.005) Female Urban Bible belt Church or school Child sponsor Regular donor Cold rental 0.31 (0.005) 0.12 (0.003) 0.0008 (0.0003) 0.30 (0.005) 0.44 (0.005) 0.31 (0.005) 0.12 (0.003) 0.0006 (0.0003) 0.31 (0.005) 0.43 (0.005) Standard errors in parentheses. There are 9,561 observations for each cell with the exception that the variable Female has only 3,852 observations in the control group and 3,859 in the treatment group. Table 2: Basic experiment results Donation amount Response Amount conditional on Giving Log of donation Amount (1) Control 1.29 (0.064) 0.11 (2) Treatment 1.31 (0.12) 0.11 11.99 (0.47) 2.11 12.28 (1.09) 2.07 (0.025) (0.025) (0.003) (0.003) Log of post-experiment 3.07 3.04 donation amount (0.023) (0.023) There are 9,561 observations for each cell in rows 1&2, in rows 3&4 there are 1,027 observations in column 1 and 1,022 observations in column 2. Table 3: Target areas chosen among treatment group (2) (1) (1) Education (2) Health (3) Number of Donors 59 29 Wherever 407 most needed (4) No choice 404 Made (5) Unknown 125 Choice ._ (6) Education or 88 Health (7) Any choice 495 Made The first five rows are mutually Is rows 1, 2 and 3 together. (3) (4) Percent of total donors 5.7% Mean Mean log Donation Donation 13.63 2.27 (1.96) (0.10) 2.8% 7.40 1.74 (0.88) (0.16) 39.8% 11.93 2.15 (0.59) (0.039) 39.5% 10.44 1.92 (1.08) (0.040) 12.0% 19.82 2.26 __Q._5) ........... JO-074)_ 8.6% 11.58 2.10 (1.23) (0.091) 48.4% 11.86 2.14 (0.54) (0.036) exclusive, row 6 is rows 1 and 2 together, and row 7 Table 4: Basic regressions with interactions (1) Donation amount Choice Prior donations 0.025 (0.139) (2) Donation amount 0.010 (0.124) 21.296 (0.322)** (3) Donation amount -0.019 (0.162) 7.017 (0.471)** (4) Donation amount -0.019 (0.119) 7.012 (0.345)** Log of prior Donations Prior donations greater than zero Choice * Prior Donations Choice * Log prior donations Choice * Prior don. greater than zero (5) Log donation amount -0.002 (0.012) 0.244 (0.007)** 0.172 (0.130) 1.781 (0.177)** 25.067 (0.624)** -2.817 (0.249)** 1.788 (0.130)** 1.655 (0.491)** -0.333 (0.183) -0.437 (0.028)** -0.014 (0.009) 0.037 (0.039) 0.26 0.09 0.22 0.00 0.20 R-squared Standard errors in parentheses. All regressions include the urban and bible belt dummies as controls. In column 1 donation amount is regressed on choice, in column 2 total prior donations since 2001 is added to the regressors, and in column 3 the interaction of choice and prior donations is added as a regressor. Column 4 is the same as column 3 with one outlier dropped. Columns 5 and 6 are the same as column 3 except column 5 is in logs and column 6 is in logs except for the zeros, which are left as zeros. There are 19,122 observations in every regression except column 4, which has only 19,121. * significant at 5%; ** significant at 1% Table 5: Whether gave above cutoffs (6) (5) (4) (3) (2) (1) Response At least 65 At least 610 At least 615 At least 620 At least 625 Choice -0.001 -0.001 -0.000 0.000 0.000 0.000 (0.005) (0.005) (0.004) (0.003) (0.002) (0.002) Log of previous 0.092 0.093 0.073 0.039 0.024 0.019 Donations (0.003)** (0.003)** (0.002)** (0.002)** (0.001)** (0.001)** Choice*Log of -0.005 -0.004 -0.009 -0.001 0.003 0.000 Prev. donations (0.004) (0.004) (0.003)** (0.002) (0.002) (0.002) Donated before -0.120 -0.155 -0.153 -0.096 -0.060 -0.050 (0.012)** (0.011)** (0.009)** (0.007)** (0.005)** (0.005)** Choice*Donated 0.020 0.014 0.019 0.003 -0.008 -0.002 Before (0.017) (0.016) (0.013) (0.009) (0.007) (0.006) Observations 19122 19122 19122 19122 19122 19122 R-squared 0.21 0.20 0.15 0.08 0.06 0.04 These are linear probability regressions of donating an amount above the given cutoff amount (0, 65, 610, 615, 620, or 625) on choice; the log of previous donations since 2001 (except with zeros, which are coded as zeros rather than missing); the interaction of choice and the log of previous donations; a dummy for previous donations being greater than zero; and the interaction of choice and this dummy. Standard errors are in parentheses. * significant at 5%; ** significant at 1% Table 7: Donation rates and amounts by group 5798 (2) Response rate 0.31 (3) Average log donation 2.07 2263 0.009 3.84 (1) Number Regular Donors Churches & Schools Cold rentals Cold rentals are a donation. 8312 0.004 2.11 newsletter recipients who have never made Table 8: Excluding churches, schools, and cold rentals (6) (5) (4) (3) (2) (1) Response At least C5 At least £10 At least £15 At least 620 At least £25 Choice 0.012 0.005 0.015 0.002 -0.012 -0.003 (0.024) (0.026) (0.019) (0.014) (0.011) (0.009) Log of previous 0.103 0.103 0.081 0.043 0.026 0.020 Donations (0.005)** (0.004)** (0.003)** (0.002)** (0.002)** (0.002)** -0.004 Choice * Log of -0.002 -0.008 -0.001 0.003 0.000 prev. donations (0.006) (0.006) (0.005) (0.003) (0.003) (0.002) Constant -0.145 -0.180 -0.176 -0.107 -0.064 -0.051 (0.019)** (0.017)** (0.014)** (0.010)** (0.008)** (0.007)** Observations 8139 8139 8139 8139 8139 8139 R-squared 0.11 0.12 0.11 0.07 0.05 0.04 This table excludes all churches, schools, and cold rentals (newsletter recipients who have never made a donation). The dependent variables are whether the experimental donation was above the given cutoff amount (0, £5, £10, £15, £20, or 625) and the regressors are choice, the log of total previous donations since 2001, and the interaction of these two variables. Standard errors are in parentheses. * significant at 5%; ** significant at 1% Table 9: Basic regressions of donations made in the year after the experiment Choice Prior donations Log of prior Donations Prior donations greater than zero Choice * Prior Donations (1) Donation amount 0.057 (0.610) (2) Donation amount -0.041 (0.503) 115.175 (1.307)** (3) Donation amount 0.569 (0.679) 147.109 (1.968)** 0.640 (0.010)** 4.127 (0.527)** 1.118 (0.741) -56.059 (2.608)** Choice * Log prior donations Choice * Prior don. greater than zero (4) Log donation amount -0.001 (0.019) 5.122 (1.041)** -0.977 (0.044)** -0.004 (0.015) 0.014 (0.062) 0.47 0.32 0.34 R-squared 0.00 Standard errors are in parentheses. There are 19,122 observations in each column. * significant at 5%; ** significant at 1% Table 10: Whether gave above cutoffs after the experiment (3) Any donation Choice -0.000 (0.006) 0.140 Log of previous Donations (0.003)** 0.002 Choice*Log ofprev. Donations (0.005) -0.062 Donated before (0.014)** Choice*Donated -0.001 Before (0.020) -0.002 Constant (0.005) 19122 Observations 0.42 R-squared Standard errors in parentheses * significant at 5%; ** significant at 1% At least 65 -0.000 (0.006) 0.150 (0.003)** 0.000 (0.005) -0.118 (0.014)** 0.003 (0.019) -0.001 (0.005) 19122 0.42 At least 610 -0.001 (0.006) 0.167 (0.003)** 0.001 (0.004) -0.250 (0.013)** 0.002 (0.018) -0.000 (0.005) 19122 0.42 (4) At least 625 -0.000 (0.005) 0.146 (0.003)** -0.002 (0.004) -0.336 (0.011)** 0.008 (0.015) 0.001 (0.004) 19122 0.34 (5) At least 650 -0.000 (0.004) 0.093 (0.002)** -0.007 (0.003)** -0.243 (0.008)** 0.018 (0.012) 0.002 (0.003) 19122 0.22 (6) At least 6100 0.000 (0.002) 0.040 (0.001)** -0.003 (0.002) -0.113 (0.005)** 0.007 (0.008) 0.002 (0.002) 19122 0.10 Chapter 3 Schelling Revisited: Historic Discrimination, the Desire for Diversity, and Current Segregation with Elizabeth Ananat 1 Introduction In the United States, residential areas are overwhelmingly segregated by race. This fact has been blamed for many economic phenomena, including higher rates of poverty and joblessness among African-Americans (cf. Kain, 1968; 1992) and poor education (cf. Orfield and Eaton, 1996). Segregation is also, however, an economically interesting fact in its own right, because the existing racial distribution of neighborhoods does not offer the integrated areas for which a significant number of Americans express preferences. What, then, causes segregation? Is segregation a market failure, in which the play of