Decisions under Uncertainty The Approach • Goal: Develop a useful set of framework for predicting investor choices under uncertainty: – A) 5 axioms of rational choice under uncertainty – End-Product: Expected Utility Theorem to measure utility in the presence of risk. – B) Assumption of non-satiation (i.e., greed) – C) Risk-aversion – D) Measuring the objects of choice (i.e., the assets that investors invest) using Mean and Variance of asset return. – D) Mapping trade-offs between Mean and Variance that provides indifference curves of investors. – such trade-off reveals an investor’s degree of risk-aversion. 2 The End-product • By the end of this lecture, we will be able to formulate the following diagram of individual investor’s indifference curves. Returns EU2 EU1 Message: Risk [i] For the same level of risk, everyone prefers higher returns. [ii] For the same level of returns, everyone prefers lower risk. 3 Why care about uncertainty? Simple answer: Because in reality, almost every decision we make involves uncertainty. • Example: – Uncertainty from product quality. (e.g., used vehicle, order food before eating, any durable goods consumption) – Uncertainty in dealing with others. (i.e., your payoffs depend on others’ actions, e.g., marriage, competition among firms, driving, etc.) – Purchase of risky assets (i.e., risk in the sense that the payoffs of assets depends on what happen in the future, e.g., stocks, bonds, etc.) This is the essence of Financial Economics 4 An example to motivate Expected utility theory says: • When payoffs in the next period are uncertain, any individual’s subjective preference can be represented by a utility function, if his subjective preference satisfies the five axioms. • => “5 axioms” + “Greed” => individual’s decision-making process under uncertainty can be described by the following problem: Max [Expected utility of wealth] subject to constraints. • Qs.: Suppose Robert’s constraint is such that the money he now has can ONLY be allocated in one of the two assets, Asset i or Asset j, that pay off in the next period according to the two diagrams below. What should he do? • Answer: He chooses to hold the asset that gives him the highest expected utility of wealth, but NOT the highest expected wealth. 0.4 $10 0.6 $2 $8 E(W) = 0.4(10) + 0.6(2) = 5.2 E[U(W)] = 0.4U(10) + 0.6U(2) = ? Asset i 0.3 Asset j 0.7 $4 He would choose the asset that gives him highest E[U(W)] E(W) = 0.3(8) + 0.7(3) = 4.5 E[U(W)] = 0.3U(8) + 0.7U(3) = ? 5 St. Petersburg Paradox • The ultimate question that expected utility theorem wants to address is: “Is there a way to systematically measure the level of happiness under uncertainty?” The St. Petersburg Paradox is an example to convinces you that the following: “happiness under uncertainty =X= E(W)” “Suppose someone offers to toss a fair coin repeatedly until it comes up heads, and to pay you $1 if this happens on the first toss, $2 if it takes two tosses to land a head, $4 if it takes three tosses, $8 if it takes four tosses, etc. What is the largest sure gain you would be willing to forgo in order to undertake a single play of this game?” • • • State (The number of toss a head first comes up) Payoff Probability 1st toss 20=$1 ½ 2nd toss 21=$2 (½)2 = ¼ 3rd toss 22=$4 (½)3 = 1/8 The table illustrates only 3 possible states, but you can construct this table infinitely. The point is, the game’s Expected payoff (i.e, E(x)) is infinite, i.e., ∞. Depending on your risk-preference, you may probably pay $2, or even $10 to play this gamble. But you are unlikely to pay $1,000 to play. The point is, probably no one on earth would pay any amount close to the expected payoff. Why? Because maximizing our happiness does not imply maximizing our expected wealth. It is really the expected utility of wealth that measures our level of happiness. 6 Rational decision theory • To develop a theory of rational decision making under uncertainty, we impose some precise yet reasonable axioms about an individual’s behavior. • We assume 5 axioms of cardinal utility. – Axiom 1: Comparability (a.k.a., completeness) – Axiom 2: Transitivity (a.k.a., consistency) – Axiom 3: Strong independence – Axiom 4: Measurability – Axiom 5: Ranking • What do these axioms of generally mean? – all individuals are assumed to make completely rational decisions (reasonable) – people are assumed to make these rational decisions among thousands of alternatives (hard) • CONCERNING C49: – The following 4 pages of slides explain each axiom in full details. You may skip them because I would not test you more than remembering their names. However, they don’t seem as hard as they sounds. I will go through each of them with an example in class. – Believe it or not, it is just these 5 simple axioms, we establish the expected utility theory. The derivation is mathematical and I will neither go through it nor test it. If you are interested, Chapter 3 section B is what you should read. – The derivation is elegant! If you like math, you should take a look at it. Click on http://montoya.econ.ubc.ca/Econ600/expected_utility_lecture.PDF 7 by Professor Mike Peters of UBC if you are interested in the full proof. 