Commentary on Case of Mr. Smith John Z Sadler, M.D. Professor of Psychiatry Daniel W. Foster, M.D., Professorship in Medical Ethics UT Southwestern Medical Center Mr. Smith is a homeless man with severe alcoholic cirrhosis, no family, and no financial resources. He is dying from his medical problems and is now in the hospital requiring intensive treatment and multiple blood transfusions. The medical and surgical treatments available now can only prolong his dying, not save his life. The question is about what kind of humane dying process is ethical. Sometimes, even often, medical ethics has to settle for not what is good, but what is the least awful option. Mr. Smith’s case is one of these. A happy outcome is not possible here. We have to find the most decent outcome. There are three general options. 1) Continue to prolong Mr. Smith’s life, and dying, through the current program of providing aggressive treatment including blood transfusions. 2) We could withdraw or withhold current life-sustaining treatments, and continue to give Mr. Smith ‘comfort care,’ which is focused on keeping him comfortable and respecting his dignity as a person as he passes. 3) Give Mr. Smith, some, but not all, life-sustaining treatments. Let’s consider each in turn. Continue current treatments (option 1). Given that the doctors, regardless of what treatment they offer, cannot save Mr. Smith’s life, one might wonder what value the current life-saving treatments offer to him. He’s going to die anyway, so what’s the point? However, every moment of life is precious, and so from that standpoint we might want to continue his treatment. While we recognize that life is precious, in the abstract, we have to ask ourselves is it likely that Mr. Smith is enjoying life in some way, or any way, in his present, apparently miserable condition? The answer here is almost certainly no, in that he is in a coma, one which he is unlikely to recover from before he dies. So given the limited (at best) benefits of treatment, we should see if the treatments provided to Mr. Smith somehow affect other people, who may have a ‘stake’ in the issues. It turns out that providing less-than-beneficial care to Mr. Smith might well have an impact on others. For example, one of Mr. Smith’s problems requires frequent blood transfusions. Blood is always a scarce resource in the nation’s hospitals; it is routinely required in scheduled surgery as well as in the treatment of accidents and other traumatic injuries associated with blood loss. Mr. Smith’s need for blood has a potential, and occasionally real, impact on the care of people whose transfusions could save lives. Given the potential for blood to save the life of people who are not dying, and who could receive great benefits from transfusion, it seems difficult to justify giving repeated transfusions to Mr. Smith given that he will die soon regardless. The financial costs of treating Mr. Smith must be considered, however painful or unfair it seems for us. Mr. Smith is likely cared for in a community hospital, like Parkland in Dallas, where funding is limited. When you have many poor and uninsured people to serve, it would be irresponsible to the community to not consider the cost of care, because using limited resources wisely is a requirement for making the best use of them, and helping the most people who can benefit from those scarce resources. In this regard, the need for a frankly scarce product like blood makes this case a little easier, in that the need for limiting end-of-life care is explicit, so that blood can be saved for use with other patients who can benefit much more. For these reasons, I would favor withholding further transfusions and provide comfort care to Mr. Smith (option 2), allowing his diseases to take their course, and for Mr. Smith to have a more natural death. The option (3) has not been considered yet. The difficulty with this option is choosing which treatments to provide, and how to justify their value. As Mr. Smith is slowly bleeding to death from untreatable causes, it’s unclear to me what benefit other treatments would have, other than comfort care for him (pain control, baths, dental care, spiritual care if the patient is responsive). Comfort care would always be provided to him under option (2). What is often as important, or even more important, than ‘what’ you do in similar difficult end-of-life cases is ‘how’ you do it. American physicians are trained to treat every human life as equally valuable - so with this ethic, whether Mr. Smith is poor and homeless or Mr. Smith is the president of a major corporation should make no difference in how his care is planned or regarded. This is often difficult to do in the case of U.S. health care, where “health disparities”-- unequal treatment-- is so common when we compare the insured with the uninsured. I would want the discussion of withdrawing life-sustaining treatment to be made with family, and with chaplain or religious support suitable to the patient’s beliefs. Moreover, serious decisions involving end-of-life care should always be medical team discussions in concern with the patient and family - if possible. If the patient is unable to participate, and no family is available, pastoral care services in hospitals, as well as ethics consultation services can participate in these tough decisions. In cases like that of Mr. Smith, too often the soul of end-of-life care falls to the nurses who will care for him in his dying hours, and I’ve been lucky to witness extraordinary compassion on the part of nurses in caring for dying patients who had literally no one else. So I’ll end this brief essay with a salute to nurses, who are the heart and soul of medicine.