individual preferences cannot create the equilibrium that individuals prefer? Is it a result of inertia, caused by a past in which institutions created and maintained segregation? Does it result from contemporary discrimination by some market agents, who prevent others from realizing their preferences? In what follows, we create a model of this process of segregation in order to answer these questions. Thomas Schelling's now canonical model of segregation predicts that if people have (even quite mild) preferences to live with some people like themselves, they will end up quite severely segregated from people who are unlike themselves. The vastly increased computing power (and data on preferences) that has become available since 1971 allows us to study the effects of different preferences, of past discrimination, and of current discrimination in creating the high levels of segregation we see today by expanding on Schelling's model. It also allows us to study the impact of a potential government policy designed to foster integration. We find that accounting for the effects of past discrimination decreases the amount of integration in equilibrium by almost half. This effect, in general, dominates the effects of varying preferences and the fraction of the population with given characteristics and preferences. In the absence of historical discrimination, current discrimination also has powerful effects on the level of integration in equilibrium. Combining current and historical discrimination leads to a very interesting conclusion: historical discrimination has caused such high levels of current segregation that current discrimination has very little effect. This is because segregation was so severe in 1970 that 70% of neighborhoods were at least 99% white, and in our model blacks do not want to move into any of those neighborhoods, so the fact that they would be discriminated against if they wanted to buy a house there is unimportant. Finally, we examine a potential policy and find that it increases the ability of those who desire integration to form integrated neighborhoods, thereby increasing utility. By expanding upon Schelling's original model, we are thus able to learn a great deal more about residential racial segregation, and the role of current and historical discrimination and people's changing preferences for segregation and integration in maintaining segregation. In contrast to Schelling, we find that rather than being the natural outcome of market forces, the severe levels of segregation we see today are the result of sub-optimally high levels of segregation imposed by historic discrimination. In addition, eliminating current discrimination will not be sufficient to get the nation out of this high-segregation equilibrium; an activist policy would be necessary to create the higher level of integration that would have resulted from a wellfunctioning market in the absence of historical discrimination. The paper is laid out as follows: section 2 discusses the history of discrimination, section 3 describes the Schelling model, section 4 shows how our model builds on the Schelling model, section 5 describes the simulations, section 6 gives the results, and section 7 concludes. 2 The Makings of American Segregation In 1890, African-Americans in the northern U.S. were only slightly more segregated from native-born whites than were European immigrants. Using a dissimilarity index, a conventional measure of segregation that ranges from 0 to 100 and on which 60 is considered high, neither blacks, at an average of 46, nor foreign-born whites faced highly segregated conditions in h 19t century northern cities. And in the South, where blacks lived in alleys and byways interspersed between blocks of white-owned mansions, segregation was even lower. Moreover, in 1890 place of residence was determined by class and not race. The two were of course highly correlated, but those African-Americans who did amass wealth took residence in neighborhoods of other wealthy people, meaning for the most part neighborhoods that were predominantly white (Massey and Denton 1993). By 1940, however, the northern dissimilarity index averaged around 80, nearly double what it had been 50 years earlier; southern cities experienced similar increases in segregation. Cutler, Glaeser, and Vigdor (1999) find that by their definition only one city (Indianapolis) had a "ghetto" in 1890; in 1940, 55 cities did. And segregation ceased to be a function of economic class (Sims, 1999). What happened to cause such dramatic increases in the separation of blacks and whites? In their 1993 book American Apartheid, Douglas Massey and Nancy Denton explain in compelling detail how this radical shift occurred. In the first two decades of the 2 0th century, as significant numbers of blacks migrated to Northern cities in search of industrial jobs and greater civil liberties, whites responded with riots and murders targeting African-Americans who lived outside black areas. After the violence exhausted itself, whites turned heavily to the nonviolent but perhaps more effective "restrictive covenant," a type of collective agreement that prevented whites in a neighborhood from selling houses to blacks. By the time such agreements were ruled unenforceable by the Supreme Court in 1948, the federal government had institutionalized segregation through its lending practices: the Federal Housing Administration, which both made loans and set norms for private lenders, had instituted the practice of "redlining," in which almost no loans went to neighborhoods with even small percentages of black residents; moreover, the government still afforded no protection for victims of explicit housing discrimination. In 1968 the civil rights movement brought about the Fair Housing Act, and the housing market became for the first time, if in many ways only ostensibly, a place where individual preferences determined outcomes. But by that time, 70 years of implicit and explicit government policy of enforcing segregation had left its very visible mark on the composition of neighborhoods throughout the United States. Subsequently, segregation has changed very little. The average metropolitan dissimilarity index for African-Americans, which hovered around an average of 80 in 1970 (Cutler et al. 1999), had fallen to about 65 by 2000-still highly segregated-but that fall was driven almost entirely by cities with very low black populations. The cities where the majority of blacks live tend also to be those that are the most segregated, and in those cities the segregation indexes not only were higher at the beginning of the ostensibly free housing market, but also have fallen by much less (Mumford, 2001). This stagnation does not appear to be driven by an African-American preference for selfsegregation, however. The modal ideal neighborhood among African-Americans has been 50% white ever since the question was first asked in the 1976 Detroit Area Study (Farley and Schuman, 1976). Moreover, according to results from the 1994 Multi-City Study of Urban Inequality (Bobo et al., 1994), some 20% of African-Americans would be unwilling to move into an all-black neighborhood, while some 40% would be willing to move into an all-white neighborhood. And the major explanatory factor for black unwillingness to move into all-white neighborhoods is concern about white intolerance (Krysan and Farley, 2002). Over the same time period, white attitudes have become consistently more prointegration. White support for the right of whites to keep blacks out of their neighborhoods if they want has fallen from 47% in 1970 to 13% in 1996. On the level of personal preferences, in 1976 58% of whites stated a preference for living in a mostly- or all-white neighborhood, while 20 years later that figure had fallen to 43% (Schuman et al., 1997). Nonetheless, there is still substantial evidence of discrimination against AfricanAmericans. This includes institutional discrimination, in the form of discriminatory lending (Goering and Wienk, 1996) and real estate marketing practices (Galster 1992) as well as preference-based decentralized discrimination, in the form of the premium paid by whites to avoid living in black areas (Cutler et al, 1999). 