A graded Bayesian coherence notion Frederik Herzberg Center for Mathematical Economics (IMW), Bielefeld University Munich Center for Mathematical Philosophy, Ludwig Maximilian University of Munich W ORKSHOP ‘F ULL AND PARTIAL B ELIEF ’ ( CO - LOCATED WITH THE 4 TH R ENÉ D ESCARTES L ECTURES ) Tilburg University 21 October 2014 imw Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 1 / 56 Introduction 1 Introduction 2 Formalisation of (the core of) BonJour’s coherence notion Formal framework Formalising BonJour’s first desideratum Formalising BonJour’s second desideratum Formalising BonJour’s third and fourth desiderata 3 Example: BonJour’s “ravens” challenge Preparations for the formalisation of BonJour’s challenge Formalisation of the belief systems Calculation of the third and fourth component of the coherence measure Calculation of graded probabilistic consistency. The second component of the coherence measure Calculation of the first component of the coherence measure Summary 4 Conclusion and discussion imw Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 2 / 56 Introduction Introduction (1) Epistemic (doxastic) justification is a central and ancient topic of theoretical philosophy: I I Can one ever be justified in believing any proposition? If so, what are necessary and/or sufficient conditions? Based on Aristotle’s “regress argument”, it has been argued that there are exactly three non-skeptical views about the structure of epistemic justification (structure of reasons). According to this position, non-skeptical positions on epistemic justification either assert I I I that reasons form a finite chain with some foundational proposition at the base (foundationalism) — illustration: foundation of a house (D ESCARTES); or that reasons mutually support each other (coherentism) — illustration: planks of a boat (N EURATH); or that reasons form an infinite regress (infinitism) — illustration: imw open-ended loop. Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 3 / 56 Introduction Introduction (2) The philosophical discussion on epistemic justification has seen interesting turns during the past two decades: I I I infinitist accounts of epistemic justification were revived (e.g. K LEIN 1998ff; formally: P EIJNENBURG 2007); a major proponent of coherentism abandoned this position (B ON J OUR 1999, 2010) for Cartesianism; impossibility theorems for coherence measures suggest that coherentism defies formalisation (pioneers: K LEIN –WARFIELD 1994), formally reiterating an earlier criticism by E WING (1934). We give a formal defense of coherentism that takes traditional epistemology seriously: I I We propose a class of coherence measures that meet the thrust of BonJour’s desiderata. The domain of these coherence measures will be systems of degrees of belief. (Our own position is a graded version of sufficiency coherentism; it accommodates foundationalist and infinitist intuitions, but rejects imw the Principle of Inferential Justification. H. 2014b) Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 4 / 56 Introduction The (im)possibility of formal coherence concepts (1) There is a rich body of literature, originally closely related to the discussion on epistemological coherentism, on the (im)possibility of a formal graded coherence notion (K LEIN –WARFIELD 1994, 1996; S HOGENJI 1999; A KIBA 2000; F ITELSON 2003; B OVENS –H ARTMANN 2003a,b, 2005, 2006; O LSSON 2002, 2005; D IETRICH –M ORETTI 2005; M EIJS –D OUVEN 2007; S CHUPBACH 2008; S IEBEL –W OLFF 2008). The overall finding of this literature is that it appears to be very difficult to come up with a convincing (especially one-dimensional) graded coherence notion. imw Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 5 / 56 Introduction The (im)possibility of formal coherence concepts (2) However, the recent formal literature on coherence measures I I does not interact closely with the traditional literature on coherentism (e.g. B ON J OUR 1985, L EHRER 2000) and in general models belief systems as sets of propositions endowed with a unique probability measure — a very strong assumption (psychologically and decision-theoretically less than compelling). We suggest a new formal framework which models belief systems as sets of conditional probability assignments, compatible with several (even infinitely many) probability measures; they induce a Bayesian network on the propositions. Within that framework, we propose a formalisation of the thrust of BonJour’s (1985) (multi-dimensional) coherence concept: I I inferential connections and fragmentation are measured through graph-theoretic concepts on the induced Bayesian network; probabilistic consistency is measured via the size of the set of probability measures compatible with the belief system. imw (H. 2014c) Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 6 / 56 Introduction Criteria for a formal graded coherence notion (1) B ON J OUR’s coherence concept provides desiderata for a formal coherence notion: [(I)] A system of beliefs is coherent only if it is logically consistent. [(II)] A system of beliefs is coherent in proportion to its degree of probabilistic consistency. [. . . ] [(III)] The coherence of a system of beliefs is increased by the presence of inferential connections between its component beliefs and increased in proportion to the number and strength of such connections. [(IV)] The coherence of a system of beliefs is diminished to the extent to which it is divided into subsystems of beliefs which are relatively unconnected to each other by inferential connections. imw (B ON J OUR 1985, Section 5.3, pp. 95, 98, 99) Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 7 / 56 Introduction Criteria for a formal graded coherence notion (2) There is, in addition, also a fifth desideratum, which however does not admit a natural formalisation. [(V)] The coherence of a system of beliefs is decreased in proportion to the presence of unexplained anomalies in the believed content of the system. (B ON J OUR 1985, Section 5.3, pp. 95, 98, 99) We propose a class of formal coherence concepts which satisfy the first four of B ON J OUR’s desiderata — and ultimately might be restricted to satisfy a formalisation of the fifth desideratum, too. There are several classes of epistemic anomalies. A local anomaly might be a non-foundational belief with high degree of centrality. A global anomaly might be a belief whose omission from the belief system would result in a substantial reduction in complexity. Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 imw 8 / 56 Introduction Multiplicity of subjective probability measures (priors) Our formal framework allows for belief systems that are compatible with multiple probability measures. This reflects the consensus of contemporary decision theory (and also psychology, cf. e.g. M INSKY 1986 or O RNSTEIN 1986): I I I Building on work by E LLSBERG (1961) and G ILBOA –S CHMEIDLER (1989), decision making under multiple priors or probabilistic ambiguity (uncertainty in the sense of K NIGHT 1921) is studied. There is a body of literature on probabilistic opinion pooling (e.g. M C C ONWAY 1981 and C OOKE 1991). The problem of aggregating probability measures can also be studied within a comprehensive, theory of aggregating propositional attitudes (D IETRICH –L IST 2011). Most recently, these results have been extended: I I A unified methodology for the theory of propositional-attitude aggregation has been proposed, via universal algebra (H. 2014d). The theory of probabilistic opinion pooling has been extended to infinite profiles of priors — a set-theoretically delicate problem imw which can be solved using ultrafilters (H. 2014a). Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 9 / 56 Formalisation of (the core of) BonJour’s coherence notion 1 Introduction 2 Formalisation of (the core of) BonJour’s coherence notion Formal framework Formalising BonJour’s first desideratum Formalising BonJour’s second desideratum Formalising BonJour’s third and fourth desiderata 3 Example: BonJour’s “ravens” challenge Preparations for the formalisation of BonJour’s challenge Formalisation of the belief systems Calculation of the third and fourth component of the coherence measure Calculation of graded probabilistic consistency. The second component of the coherence measure Calculation of the first component of the coherence measure Summary 4 Conclusion and discussion imw Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 10 / 56 Formalisation of (the core of) BonJour’s coherence notion Formal framework 1 Introduction 2 Formalisation of (the core of) BonJour’s coherence notion Formal framework Formalising BonJour’s first desideratum Formalising BonJour’s second desideratum Formalising BonJour’s third and fourth desiderata 3 Example: BonJour’s “ravens” challenge Preparations for the formalisation of BonJour’s challenge Formalisation of the belief systems Calculation of the third and fourth component of the coherence measure Calculation of graded probabilistic consistency. The second component of the coherence measure Calculation of the first component of the coherence measure Summary 4 Conclusion and discussion imw Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 11 / 56 Formalisation of (the core of) BonJour’s coherence notion Formal framework Formal framework for belief systems Our formal framework assumes probabilism — the thesis that assignments of (conditional) degrees of belief have the formal properties of probability measures. (Cf. J OYCE 2009; L EITGEB –P ETTIGREW 2010; E ASWARAN –F ITELSON 2012; F ITELSON –M C C ARTHY 2013; W EDGWOOD 2013.) Fix some algebra A of propositions. A belief system is a set S of triples hA|Bkαi, where A, B ∈ A and α ∈ [0, 1]. Read hA|Bkαi ∈ S as “the belief system S assigns to A, given B, a conditional degree of belief α”. (A is foundational for S if hA|>k1i ∈ S.) A belief system S is probabilistically consistent if and only if there exists a probability measure P : A → [0, 1] such that P(A|B) = α whenever hA|Bkαi ∈ S for any A, B ∈ A and α ∈ [0, 1]. Such a probability measure P is then said to be compatible with S, denoted P ∈ PS . imw Such belief systems can be viewed as Bayesian networks. Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 12 / 56 Formalisation of (the core of) BonJour’s coherence notion Formal framework Infinite regresses as formal belief systems A (recipe for a) probabilistic regress is a pair α, β ∈ [0, 1]N such that αk > βk for all k ∈ N. A recipe for a probabilistic regress is consistent if and only if there exist both a sequence S = hSk ik ∈N ∈ AN and a probability measure P : A → [0, 1] such that for all k ∈ N, 0 < P(Sk +1 ) < 1, P(Sk |Sk +1 ) = αk > βk = P(Sk |{Sk +1 ) (i.e. {hSk |Sk +1 kαk i : k ∈ N} ∪ Sk |{Sk +1 kβk : k ∈ N is consistent). Such a pair hP, Si will be called a model for hα, βi. Put in terms of Bayesian confirmation theory: In a regress, Sk +1 confirms Sk for all k ∈ N — so that S0 is confirmed by S1 , which is confirmed by S2 , which is confirmed by S3 etc. ad infinitum.) imw Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 13 / 56 Formalisation of (the core of) BonJour’s coherence notion Formal framework A graded formal coherence notion (1) We propose a vector-valued