3 The Schelling Model In 1971, Thomas Schelling developed several models with similar implications that became the canonical economic wisdom on segregation. In the simplest of these, using nickel and penny "agents" on a table, he demonstrated that, given random initial conditions, agents with relatively modest preferences for being with at least some agents like themselves would soon be severely segregated from those unlike themselves. He intended this model to be general enough that it could be applied to many types of segregation, but in the paper he applied it specifically to racial segregation in housing in the U.S. In his model, each nickel or penny represented a household: one type of coin represented whites, the other blacks. A household was either happy or unhappy, depending on the color of its immediate neighbors. If some portion of its neighbors were the same color as it, it was happy. Schelling randomly placed nickels and pennies on a grid, leaving 25 to 30 percent of the spaces empty. He then went through the grid and moved each unhappy household to the nearest empty space where it would be happy. He continued the moving process until nobody was movingi.e., either every household was happy or unhappy households could not be made happy in any vacant spot. Figure 1, a replication of Schelling, shows the severe segregation that results from ingroup preferences of 50% enacted in an initially random, well-integrated grid. Here, many people have no neighbors of the opposite color at all, so the average household has many more neighbors of their own color than they require to be happy. Figure 1. Schelling's finding has frequently been taken by economists to mean that American racial segregation results from the market expression of reasonable individual preferences, and thus that there is little economics to justify policy intervention in housing. To the extent that economists have viewed segregation as a problem, then, their focus tends to be either on continuing institutional discrimination (either in lending or in real estate markets) or on waiting for neighborhoods to change as in-group preferences erode.4 4 Our Model Our basic model differs from the Schelling model in two basic ways: the definition of neighborhood and the description of preferences. We then expand upon this basic model to explore the effects of both past and current discrimination, and to evaluate a policy proposal. 4.1 Constructing neighborhoods In the Schelling model, as in most agent-based models, an agent's neighborhood consists solely of immediate neighbors. By contrast, in our model we define neighborhoods as fixed squares composed of 100 homes, because survey data indicate that this is how respondents view neighborhoods. Lee and Campbell (1997) conclude, in their study of survey respondents' neighborhood definitions, that "[m]ost people use the word [neighborhood] to refer to a territorial unit." Moreover, they find that the vast majority of urban residents identify their 4 In general, there has not been much attention paid to empirically testing the Schelling model and its implications; we are aware of only one macro (rather than case-study) examination. Easterly (2003) uses U.S. data to test the tipping point implication of the mathematical version of Schelling's model, which allows for a continuum of nonisolation preferences; he finds little support for simple tipping as a description of neighborhood racial change in the U.S. neighborhood using a modal neighborhood name (e.g. SoHo or Beverly Hills)-regardless of where in that neighborhood they live. Such an understanding of neighborhoods also underlies the questions asked in MCSUI, where preferences are assumed to depend on non-adjacent houses. Prior to our current set of simulations, we tested the effect of this change on an otherwise classic Schelling model with in-group preferences of 50%. Figure 2 shows the result of basing utility on fixed neighborhood composition-here, agents' utility is a function of the composition of the quadrant of the grid in which they reside. This leads to complete segregation, even more severe than in the classic model. Figure 2. With milder in-group preferences, the model becomes much more sensitive to initial conditions: for some preferences stability is reached either at complete segregation or at complete integration, depending on the initial random distribution. Such extreme results and severe dependence on initial conditions do not mirror what we see in the real world, so on its own this modification does not make the predictions of the Schelling model more realistic. 4.2 Constructingpreferences Schelling's model assumed that people were indifferent between a neighborhood that was 100% in-group and one that was 50% in-group: the only thing Schelling agents care about is being with enough members of their own group. They get no value out of living with out-group members. Put yet another way, in the Schelling model no one places value on diversity; thus, it is not surprising that the resulting neighborhoods are not diverse. However, this model of preferences is belied by all available survey data. As discussed in section II, the modal preferred neighborhood for African-Americans is 50% white. Moreover, a significant minority of white Americans would be unwilling to move into an all-white neighborhood, preferring neighborhoods with a non-zero black presence. Because of this, we update the preferences in the model, basing them on data from the Multi-City Study of Urban Inequality (Bobo et al., 1994). MCSUI is a study of more than 8,500 households in Boston, Detroit, Atlanta, and Los Angeles that asked whites and blacks about their preferences over neighborhood racial composition. They were each shown a set of flashcards depicting 15 houses-three rows of five-with the middle house in the middle row indicating their home and with each other house colored either white or black to depict the race of its residents. Unfortunately, whites and blacks were not shown flashcards with the same series of white/black ratios, nor were they asked the same questions about their preferences; nonetheless, we have been able to construct a reasonable set of preferences from the available data. Whites were shown one card with each of the following racial compositions: 14 white houses, 13 white houses and one black house, 11 white houses and three black houses, 9 white and 5 black, and 6 white and 8 black. They were asked: Suppose you have been looking for a house and have found a nice one you can afford. This house could be located in several different types of neighborhoods, as shown on these cards. Would you consider moving into any of these neighborhoods? If they say yes, they are then asked to hand to the interviewer the cards for all the neighborhoods they would be willing to move into. We used a very strict measure for identifying white respondents as "integrationists": they not only had to be willing to move into neighborhoods with non-zero proportions of African-Americans, they had to be unwilling to move into an all-white neighborhood. That is, we required that their utility be clearly increasing over some range of African-American presence. Three percent of white respondents met this criterion. However, this approach does not take into account that utility may also increase over some range of African-American presence among those who would be willing to live in an allwhite neighborhood-a group that includes not only those who say they would be unwilling to live in neighborhoods with high proportions of African-Americans, but also those who state that they would be willing to live in all of the neighborhoods shown. Eighty-seven percent of respondents, for example, stated that they would be willing to move into a neighborhood with 1 black and 13 white houses; 42 percent would be willing to move into the highest percentageblack neighborhood they were shown. Certainly it is unlikely that all of these respondents have increasing utility over some range of African-American presence; it seems equally unlikely, however, that none of these respondents do. We thus make for our model the quite conservative assumption that half of integrationists reveal themselves through our mechanism and half do not-i.e., that the true percentage of whites who are integrationist is 6%. Among integrationist whites, preference patterns bifurcate. Recall that white respondents were asked about neighborhoods that range from 0/14 to 8/14 black; for half (50.7%) of integrationists, as the proportion black starts to increase they become willing to enter the neighborhood, but at higher proportions they become unwilling. The other half, however, never become unwilling over the observed range. Based on their responses to a separate, "ideal neighborhood" question, we impute that their preferences mirror those of black integrationists, whose preferences we observe over the full range of neighborhoods. Thus in our model we have two types of white integrationists: those whose utility declines prior to the midpoint of the racial distribution we call "mild integrationists," and those whose preferences look like those of black integrationists we call "full integrationists." The utility function of mild integrationists is based on taking the median of the length of the interval of neighborhoods that the integrationist whites are willing to move into, and assuming that their ideal neighborhood is halfway between the endpoints of that interval. Their utility thereby peaks at 4.5 black neighbors, and is higher for no black neighbors than for more than 9. As with all of our agents, their utility is normalized to have a minimum of 0 and a maximum of 1 and is assumed to be piecewise linear. Figure 3 shows the preferences we generated for mild integrationists. Figure 3. Utility of Mild Integrationists I 0.8 0.6 0.40.2A v 1 Race % Same Race % Same Race % Same lOO 100 10 Black respondents were shown one card with each of the following racial compositions: 14 black houses, 10 black houses and 4 white houses, 7 black houses and 7 white houses, 2 black and 12 white, and 14 white. They were asked: Suppose you have been looking for a house and have found a nice one you can afford. This house could be located in several different types of neighborhoods, as shown on these cards. Would you look through the cards and rearrange them so that the neighborhood that is the *most* attractive to you is on top, the next most attractive second, and so on down the line with the least attractive on the bottom. Roughly one-quarter (22.5%) of African-American respondents placed the all-black neighborhood first. Among these respondents, the average ranking of each other neighborhood fell as the percentage black in that neighborhood fell--we classify these respondents as isolationist blacks. Isolationists, both white and black, have preferences that are monotonically decreasing over percent other race. Figure 4 shows the utility function that we assigned them. Figure 4 Utility of Isolationists 1 0.8 0.6 0.4 0.2 0 %Other Race 100 Among the black respondents who did not rank the all-black neighborhood first, the 7 black:7 white neighborhood had the highest average ranking, the 10:4 neighborhood ranked second, the 2:12 neighborhood third, the 14:0 neighborhood fourth, and the 0:14 neighborhood fifth. We only know the relative rankings of these 5 neighborhoods from these responses, and the relative utility of the differently ranked points turn out to affect the results of our model. Thus in our simulations we vary the values of X and Y, where X is the utility of a neighborhood that is 1/14 the other race and Y is the utility of a neighborhood that is 13/14 the other race. In Figure 5 are two examples of full integrationist utility functions showing different pairs of X, Y values. On the left, X is much higher than Y, so that neighborhoods with very low percentages other race will be preferred to those with compositions even slightly over 50% other race. On the right, X is quite close to Y, so that neighborhoods closer to the midpoint tend to be preferred to neighborhoods with more same-race residents. In our simulations, we allow the X value to vary between .35 and .75, while the Y value varies between .3 and .65; Y is constrained to be less than or equal to X. The X and Y values of the white full integrationists vary independently from the X and Y values of the black integrationists. Figure 5. Utility of Integrationists, Version Utility of Integrationists, Version 1 I 1 I- 0.8 0.8 - 0.6 0.6 - 0.4 0.4 - 0.2 0.2 - 0 1 % Other Race I 100 X Y 0 I 1 % Other Race 100 4.3 Constructingthe simulation At the beginning of a simulation, 1750 agents are randomly assigned a type. They have a 3% probability of being an isolationist black, a 9% probability of being an integrationist black, a 2.64% chance of being a full integrationist white, a 2.64% chance of being a mild integrationist white, and an 82.7% chance of being an isolationist white. They are then randomly assigned to a neighborhood. Once all of the agents have been created and assigned a home, they begin to move. In each period, agents are randomly assigned a move order, and the period ends when each agent has had the opportunity to move. Moving is costless, and agents always move to the neighborhood that offers them the highest utility and has a space available, unless no neighborhood offers higher utility than their current neighborhood. The simulation ends when an entire period passes where no agent has moved-i.e., each agent's utility is maximized over current vacancies and neighborhood compositions, so the simulation has stabilized. (For a more detailed explanation of the simulations, see the Appendix.) 4.4 Extension One : Historic Discrimination The Schelling model and our basic model assume that preferences play out within an initially random racial distribution. However, we know that the residential distribution in 1970-around the time that individual preferences were first allowed to have relatively free reign in the housing market-was anything but random. Rather, as discussed in section II, decades of financial discrimination, restrictive covenants, and intimidation had created a highly stratified system of neighborhoods. We thus extend our model to explore the impact of past discrimination by assigning agents to their initial houses according to the 1970 U.S. metropolitan distribution of racial compositions, as shown in the Appendix in Table A.1, rather than randomly; we refer to this as the "historical distribution." 