coherence measure (H. 2014c): The first component is a binary measure of logical consistency. Herein, a belief system is logically consistent if and only if the intersection of those propositions/events which get assigned a high degree of belief is non-empty. The probabilistic consistency of a belief system is measured via the size of the set of probability measures supporting a belief system. (This set has a distinctive geometrical structure, viz. the intersection of several hyperplanes with a simplex, hence its size can easily be measured as the pair consisting of the H AUSDORFF (1918) dimension and H AUSDORFF measure.) The number of inferential connections can be measured in terms of graph-theoretic notions of connectivity; their strength can be measured using a confirmation function. The fragmentation can be measured in terms of the number of imw maximal connected (proper) subgraphs (components). Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 14 / 56 Formalisation of (the core of) BonJour’s coherence notion Formal framework A graded formal coherence notion (2) This coherence notion is only well-defined for finite belief systems, i.e. finite sets of conditional probability assignments. Using A. R OBINSON’s (1961, 1966) nonstandard analysis, one can extend this real-vector-valued coherence notion for finite belief systems to a hyperreal-vector-valued coherence notion for hyperfinite (“formally finite”) belief systems. Thus, one arrives at a coherence notion which is applicable to certain infinite belief systems defined, in particular hyperfinite probability spaces. Such spaces are extremely rich in a rigorous sense, viz. saturated and universal in the sense of the model theory of stochastic processes (H OOVER –K EISLER 1984; FAJARDO –K EISLER 2002). imw Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 15 / 56 Formalisation of (the core of) BonJour’s coherence notion Formalising BonJour’s first desideratum 1 Introduction 2 Formalisation of (the core of) BonJour’s coherence notion Formal framework Formalising BonJour’s first desideratum Formalising BonJour’s second desideratum Formalising BonJour’s third and fourth desiderata 3 Example: BonJour’s “ravens” challenge Preparations for the formalisation of BonJour’s challenge Formalisation of the belief systems Calculation of the third and fourth component of the coherence measure Calculation of graded probabilistic consistency. The second component of the coherence measure Calculation of the first component of the coherence measure Summary 4 Conclusion and discussion imw Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 16 / 56 Formalisation of (the core of) BonJour’s coherence notion Formalising BonJour’s first desideratum BonJour’s requirement (I) for systems of degrees of belief presupposes a bridge principle between belief simpliciter and degrees of belief. There is still an ongoing debate in formal epistemology on this — cf., e.g., A RLÓ -C OSTA –PARIKH (2005), F OLEY (2009), L EITGEB (2013, 2014) , A RLÓ -C OSTA –P EDERSEN (2012). As a working hypothesis we choose the most well-known bridge principle, viz. the Lockean thesis: belief simpliciter is partial belief to a sufficiently high degree (c, say). This seems problematic because it makes coherence dependent of the threshold c. imw Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 17 / 56 Formalisation of (the core of) BonJour’s coherence notion Formalising BonJour’s first desideratum A very strong parameter-independent version of desideratum (I) would require for logical consistency: η (S, (1/2, 1]) 6= ∅, (1) wherein η(S, I), for all I ⊆ [0, 1], denotes the intersection of all propositions/events to which a probability within I is assigned by all probability measures compatible with S: o \\n η(S, I) := P −1 (I) : P ∈ PS \ = A. A∈A ∀P∈PS P(A)∈I A very weak parameter-independent reading of requirement (I) would only demand: η (S, {1}) 6= ∅. (2) imw Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 18 / 56 Formalisation of (the core of) BonJour’s coherence notion Formalising BonJour’s first desideratum Both requirements expressed in formulae (1) and (2) take an all-or-nothing approach to logical consistency. This is perfectly in line with B ON J OUR’s (1985) position: Logical consistency is a binary component of the multi-faceted, non-binary, graded concept of coherence. We propose to choose the weak requirement, viz. (2): 1, η (S, {1}) 6= ∅ β1 (S) = 0, η (S, {1}) = ∅. This allows for some degree of coherence even in the belief systems of the preface or lottery paradoxes. It avoids the conclusion that most humans hold utterly incoherent belief systems. imw Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 19 / 56 Formalisation of (the core of) BonJour’s coherence notion Formalising BonJour’s second desideratum 1 Introduction 2 Formalisation of (the core of) BonJour’s coherence notion Formal framework Formalising BonJour’s first desideratum Formalising BonJour’s second desideratum Formalising BonJour’s third and fourth desiderata 3 Example: BonJour’s “ravens” challenge Preparations for the formalisation of BonJour’s challenge Formalisation of the belief systems Calculation of the third and fourth component of the coherence measure Calculation of graded probabilistic consistency. The second component of the coherence measure Calculation of the first component of the coherence measure Summary 4 Conclusion and discussion imw Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 20 / 56 Formalisation of (the core of) BonJour’s coherence notion Formalising BonJour’s second desideratum A naïve reading of BonJour’s requirement (II) would look for a measure for the degree of probabilistic consistency of a belief system in our above formal framework. However, if one reads this requirement in context, one finds the following paragraph: Probabilistic consistency differs from straightforward logical consistency in two important respects. First, it is extremely doubtful that probabilistic inconsistency can be entirely avoided. Improbable things do, after all, sometimes happen, and sometimes one can avoid admitting them only by creating an even greater probabilistic inconsistency at another point. Second, probabilistic consistency, unlike logical consistency, is plainly a matter of degree, depending on (a) just how many conflicts the system contains and (b) the degree of improbability involved in each case. (B ON J OUR 1985, p. 95) imw Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 21 / 56 Formalisation of (the core of) BonJour’s coherence notion Formalising BonJour’s second desideratum However, that events which were a priori unlikely do sometimes happen and therefore can enter a belief system a posteriori does not at all constitute probabilistic inconsistency. In our Bayesian framework, probabilistic consistency is already defined in a very natural way — even though as a binary concept: 1, PS 6= ∅ β2 (S) = 0, PS = ∅. That said, it is still interesting whether probabilistic consistency could be a matter of degree. Here, the geometric structure of PS is helpful. One can measure the probabilistic consistency essentially as the H AUSDORFF (1918) dimension and H AUSDORFF measure of PS . imw Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 22 / 56 Formalisation of (the core of) BonJour’s coherence notion Formalising BonJour’s second desideratum Since A ⊆ 2Ω , one can canonically — up to permutations of the coordinates — embed the set ∆ of all probability measures defined on A into [0, 1]card(Ω) by some map ι. The geometric representation of subjective probability measures by ι is the key to our graded notion of probabilistic consistency. We shall measure the size of PS — and hence the probabilistic consistency of the belief system S — by the pair consisting of the H AUSDORFF dimension of the canonical image of PS under ι and its H AUSDORFF measure: D E β̃2 (S) := D (ι[PS ]) , HD(ι[PS ]) (ι[PS ]) , where PS is greater than PS0 if and only if either (i) D (ι[PS ]) > D (ι[PS0 ]) or (ii) D (ι[PS ]) = D (ι[PS0 ]), but HD(ι[PS ]) (ι[PS ]) > HD(ι[PS0 ]) (ι[PS0 ]) (lexicographic ordering). imw Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 23 / 56 Formalisation of (the core of) BonJour’s coherence notion Formalising BonJour’s third and fourth desiderata 1 Introduction 2 Formalisation of (the core of) BonJour’s coherence notion Formal framework Formalising BonJour’s first desideratum Formalising BonJour’s second desideratum Formalising BonJour’s third and fourth desiderata 3 Example: BonJour’s “ravens” challenge Preparations for the formalisation of BonJour’s challenge Formalisation of the belief systems Calculation of the third and fourth component of the coherence measure Calculation of graded probabilistic consistency. The second component of the coherence measure Calculation of the first component of the coherence measure Summary 4 Conclusion and discussion imw Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 24 / 56 Formalisation of (the core of) BonJour’s coherence notion Formalising BonJour’s third and fourth desiderata Belief systems as directed graphs For BonJour’s third and fourth requirements, we suggest viewing a belief system S as a directed graph, such that the vertices (nodes) are propositions to which a rational agent with belief system S will assent and such that an arrow from B to A means that B confirms A (in the sense of Bayesian confirmation theory) with respect to the belief system S. This would formalise coherentist intuitions such as Quine’s and Ullian’s “web of belief” (Q UINE –U LLIAN 1970). However, it invokes the concept of belief simpliciter within a framework that is built around (conditional) degrees of belief. More careful definitions are necessary. imw Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 25 / 56 Formalisation of (the core of) BonJour’s coherence notion Formalising BonJour’s third and fourth desiderata The extended web of belief Let us first consider the extended web of belief HS : The vertices are all those propositions A ∈ A that are at least candidates for objects of full belief in the sense that P(A) > 1/2 for all P ∈ PS . There will be an arrow between vertex B and vertex A if and only if B confirms A in the sense of Bayesian confirmation theory (with the belief system S in the background), i.e. if and only if P(A|B) − P(A) > 0 for all P ∈ PS . Note: The extended web of belief contains propositions as vertices to which not a precise probability, but merely a lower bound is assigned by the belief system — e.g. all events/propositions that extensionally dominate an event/proposition to which S unconditionally assigns some precise probability > 1/2. imw Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 26 / 56 Formalisation of (the core of) BonJour’s coherence notion Formalising BonJour’s third and fourth desiderata The inner web of belief Our coherence notion will be based on the inner web of belief GS : The vertices are all those propositions A ∈ A which can be proved to be objects of full belief for suitable thresholds c in the Lockean thesis. More precisely, the vertices of GS are all those propositions A ∈ A to which precise unconditional probabilities > 1/2 are assigned by the belief system, in the sense that there is a real number α > 1/2 such that P(A) = α for all P ∈ PS . There will be an arrow between vertex B and vertex A if and only if B confirms A in the sense of Bayesian confirmation theory (with the belief system S in the background) with a precise degree of confirmation, i.e. if and only if there exists some real number γ > 0 such that P(A|B) − P(A) = γ for all P ∈ PS . For any such A, B, we shall refer to this positive real γ as γ(B, A). If there is, for any A, B, no γ > 0 that would satisfy P(A|B) − P(A) = γ for all P ∈ PS , we imw simply put γ(B, A) = 0. Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 27 / 56 Formalisation of (the core of) BonJour’s coherence notion Formalising BonJour’s third and fourth desiderata More restrictive notions of the inner web of belief One could define, for any c ≥ 1/2, the c-core of beliefs as the subgraph GSc of GS which consists of only those propositions A to which precise unconditional probabilities > c are assigned by the belief system, in the sense that there is a real number α > c such that P(A) = α for all P ∈ PS . For all c ≥ 1/2, GSc as well as GS and HS are Bayesian networks. imw Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 28 / 56 Formalisation of (the core of) BonJour’s coherence notion Formalising BonJour’s third and fourth desiderata Two aspects of BonJour’s desideratum (III) 1 2 “The coherence of a system of beliefs is increased by the presence of inferential connections between its component beliefs and increased in proportion to the number [. . . ] of such connections” (B ON J OUR 1985, p. 98; emphasis mine). We suggest to capture this by the graph-theoretic notion of (vertex) connectivity κ. “The coherence of a system of beliefs is increased [. . . ] in proportion to the [. . . ] strength of [inferential] connections [between its component beliefs]” (B ON J OUR 1985, p. 99; emphasis mine). In a Bayesian setting, a natural interpretation of the “strength of an inferential connection” from B to A is the degree by which B confirms A (in the sense of Bayesian confirmation theory). The most widely used measure of confirmation is the relevance measure, (difference measure) P(A|B) − P(A). imw We therefore propose: β3 (S) := hκ(GS ), hγ(B, A) : A, B ∈ Aii . Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 29 / 56 Formalisation of (the core of) BonJour’s coherence notion Formalising BonJour’s third and fourth desiderata BonJour’s desideratum (IV) B ON J OUR’s penultimate requirement is (IV): the relative fragmentation of a belief system (given the overall level of connectivity within the belief system) diminishes coherence. A natural proposal might be to consider FS := {F ( G : F maximal (κ(GS ) + 1)-connected} and then define the inverse degree of relative fragmentation as follows: #FS , FS 6= ∅, β4 (S) = 0, FS = ∅. For example, in the special case when κ(GS ) = 0 (i.e. GS is totally disconnected), we have β4 (S) = 0. imw Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 30 / 56 Example: BonJour’s “ravens” challenge 1 Introduction 2 Formalisation of (the core of) BonJour’s coherence notion Formal framework Formalising BonJour’s first desideratum Formalising BonJour’s second desideratum Formalising BonJour’s third and fourth desiderata 3 Example: BonJour’s “ravens” challenge Preparations for the formalisation of BonJour’s challenge Formalisation of the belief systems Calculation of the third and fourth component of the coherence measure Calculation of graded probabilistic consistency. The second component of the coherence measure Calculation of the first component of the coherence measure Summary 4 Conclusion and discussion imw Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 31 / 56 Example: BonJour’s “ravens” challenge Preparations for the formalisation of BonJour’s challenge 1 Introduction 2 Formalisation of (the core of) BonJour’s coherence notion Formal framework Formalising BonJour’s first desideratum Formalising BonJour’s second desideratum Formalising BonJour’s third and fourth desiderata 3 Example: BonJour’s “ravens” challenge Preparations for the formalisation of BonJour’s challenge Formalisation of the belief systems Calculation of the third and fourth component of the coherence measure Calculation of graded probabilistic consistency. The second component of the coherence measure Calculation of the first component of the coherence measure Summary 4 Conclusion and discussion imw Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 32 / 56 Example: BonJour’s “ravens” challenge Preparations for the formalisation of BonJour’s challenge B ON J OUR’s (1985, p. 96) challenge, as summarised by B OVENS –H ARTMANN (2003, p. 718), is to consider the following propositions: R̃1 : ‘All ravens are black.’ R2 : ‘This bird is a raven.’ R3 : ‘This bird is black.’ R10 : ‘This chair is brown.’ R20 : ‘Electrons are negatively charged.’ R30 : ‘Today is Thursday.’ n o Let R̃ = R̃1 , R2 , R3 and R0 = R10 , R20 , R30 . One has to account for the fact that R̃ is more coherent than R0 .” imw Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 33 / 56 Example: BonJour’s “ravens” challenge Preparations for the formalisation of BonJour’s challenge Reformulation No inferential connections among R10 , R20 , R30 are known. In R̃ and R0 , there are no inferential connections except for the obvious one, viz. modus ponens inference from R1 , R2 to R3 . R̃1 is a scheme of inferential connections rather than as a proposition. In the context of the belief system R̃, it can be replaced by a mere single inferential connection such as: R3 |R2 : ‘If this bird is a raven, then it is black.’ We shall henceforth study R := {R3 |R2 , R2 , R3 } en lieu of R̃. BonJour’s challenge is to give an account of the greater coherence of R compared to that of R0 . imw Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 34 / 56 Example: BonJour’s “ravens” challenge Formalisation of the belief systems 1 Introduction 2 Formalisation of (the core of) BonJour’s coherence notion Formal framework Formalising BonJour’s first desideratum Formalising BonJour’s second desideratum Formalising BonJour’s third and fourth desiderata 3 Example: BonJour’s “ravens” challenge Preparations for the formalisation of BonJour’s challenge Formalisation of the belief systems Calculation of the third and fourth component of the coherence measure Calculation of graded probabilistic consistency. The second component of the coherence measure Calculation of the first component of the coherence measure Summary 4 Conclusion and discussion imw Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 35 / 56 Example: BonJour’s “ravens” challenge Formalisation of the belief systems If the information available to a rational individual is represented by R (or R0 , respectively), this could in a Bayesian framework rendered thus: 1 she assigns to each of the propositions/events and conditional events in R (or R0 , respectively) a sufficiently high degree of belief; 2 all degrees of belief that she assigns to other conditional events assume pairwise independence of the propositions constituting the conditional event in question. Next choose two algebras of propositions/events to which conditional degrees of belief will be assigned, A and A0 . By Stone’s theorem, we can identify A and A0 with power-set algebras 0 2 Ω , 2Ω . imw Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 36 / 56 Example: BonJour’s “ravens” challenge Formalisation of the belief systems An individual with information set R has a belief system S consisting of: hRi |Ωkαi i for each i ∈ {2, 3} for some αi ∈ [0, 1] that is sufficiently close to 1; hR3 |R2 kα1 i for some α1 ∈ [0, 1] that is sufficiently close to 1 and strictly greater than α3 . Hence for the belief system S, the set Ω of states of the world only needs four elements (ω (1) , . . . , ω (4) ) — given by the state descriptions ‘R2 and R3 ’, ‘R2 but not R3 ’, ‘R3 but not R3 ’, ‘neither R2 not R3 ’. More formally: D E ω (1) := Ṙ2 , Ṙ3 D E ω (3) := ¬˙ Ṙ2 , Ṙ3 D E ω (2) := Ṙ2 , ¬˙ Ṙ3 D E ω (4) := ¬˙ Ṙ2 , ¬˙ Ṙ3 . imw Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 37 / 56 Example: BonJour’s “ravens” challenge Formalisation of the belief systems An individual with information set R0 has a belief system S0 consisting of: 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 R |Ω kα , R |R kα , R |R kα for some α10 ∈ [0, 1]; 10 0 10 10 20 10 10 30 10 R |Ω kα , R |R kα , R |R kα for some α20 ∈ [0, 1]; 20 0 20 20 10 02 20 30 02 R3 |Ω kα3 , R3 |R1 kα3 , R3 |R2 kα3 for some α30 ∈ [0, 1], wherein for every i ∈ {1, 2, 3}, αi0 is sufficiently close to 1. Hence for the belief system S0 , the set Ω0 of states of the world only needs eight elements: D E D E ω 0(1) := Ṙ10 , Ṙ20 , Ṙ30 ω 0(2) := Ṙ10 , Ṙ20 , ¬˙ Ṙ30 D E D E ω 0(3) := Ṙ10 , ¬˙ Ṙ20 , Ṙ30 ω 0(4) := Ṙ10 , ¬˙ Ṙ20 , ¬˙ Ṙ30 E D E D ω 0(6) := ¬˙ Ṙ10 , Ṙ20 , ¬˙ Ṙ30 ω 0(5) := ¬˙ Ṙ10 , Ṙ20 , Ṙ30 D E D E ω 0(8) := ¬˙ Ṙ10 , ¬˙ Ṙ20 , ¬˙ Ṙ30 ω 0(7) := ¬˙ Ṙ10 , ¬˙ Ṙ20 , Ṙ30 imw Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 38 / 56 Example: BonJour’s “ravens” challenge Formalisation of the belief systems Now we shall compute — or at least estimate — the several components β1 , β2 , β3 , β4 of our coherence measure applied to S and S0 , and show that according to our multi-dimensional coherence measure, the coherence of S dominates that of S0 . For the application of our coherence measure (in particular for β3 , β4 ), we need to represent S and S0 as Bayesian networks. The belief system S0 is represented by a completely disconnected graph GS0 with three vertices, so that β3 (S0 ) = h0, h0, . . . , 0ii , β4 (S0 ) = 0. The belief system S consists of two vertices with an arrow from R2 (‘This bird is a raven’) to R3 (‘This bird is black’). We shall now calculate β1 , β2 , β3 , β4 for S and S0 ; we shall also estimate imw β̃2 for both belief systems. Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 39 / 56 Example: BonJour’s “ravens” challenge Calculation of the third and fourth component of the coherence measure 1 Introduction 2 Formalisation of (the core of) BonJour’s coherence notion Formal framework Formalising BonJour’s first desideratum Formalising BonJour’s second desideratum Formalising BonJour’s third and fourth desiderata 3 Example: BonJour’s “ravens” challenge Preparations for the formalisation of BonJour’s challenge Formalisation of the belief systems Calculation of the third and fourth component of the coherence measure Calculation of graded probabilistic consistency. The second component of the coherence measure Calculation of the first component of the coherence measure Summary 4 Conclusion and discussion imw Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 40 / 56 Example: BonJour’s “ravens” challenge Calculation of the third and fourth component of the coherence measure For the calculation of the third coherence component, observe: The (vertex) connectivity of GS is 1, the single inferential non-zero connection in GS being the one from R2 to R3 , whose strength is γ(R2 , R3 ) = α1 − α3 > 0. In contrast, the (vertex) connectivity of GS0 is 0, and thus the vector of strengths of inferential connections among the vertices in GS0 is trivial (consists of zeroes only). Thus, * * ++ β3 (S) = 1, α1 − α3 , 0, . . . , 0 | {z } . >0 0 β3 (S ) = h0, h0, . . . , 0ii . imw Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 41 / 56 Example: BonJour’s “ravens” challenge Calculation of the third and fourth component of the coherence measure For the calculation of the fourth coherence component, observe that the relative fragmentation of both S and S0 is zero: GS has connectivity 1, but no 2-connected components; GS0 has connectivity 0 (is totally disconnected) and therefore cannot have any 1-connected components. Thus, β4 (S) = 0 = β4 (S0 ). imw Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 42 / 56 Example: BonJour’s “ravens” challenge Calculation of graded probabilistic consistency. The second component of the coherence measure 1 Introduction 2 Formalisation of (the core of) BonJour’s coherence notion Formal framework Formalising BonJour’s first desideratum Formalising BonJour’s second desideratum Formalising BonJour’s third and fourth desiderata 3 Example: BonJour’s “ravens” challenge Preparations for the formalisation of BonJour’s challenge Formalisation of the belief systems Calculation of the third and fourth component of the coherence measure Calculation of graded probabilistic consistency. The second component of the coherence measure Calculation of the first component of the coherence measure Summary 4 Conclusion and discussion imw Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 43 / 56 Example: BonJour’s “ravens” challenge Calculation of graded probabilistic consistency. The second component of the coherence measure We shall calculate β̃2 for S, S0 ; as a by-product, this will yield probabilistic consistency proofs for both S and S0 . Now, in the case of S, the canonical geometrical representation ι[PS ] is the intersection of the four-dimensional unit cube with four hyperplanes, one for each of the three (conditional) probability assignment) plus the hyperplane generated by requiring the total mass to add up to one: x (1) + x (2) + x (3) + x (4) = 1, x (1) = x (1) + x (2) α1 , 4 ι[PS ] = x ∈ [0, 1] : . x (1) + x (2) = α2 , x (1) + x (3) = α3 . Herein, any x = x (1) , x (2) , x (3) , x (4) ∈ ι[PS ] represents a probability (1) (2) (3) (4) measure on the power-set of Ω = ω , ω , ω , ω that is compatible with S and assigns probability x (i) to {ω (i) } for each i ∈ {1, 2, 3, 4}; the three (conditional) probability assignments that imw make up S have been encoded accordingly. Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 44 / 56 Example: BonJour’s “ravens” challenge Calculation of graded probabilistic consistency. The second component of the coherence measure By elementary linear algebra, this reduces to α1 α2 α (1 − α1 ) 2 ι[PS ] = α − α1 α2 3 1 − α2 (1 − α1 ) − α3 . (3) This is a singleton and thus its H AUSDORFF dimension is zero and so is its H AUSDORFF measure: Therefore, β̃2 (S) = h0, 0i. This, however, does not mean that S is probabilistically inconsistent, just that is in a sense ‘minimally consistent’ probabilistically. The belief system S is probabilistically consistent, yet S induces a unique probability system that is compatible with S. Thus, S cannot be dominated in terms of probabilistic consistency imw simpliciter by S0 . Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 45 / 56 Example: BonJour’s “ravens” challenge Calculation of graded probabilistic consistency. The second component of the coherence measure Nevertheless, for the sake of illustration, we shall also compute β̃2 (S0 ). A similar analysis for S0 will show that ι[PS0 ] is actually given by the following linear equation system: (1) + · · · + x (8) = 1, x (1) + x (2) + x (3) + x (4) = α0 , x 1 (1) (2) (1) (2) (5) (6) 0 x + x = x + x + x + x α , 1 (1) (3) (1) (3) (5) (7) 0 x + x = x + x + x + x α , 1 (1) (2) (5) (6) 0 x + x + x + x = α , 8 2 , x ∈ [0, 1] : ι[PS0 ] = x (1) + x (2) = x (1) + x (2) + x (3) + x (4) α20 , x (1) + x (5) = x (1) + x (3) + x (5) + x (7) α20 , (1) (3) (5) (7) 0 x + x + x + x = α , 3 (1) (3) (1) (2) (3) (4) 0 x + x = x + x + x + x α , 3 (1) (5) (1) (2) (5) (6) 0 x +x = x +x +x +x α3 . imw Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 46 / 56 Example: BonJour’s “ravens” challenge Calculation of graded probabilistic consistency. The second component of the coherence measure This can be simplified to become ι[PS0 ] λ 0 α1 α20 − λ α10 α30 − λ 0 α1 − α10 α20 − α10 α30 + λ = α20 α30 − λ 0 α2 − α10 α20 − α20 α30 + λ α30 − α10 α30 − α20 α30 + λ 0 (1 − α1 )(1 − α20 ) + α30 (α20 − 1) + α10 α30 − λ : λ∈R ∩[0, 1]8 imw Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 47 / 56 Example: BonJour’s “ravens” challenge Calculation of graded probabilistic consistency. The second component of the coherence measure In other words, ι[PS0 ] consists of all vectors of the eight-dimensional unit cube that can be written in the form 1 0 −1 α10 α20 0 α0 −1 α 1 3 1 α10 (1 − α20 − α30 ) + −1 λ α20 α30 1 α20 (1 − α10 − α30 ) 1 α30 (1 − α10 − α20 ) −1 (1 − α10 )(1 − α20 ) + α30 (α20 − 1) + α10 α30 for some real number λ. Clearly, the H AUSDORFF dimension of ι[PS0 ] is one, and its H AUSDORFF measure is positive. imw Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 48 / 56 Example: BonJour’s “ravens” challenge Calculation of the first component of the coherence measure 1 Introduction 2 Formalisation of (the core of) BonJour’s coherence notion Formal framework Formalising BonJour’s first desideratum Formalising BonJour’s second desideratum Formalising BonJour’s third and fourth desiderata 3 Example: BonJour’s “ravens” challenge Preparations for the formalisation of BonJour’s challenge Formalisation of the belief systems Calculation of the third and fourth component