4.5 Extension Two: CurrentDiscrimination The basic model also abstracts away from any current discrimination that may exist, so we extend our model to include the possibility that discrimination remains in the housing market. In the baseline model, there are no limits on which neighborhood agents can move into--they simply move to the neighborhood that maximizes their utility. In reality, however, people can be kept out of neighborhoods: the Urban Institute recently conducted two studies for the Department of Housing and Urban Development that both found significant discrimination in housing markets by real estate and rental agents as well as loan officers (Turner et. al. 2002a, Turner et. al. 2002b). In particular, the realtor study illustrates a discriminatory mechanism that is straightforward to incorporate into our model. That study, which took place in 2000, involved sending one minority and one white person to pose as otherwise identical homeseekers while visiting realtors. The auditors faced discriminatory treatment in both the rental market and the sales market--whites received more information, had more opportunities to inspect apartments and homes, and were more likely to be shown houses in predominantly white neighborhoods. In fact, geographic steering was found to have increased since the last study in the series, which occurred in 1989. We model this process by giving black agents who attempt to move to majority-white neighborhoods a probability of being rejected. As shown in Figure 6, this probability starts at zero, for neighborhoods that are 50% white, and increases quadratically with the percentage white. We vary Z, the probability that a black agent is rejected from an all-white neighborhood, from 10% to 100%; in the simulations that assume no current discrimination, Z is implicitly set to O. Figure 6 Probability a Black Agent is Rejected 1 0.8 Z 0.6 0.4 0.2 0 1 %White 100 4.6 Extension Three: A Policy Experiment Suppose if a neighborhood contains at least 25% blacks and 25% whites the government considers it to be an integrated neighborhood, and the government gives all integrated neighborhoods a payment of some sort. They might do this by subsidizing the construction and running of a community center or some other good that everyone can use. And suppose that a neighborhood that switches from being integrated to being segregated immediately loses the subsidy. In this set of simulations, we model such a policy by assuming that this subsidy increases the utility of everyone in every integrated neighborhood by an equal amount S.5 Such a subsidy will make the integrated neighborhoods much more desirable. We do not want the subsidy to be 5 This assumption may not be very believable in the case of a community center. It would apply better to a subsidy that would be given to every resident, such as a refundable tax credit. We would not expect a policy of giving money directly to people simply because they live in the right kind of neighborhood to be politically palatable, however. Subsidizing a community center would seem to be a more feasible policy. so large, however, that isolationists will want to live in integrated neighborhoods. It is optimal for the isolationists to stay in their isolated neighborhoods, since that is where their utility has its optimum that is where they want to be; the purpose of the policy is simply to encourage the creation of integrated neighborhoods for those who desire them. The difference in an isolationist's utility of a completely segregated neighborhood and one that is 25% other race is 0.523, so the levels of subsidy we examine range from zero to 0.5. 5 The Simulations Run 5.1 Main Simulations The main set of simulations comprise 42,665 runs, and some summary statistics for them are shown in column 1 of Table 1. The first statistic here shows that exactly half of the simulations are run from an initially random distribution and half from the segregated distribution that takes into account institutionalized racism before 1970. We run simulations fully exploring the effects of variation in the preference parameters within each type; each Y value varies independently between 0.3 and 0.65 and each X value varies independently between .35 and 0.75. 5.2 CurrentDiscrimination Column 2 of Table 1 shows that these simulations were done mainly in the context of historical discrimination, although ¼ of them were done from an initially random distribution. Current discrimination varied from 0 to 1, concentrated more in the lower end of this range, generating an average discrimination level of 0.25. Panel A shows that, as discussed above, we restricted ourselves to conservative parameter values after exploring the full range in the main body of simulations, so here the Y value remains at the minimum value, .3, while the X value varies within the top end of the range, 0.65 to 0.75, which means we restrict our full integrationists to have relatively weak desire for integration. 5.3 Subsidy Now looking at column 3 of Table 1 we can see that all of the subsidy simulations were done using the segregated initial distribution, current discrimination varies evenly between 0 and 1, and the subsidy level varies evenly between 0 and 0.5. Just as for the discrimination simulations, the Y value is fixed at 0.3 and the X values vary within the upper range, although in this case it is a slightly broader range, from 0.6 to 0.75, which once again means we restrict our full integrationists to have relatively weak desire for integration. 5.4 Percentof each type of agent In our model, we designed the simulations to be 82.7% isolationist whites, 2.64% mild integrationist whites, 2.64% full integrationist whites, 9% integrationist blacks, and 3% isolationist blacks. Panel B of table 1 shows that the numbers are not exactly as planned: we have the right number of mild integrationist whites and of both integrationist and isolationist blacks, but there are slightly too many full integrationist whites and slightly too few white isolationists. The problem is most severe for the subsidy simulations but exists in each of the three datasets; this imbalance results from a small mistake in the computer code which needs to be corrected, and we will take this error into account in the discussion of the results. 5.5 Outcomes Our outcome variables are the percentages of integrationist agents who find stably integrated neighborhoods to live in. A neighborhood is defined as stably integrated if it contains at least one white and one black household at the end of the simulation. Any neighborhood that contains at least one of each will contain significant numbers of each, because none of our agents are very happy in a neighborhood where the overwhelming majority are of the other race. Table 2 shows some summary statistics for these outcomes: in the main simulations, which incorporate past but not current discrimination, 70% of full integrationists live in integrated neighborhoods, and almost 20% of mild integrationists do. This is a much higher percentage than would have been predicted by Schelling's original models. The percentages are much lower in the other columns; this is partially because they incorporate current as well as past discrimination, and partly because they make more conservative assumptions regarding desire for integration. We identify the effects of each of these variables below. 6 Results 6.1 HistoricalDiscrimination Table 3 shows the coefficient on whether the simulation began from the historical initial condition in eight different regressions. Columns 1 and 2 show regressions where the dependent variable is the percentage of white mild integrationists who live in integrated neighborhoods, columns 3 and 4 show the percentage of white full integrationists, columns 5 and 6 show the percentage of black full integrationists, and columns 7 and 8 show the percentage of all integrationist agents. Columns 1, 3, 5, and 7 show the regressions without controls, and columns 2, 4, 6, and 8 show the regressions with controls. (The controls will be described in detail in the following section.) Columns 1 and 2 show that including the controls changes the coefficient on the initial distribution from a very significant positive to a very significant negative for the white mild integrationists; controlling for the other variables is very important to understanding the impact of past discrimination on mild integrationists. In addition, with all controls, the historic discrimination only lowers the percent of mild integrationists living in integrated neighborhoods by 1.28 percentage points. Both of these results contrast with the results in columns 3 to 6, where we see that the past discrimination lowers the percentage of full integrationists who are able to live in integrated neighborhoods by over 30 percentage points, although adding all of the controls does lower the coefficient significantly (in absolute value). This is an almost 50% reduction from the mean of 70% of full integrationists living in integrated neighborhoods. 6.2 Controls Table 4 shows the effects of each of our control variables. Panel A shows the effects of the preference parameters on their own, and then the ratio of the X value to the Y value-a higher X-Y ratio means a higher preference for a neighborhood that is a majority of your race over a neighborhood that is a majority the other race. Panel B shows the effect of the percent of each type of agent, where the omitted category is white isolationists. Panel C shows the effect of the squares of these percentages. Panel D shows the effect of the interactions of the percent of each of the full integrationist types and their X- and Y-values. There are several conclusions that can be drawn from this table. First, the control variables all have almost exactly the same effect of the percent of full integrationist blacks and the percent of full integrationist whites who live in integrated neighborhoods; there are no statistically significant differences in the coefficients in columns 3 and 4. So we can talk about the effect of a variable on the percentage of full integrationists who live in integrated neighborhoods, rather than discussing blacks and whites separately. Second, in almost all of the variables in this table have a significant effect on the percentage integrated of full integrationists; the squares and interactions are highly significant, so the simple linear regression would have given a very inadequate picture of the process. However, the importance of these nonlinear functions of the variables makes it difficult to directly interpret the coefficients. We have thus created table 4a to show the effects more transparently; it shows what happens when each variable is increased a small amount from its mean and all others are kept at their mean. The values shown are the percentage point change in the percent living in integrated neighborhoods; the percent of white mild integrationists in column 1 and of black full integrationists in column 2. The first four rows show the effect of increasing each preference parameter by 0.1 from a mean of either 0.62 (X) of 0.43 (Y). The white preference parameters have a much larger impact than the black preference parameters, and they all have larger impacts on the full integrationists than on the mild integrationists. In increase of 0.1 in the white X value decreases the percentage of black full integrationists living in integrated neighborhoods by over 1 percentage point and an increase in the white Y value increases it by over 1 percentage point. Both of these mean, not surprisingly, that the more integrationist the integrationist whites are, the more agents will be able to live in integrated neighborhoods. The last four rows show the effect of increasing the percent of each type, other than white isolationists, by their standard deviation, and decreasing the percent of white isolationists by the same amount; this is the effect of switching some agents from white isolationists to these other types. The type that has by far the largest impact per percentage point change is white full integrationists-the overall impact is somewhat larger for black integrationists, but since this is a much larger group, their standard deviation is over double any of the others. Switching 0.6 percent of the agents from being white isolationists to being white full integrationists increases the percent of white mild integrationists living in integrated neighborhoods by 2.4 percentage points but decreases the percent of black full integrationists living in such neighborhoods by 7.8 percentage points. This means that as the number of white full integrationists increase, the integrated neighborhoods have enough white agents in them that they draw in the mild integrationists and thus push out many full integrationists. Since in our simulations we accidentally created too many full integrationist whites and not enough isolationist whites, putting those two back to where they should be would decrease the percent of white mild integrationists living in integrated neighborhoods but increase the percent of full integrationists in integrated neighborhoods. Finally, the control variables impact the fraction of white mild integrationists who get integrated very differently than the fraction of either full integrationist types. In panel A, only the white agents' preference parameters change the white mild integrationist percent integrated, the black preferences don't matter, while for the full integrationists they are all important. On the other hand, panel B shows that only the percent of each black types matters for the mild integrationists, while the percent of all types matter for the full integrationists. This may be because the important factor is whether there are enough black integrationists that there are some who will not fit in the fully integrationist neighborhood(s) with the full integrationist whites and are thus willing to form a somewhat integrated neighborhood with a majority of mild integrationist whites. The black integrationist exact preferences do not matter as much, because they will almost always prefer living in a neighborhood with a mix that will make the mild integrationists happy to living in an all-black neighborhood. 6.3 CurrentDiscrimination Table 5 shows the effect of current discrimination in two cases: starting from a random initial distribution of households, and starting from a segregated distribution of households. First focusing on the results when the simulation is run with the random initial distribution, current discrimination appears to be even more powerful than past discrimination-the highest level of discrimination (when the parameter Z = 1) results in, on average, over 80 percentage points fewer of the full integrationist households living in integrated neighborhoods. From a mean of 70%, this essentially brings it down to zero. The effects are of a similar relative magnitude for the white mild integrationists and all integrationists overall, and this is true whether or not the controls are included. The results for the simulations run from the segregated initial distribution are very different: here, discrimination is never significant. It seems that when past discrimination has already created a significant number of highly segregated neighborhoods, whether or not there is currently any discrimination is unimportant; thus, in the absence of government intervention, this model suggests that sub-optimally high levels of segregation, imposed by past institutionalized discrimination, will remain. 6.4 A Policy Experiment There are many possible policies that could correct for the effects of past discrimination and allow the creation of optimal levels of integration. Our model has limited scope for studying the impact of such policies, but one policy that we can evaluate takes the form of a subsidy to integrated neighborhoods. Table 6 shows the effects of this subsidy. Comparing the coefficients here to the values in Table 3 shows that the effects of the maximum subsidy, 0.5, almost exactly counteract the effects of historical discrimination (except for in the case of white mild integrationists, who are more likely to be able to live in an integrated neighborhood with the presence of the full subsidy than they would have been in the absence of both the subsidy and past discrimination.) This suggests that there may in fact be government policies that could correct for the negative effects of past discrimination on people's ability to achieve their desired level of racial integration. 