of the coherence measure Calculation of graded probabilistic consistency. The second component of the coherence measure Calculation of the first component of the coherence measure Summary 4 Conclusion and discussion imw Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 49 / 56 Example: BonJour’s “ravens” challenge Calculation of the first component of the coherence measure Now we calculate the first coherence component, β1 , i.e. logical consistency. From our above calculations of representations of PS and PS0 (under ι) it is obvious that only the top element of the Boolean algebra is assigned probability 1 by every probability measure that is compatible with the respective belief system (be it S or S0 ). Therefore, η(S, {1}) = Ω and η(S0 , {1}) = Ω0 , whence β1 (S) = 1 = β1 (S0 ). Just as claimed by B ON J OUR when introducing the challenge, S and S0 cannot be told apart by considering logical and probabilistic consistency (i.e. β1 and β2 ) alone. imw Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 50 / 56 Example: BonJour’s “ravens” challenge Summary 1 Introduction 2 Formalisation of (the core of) BonJour’s coherence notion Formal framework Formalising BonJour’s first desideratum Formalising BonJour’s second desideratum Formalising BonJour’s third and fourth desiderata 3 Example: BonJour’s “ravens” challenge Preparations for the formalisation of BonJour’s challenge Formalisation of the belief systems Calculation of the third and fourth component of the coherence measure Calculation of graded probabilistic consistency. The second component of the coherence measure Calculation of the first component of the coherence measure Summary 4 Conclusion and discussion imw Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 51 / 56 Example: BonJour’s “ravens” challenge Summary As we have seen, β1 (S) = β1 (S0 ), β2 (S) = β2 (S0 ), β3 (S) > β3 (S0 ), β4 (S) = β4 (S0 ). (4) This is fully in line with B ON J OUR’s (1985, p. 95f) expectations: the two belief systems are indistinguishable in terms of logical and probabilistic consistency, but S is more coherent than S0 — on account of inferential connections. Thus, our formal coherence notion has passed the test of B ON J OUR’s challenge. imw Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 52 / 56 Conclusion and discussion 1 Introduction 2 Formalisation of (the core of) BonJour’s coherence notion Formal framework Formalising BonJour’s first desideratum Formalising BonJour’s second desideratum Formalising BonJour’s third and fourth desiderata 3 Example: BonJour’s “ravens” challenge Preparations for the formalisation of BonJour’s challenge Formalisation of the belief systems Calculation of the third and fourth component of the coherence measure Calculation of graded probabilistic consistency. The second component of the coherence measure Calculation of the first component of the coherence measure Summary 4 Conclusion and discussion imw Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 53 / 56 Conclusion and discussion Conclusion and discussion We have formalised doxastic systems as families of conditional degree-of-belief assignments, rather than sets of propositions. Doxastic systems can thereby be studied as Bayesian networks, permitting the use of new mathematical concepts. The core of B ON J OUR’s coherence concept can be formalised in this formal framework. There is potential for relatively straightforward generalisation: I I One can replace the Lockean thesis with another bridge principle, such as those discussed by L EITGEB (2013, 2014). One can replace the relevance measure of confirmation The weights of the components have not been specified and may be dependent by context. Some norms would be desirable for this. imw Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 54 / 56 Appendix Selected References Selected References I H. Arló-Costa and R. Parikh. Conditional probability and defeasible inference. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 34(1):97–119, 2005. H. Arló-Costa and A.P. Pedersen. Belief and probability: A general theory of probability cores. International Journal of Approximate Reasoning, 53(3):293–315, 2012. L. BonJour. The structure of empirical knowledge. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 1985. L. Bovens and S. Hartmann. Solving the riddle of coherence. Mind, 112(448):601–633, 2003. R. Foley. Beliefs, degrees of belief, and the Lockean Thesis. In F. Huber and C. Schmidt-Petri, editors, Degrees of Belief, volume 342 of Synthese Library, pages 37–47. Springer, Dordrecht, 2009. F.S. Herzberg. Aggregating infinitely many probability measures. Theory and Decision, (forthcoming), 2014. F.S. Herzberg. The dialectics of infinitism and coherentism: Inferential justification versus holism and coherence. Synthese, 191(4):701–723, 2014. Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 imw 55 / 56 Appendix Selected References Selected References II F.S. Herzberg. A graded Bayesian coherence notion. Erkenntnis, (forthcoming), 2014. F.S. Herzberg. Universal algebra and general aggregation: Many-valued propositional-attitude aggregators as MV-homomorphisms. Journal of Logic and Computation, (forthcoming), 2014. K. Lehrer. Theory of knowledge. Westview Press, Boulder, CO, 2000. H. Leitgeb. Reducing belief simpliciter to degrees of belief. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 2013. H. Leitgeb. The stability theory of belief. Philosophical Review, 2014. W.V.O. Quine and J. Ullian. The web of belief. Random House, New York, 1970. imw Frederik Herzberg (IMW / MCMP) A graded Bayesian coherence notion Full and Partial Belief, 2014 56 / 56