7 Conclusion By extending and modifying the simple framework developed by Thomas Schelling, we have created a model of U.S. residential segregation that has several important implications. We find that the strength of preferences for integration and the number of agents of each racial and integration preference type have complex effects on the percent of integrationists who are able to live in integrated neighborhoods. One simple result is that the more integrationist the full integrationist whites are, the more agents will be able to live in integrated neighborhoods; the preferences of the integrationist whites have a much stronger impact than those of the integrationist blacks. Another is that the more white full integrationist whites there are, the lower the percent of full integrationists (both white and black) who find integrated neighborhoods to live in, but higher the percent of white mild integrationists who do; this is because when there are more integrationist whites, the integrated neighborhoods will be a higher fraction white, so the mild integrationists will be more comfortable there. Unfortunately, this means they push out some full integrationists. In addition, we find that historic segregation impedes diversity-seeking agents from achieving the integration they desire. Indeed, the legacy of past discrimination is such a powerful force against integration that it appears to make current discrimination somewhat irrelevant in maintaining segregation. Because this legacy is in part the result of past government action, and because this high level of segregation is sub-optimal both for individual preferences and for many social outcomes, government action to counter the effects of past segregation appears appropriate. We studied one simple version of possible government action, and found that it could be successful in facilitating integration in historically segregated environments, making individuals better off. Appendix: Executing the Simulations Our model was written using Repast, a set of Java libraries made to be used in developing agent-based models in Java. Each agent in the model is one of five types: white isolationist, white mild integrationist, white full integrationist, black isolationist and black full integrationist. Each agent lives on a 50 x 50 grid of squares, where each square represents a house. This grid is divided into a 5 x 5 grid of neighborhoods, each of which is made up of a 10 x10 grid of houses. Each type is given piecewise linear preferences as shown in Figure 2. If the x-axis gives percent other race in the agent's neighborhood, we can describe the utility of isolationists with 3 points: (0,1), (21.4,0.5) and (100,0). Mild integrationist preferences are defined by (0, 0.313),(21.4, 0.5), (32.1, 1), (42.9, 0.5) and (100, 0); full integrationist preferences are defined by (0, 0.25), (7.1, X), (50, 1), (85.7, Y), (100,0). X and Y are the parameters described on page 13. There are 2500 houses and the vacancy rate is 30% (following Schelling), so there are 1750 agents. Each agent gets a randomly generated x-coordinate (not to be confused with their assigned utility value X) and a randomly generated y-coordinate. If there is already an agent at that point then a different point is generated; if not, the agent is placed at that point. There are two ways these agents are then given identities: random and historic. In the random distribution, 88% of the agents are white and 12% are black. In the historic distribution each neighborhood is randomly assigned a value for percent black based on the distribution in Table A. 1, which comes from the racial distribution of metropolitan census tracts in 1970 (U.S. Census, 1970). The table divides the interval [0% black, 100% black] into 13 sub-intervals and shows the percentage of neighborhoods which had a percent black in that interval: Table A.1 Percent Percent of Black Neighborhoods 0 40.9 (0,1] 29.7 (1, 10] 7.3 (10,20] 5.5 (20,30] 2.9 (30, 40] 1.8 (40, 50] 1.4 (50, 60] 1.3 (60, 70] 1.3 (70, 80] 1.3 (80, 90] 1.8 (90, 100) 4.5 100 0.4 On the micro level, each agent is then randomly assigned a race based on the macro racial distribution assigned to the agent's initial neighborhood. In both setups, each white agent then has a 94% chance of being isolationist, a 3% chance of being mildly integrationist and a 3% chance of being fully integrationist; each black agent has a 25% chance of being isolationist and a 75% chance of being fully integrationist. The body of the program then consists of the agents moving. In each period, each agent has a chance to move, in a random order. A move consists of three steps. First, the agent determines its current utility, which is the utility for that agent's type given the racial composition of the agent's current neighborhood. Second, the agent looks at the other neighborhoods and determines how many of the other neighborhoods it would be happier in. If it would not be happier in any other neighborhood, it stays where it is. If it would be happier in at least one other neighborhood, it picks a neighborhood to move to. (If it would be happier in more than one other neighborhood, it chooses randomly among them.) Third, the agent randomly chooses a vacant spot in that neighborhood to move to. If there is no vacant spot it does not move. We explore the impact of discrimination by modifying this process. In the second step of the modified moving process, a white agent is able to consider every neighborhood and choose the best one. A black agent, however, may not be allowed to choose some of the majority white neighborhoods. When a black agent is evaluating the neighborhoods, the program generates a random number between 1 and 100 for each majority white neighborhood. If that number is less than f(p), where f(p) is an increasing function of the fraction p of whites in the neighborhood, then the agent is not allowed to consider that neighborhood.. We chose f(p) = 100*4/3*Z(p*p.25) for p >= .5 where Z is the discrimination parameter. This function has the general shape shown in figure 6; it is always 0 at .5 and increases quadratically until it reaches Z at 1. The simulation continues, with each agent getting one chance to move during each period, until there is a period where no agent moves, which is a stable distribution. The data is then collected for that simulation: number of agents of each type, number of integrated neighborhoods, percent of each type living in an integrated neighborhood, average utility of each type, and number of periods necessary to reach stability. When we run simulations for discrimination and subsidy we don't run through all the values of X and Y because we have already explored their effects; we want to study the effects of discrimination and policy in the most realistic context possible. For these sections, we leave Y at 0.3 and vary X from .6 to .75 in steps of .05. These are also the most conservative values to use, because a low Y and a high X makes the agents less integrationist. Because the definition of an integrated neighborhood that is used in the policy simulation is different from the definition used in the data (at least 25% each race, rather than at least one agent of each race), we cannot calculate from the data collected exactly how many agents receive the subsidy at the end of the simulation. For each integrationist type, we took the percent integrated and multiplied that by the subsidy to get an estimate of the average subsidy received by an agent of that type. This is an upper bound estimate, because it assumes that all agents who live in neighborhoods containing at least one agent of each race live in neighborhoods where at least 25% of the residents are of each race and thus receive subsidies; some of these agents might not receive the subsidy, so this is an overestimate of the average subsidy. References Bobo, L,, J. Johnson, M. Oliver, R. Farley, B. Bluestone, I. Browne, S. Danziger, G. Green, H. Holzer, M. Krysan, M. Massagli, C. Charles, J. Kirschenman, P. Moss, and C. Tilly, 1994. Multi-City Study of Urban Inequality. Ann Arbor, MI: Inter-University Consortium for Political and Social Research Study #2535. http://data.fas.harvard.edu Cutler, David, Edward Glaeser, and Jacob Vigdor, 1999. "The Rise and Decline of the American Ghetto," Journalof PoliticalEconomy 107(3): 455-506. Farley, R. and H. Schuman, 1976. Detroit Area Study, 1976: A Study of Metropolitan and Neighborhood Problems. Ann Arbor, MI: Inter-University Consortium for Political and Social Research Study #7906. http://data.fas.harvard.edu Galster, G., 1992. The Metropolis in Black and White. New Brunswick, NY: Center for Urban Policy Research. Goering, J. and R. Wienk (eds.), 1996. MortgageLending, RacialDiscriminationandFederal Policy. District of Columbia: Urban Institute Press. Kain, J., 1968. "Housing Segregation, Negro Employment, and Metropolitan Decentralization," QuarterlyJournalofEconomics 82:175:97. Kain, J., 1992. "The Spatial Mismatch Hypothesis: Three Decades Later." Housing Policy Debate 3(2):371-460. Krysan, Maria and Reynolds Farley, 2002. "The Residential Preferences of Blacks: Do They Explain Persistent Segregation?" Social Forces 80(3): 937-980. Lee, B.A. and K.E. Campbell. "Common ground? Urban neighborhoods as survey respondents see them." Social Science Quarterly 78.4 (1997): 922-936. Lewis Mumford Center. "Ethnic Diversity Grows, Neighborhood Integration Lags Behind." MetropolitanRacial andEthnic Change- Census 2000. 2001. 22 Jul 2002 <http://mumford1.dvndns.org/cen2000/WholePop/WPreport/page1 .html> Massey, D. and N. Denton, 1988. "Residential Segregation of Blacks, Hispanics, and Asians by Socioeconomic Status and Generation," Social Science Quarterly69. Massey, D. and N. Denton, 1993. American Apartheid: Segregation and the Making of the Underclass. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Orfield, G. and S. Eaton, 1996. DismantlingDesegregation:The Quiet Reversal of Brown v. Board ofEducation. New York, NY: W.W. Norton and Company. 100 Schelling, T.C. "Dynamic Models of Segregation." Journalof MathematicalSociology 1(1971): 143-186. Sims, Mario, 1999. "High-Status Residential Segregation among Racial and Ethnic Groups in Five Metro Areas, 1980-1990," Social Science Quarterly80(3): 556-73. St. John, Craig and Robert Clymer, 2000. "Racial Residential Segregation by Level of Socioeconomic Status," Social Science Quarterly81(3): 701-15. Turner, Margery Austin, et. al., 2002a. Discriminationin Metropolitan HousingMarkets: NationalResults from PhaseI HDS 2000. Washington, DC: The Urban Institute. Turner, Margery Austin, et. al., 2002b. All Other Things Being Equal: A PairedTesting Study of MortgageLending Institutions. Washington, DC: The Urban Institute. Yinger, John. 1995. "Opening Doors: How to Cut Discrimination by Supporting Neighborhood Integration." Syracuse University Center for Policy Research Policy Brief No. 3/1995. 101 Table 1: Summary statistics for each of the three sets of simulations-parameters and randomized variables Historical discrimination Current discrimination Subsidy (1) Main Simulations 0.50 (0.002) (2) Current discrimination 0.76 (3) 111 Subsidy 1 (0.006) (0) 0.25 (0.003) 0.5 (0.003) 0.25 (0.002) PanelA: Preferenceparameters White X Black X White Y Black Y White X-Y ratio Black X-Y ratio 0.62 (0.0005) 0.62 (0.0005) 0.43 (0.0005) 0.43 (0.0005) 1.48 (0.002) 1.48 (0.002) 0.69 0.67 (0.0009) (0.0006) 0.69 0.3 0.66 (0.0005) 0.3 (0) (0) (0) (0) (0.0009) 0.3 0.3 PanelB: Percentof each type of agent Pct white Isolationists Pct white mild integrationists Pct white full integrationists Pct black Isolationists Pct black integrationists 82.26 (0.016) 2.64 (0.002) 3.03 (0.005) 3.02 (0.005) 9.05 (0.013) 81.91 81.70 (0.051) 2.63 (0.004) (0.064) 2.64 (0.006) 3.29 (0.009) 3.04 (0.018) 9.11 (0.051) 3.51 (0.005) 3.04 (0.014) 9.12 (0.041) Observations 42,665 4,660 9,240 For each variable used, this shows the mean for each of the three sets of simulations, with standard errors in parentheses 102 V oC o 0) 00 m 0 6Z , 0 00, 0 O 0-. 0 z o C4 co I-- Cl% tr) 00 C- .0 0 ci Ro C' Z 0 0 0 ., G.O0 0nOvf C; 00 Mv W)C1 6t M c - - -4 - , t , f) "' I.. 06400600 N 0N 00 W.- 0 Z ' Ud .. o .8 .L ., tz8 0 Ud u- 0a S0 103 U'Dc ;m.5 Table 4: Effects of controls on the percentage of each type of integrationist agent living in integrated neighborhoods, in simulations with historic discrimination (1) Overall PanelA: Preferenceparameters White X -19.042 Black X White Y Black Y White X-Y Ratio Black X-Y Ratio (2.471)** 8.881 (1.508)** 28.843 (2.633)** -9.575 (1.781)** 4.507 (0.444)** -3.245 (0.445)** (3) (4) White mild White full Black full 48.804 (15.545)** -13.754 (9.548) -123.836 (18.731)** -127.446 (18.644)** 79.672 (11.375)** 185.763 (19.860)** -89.181 (13.433)** 32.315 (3.348)** -28.336 (3.358)** (2) -34.528 (16.525)* 15.420 (11.234) 5.280 (2.782) 0.036 (2.819) PanelB: Percentof each type of agent Pct white mild 0.727 -3.612 Integrationists (1.105) (6.925) Pct white full -5.593 -7.238 Integrationists (1.110)** (6.955) Pct black 2.050 -28.900 Isolationists (1.202) (7.526)** Pct black 2.314 -34.211 Integrationists (1.189) (7.450)** Panel C: Percent of each type of agent,squared Pct white 0.011 -0.138 isolationists, sq (0.040)** (0.006) Pct white mild 0.172 -3.542 integrationists, sq (0.142) (0.887)** Pct white full 1.102 -1.284 integrationists, sq (0.081)** (0.508)* Pct black -0.075 0.814 (0.034)* (0.215)** isolationists, sq Pct black -0.028 0.443 integrationists, sq (0.008)** (0.051)** PanelD: Interactions White X * Pct white full integrationists White Y * Pct white full integrationists Black X * Pct black full integrationists Black Y * Pct black full integrationists -1.895 (0.615)** 0.640 (0.615) 0.213 (0.085)* -0.258 (0.088)** -24.032 (3.872)** 28.068 (3.857)** 0.908 (0.537) -1.444 (0.551)** 82.527 (11.505)** 183.488 (19.912)** -84.585 (13.537)** 30.438 (3.352)** -27.242 (3.397)** 18.733 (8.345)* -53.500 (8.380)** 31.995 (9.069)** 29.290 (8.977)** 22.803 (8.343)** -46.923 (8.378)** 34.458 (9.070)** 31.117 (8.974)** 0.174 0.187 (0.048)** (0.048)** 1.207 (1.068) 11.034 (0.612)** -0.821 (0.259)** -0.183 (0.061)** 1.027 (1.068) 10.676 -15.353 (4.665)** 8.462 (4.648) 1.045 (0.646) -1.772 (0.664)** (0.608)** -0.811 (0.259)** -0.205 (0.061)** -18.091 (4.640)** 10.989 (4.638)* 1.440 (0.639)* -1.434 (0.665)* 21216 20795 Observations 20797 21216 0.1864 0.2056 0.1356 0.2371 R-squared The dependent variable is the percent of each type of integrationist agent who live in integrated neighborhoods. All observations are from the main set of simulations and were run from an initially segregated distribution. Standard errors are in parentheses. * significant at 5%; ** significant at 1% 104 U, 04 0 t 0 o I I t 00 00 I V0 -4 0-0 roo\rc •75 ~ .;N• t~vl 4..- o • eC'J • 00 rn1; og a0 0O Cd Cd0 4- 105 0 Q) ou 0 ~o ;- 0o so oo ag) 106 9 Table 6: The effect of subsidies on the percent of integrationist agents who live in integrated neighborhoods Subsidy Current Discrimination Controls (1) White mild 67.234 (1.803)** -1.215 (0.974) (2) White full 60.322 (1.893)** -1.347 (1.022) (3) Black full 59.753 (1.842)** -3.363 (0.995)** (4) Overall 9.268 (0.252)** -0.305 (0. 136)* Yes Yes Yes Yes Observations 9240 9240 9239 9240 R-squared 0.2216 0.1713 0.2080 0.1491 The dependent variable is the percent of each type of integrationist agent who live in integrated neighborhoods. Each regression includes controls for preference parameters and percentages of each type of agent. These regressions are run using the third set of simulations, which focus on the subsidy. Standard are errors in parentheses. * significant at 5%; ** significant at 1% 107