5 Axioms of Choice under uncertainty A1.Comparability (also known as completeness). For the entire set, S, of uncertain alternatives, an individual can say that either outcome x is preferred to outcome y (x › y) or y is preferred to x (y › x) or indifferent between x and y (x ~ y). A2.Transitivity (also known as consistency). If an individual prefers x to y and y to z, then x is preferred to z. If (x › y and y › z, then x › z). Similarly, if an individual is indifferent between x and y and is also indifferent between y and z, then the individual is indifferent between x and z. If (x ~ y and y ~ z, then x ~ z). 8 5 Axioms of Choice under uncertainty A3.Strong Independence. Suppose we construct a gamble where the individual has a probability α of receiving outcome x and a probability (1-α) of receiving outcome z. This gamble is written as: G(x,z:α) Strong independence says that if the individual is indifferent to x and y, then he will also be indifferent as to a first gamble, set up between x with probability α and a mutually exclusive outcome z, and a second gamble set up between y with probability α and the same mutually exclusive outcome z. If x ~ y, then G(x,z:α) ~ G(y,z:α) NOTE: The mutual exclusiveness of the third outcome z is critical to the axiom of strong independence. 9 5 Axioms of Choice under uncertainty A4.Measurability. (concerning about CARDINAL UTILITY) If outcome y is less preferred than x (y ‹ x) but more than z (y › z), then there is a unique probability α such that: the individual will be indifferent between [1] y and [2] A gamble between x with probability α z with probability (1-α). In Math: if x › y > z or x > y › z , then there exists a unique probability α such that y ~ G(x,z:α) 10 5 Axioms of Choice under uncertainty A5.Ranking. (CARDINAL UTILITY) If alternatives y and u both lie somewhere between x and z and we can establish gambles such that an individual is indifferent between y and a gamble between x (with probability αy) and z, while also indifferent between u and a second gamble, this time between x (with probability αu) and z, then if αy is greater than αz, y is preferred to u. If x > y > z and x > u > z then by axiom 4, we have y ~ G(x,z:αy) and u ~ G(x,z:αz), then it follows that if αy > αz then y › u, or if αy = αz , then y ~ u 11 Sketch of the Proof Question: How do individuals rank various combinations of risky alternatives? • The derivation, one of the most elegant inductive proofs of human knowledge, uses the axioms to show how preferences can be mapped into measurable utility. • That means, in principle, I can tell exactly that risky asset i gives me EUi unit of expected utility, and EUj for risky asset j. By comparing EUi and EUj, I can ALWAYS claim whether I prefer i to j, or j to i, or indifferent between them. • In the end, expected utility theory shows that the correct ranking function for risky alternatives is the expected utility. • Example again: If risky asset j gives random payoff in the next period: $10 with probability 0.5, $5 with probability 0.2, and $-10 with probability 0.3. Then I evaluate j as E(U(W)) = ∑i [(Prob. of state i) x (payoffs in state i)] = 0.5x(U(10)) + 0.2x(U(5)) + 0.3x(U(-10)) 12 Your preference dictates U(W) E(U(W)) = ∑i [(Prob. of state i) x (payoffs in state i)] • With this in mind, we do an exercise to show how your preference constructs your unique utility function. Suppose I arbitrarily assign a utility of -10 to a loss of $1000 and ask the following question: – If you are faced with a gamble with prob. p of winning $1000, and prob. (1-p) of losing $1000. What is this precise p that makes you indifferent between: [i] taking the gamble or [ii] getting $0 with certainty? • • • • In math, we have: U(0) = pU(1000) + (1-p)U(-1000) = pU(1000) + (1-p)(-10) Assume U(0) = 0 for yourself, and if your answer is that p = 0.6, then, U(1000) = 6.66667. Repeat this procedure for different payoffs, and you can work out your own utility function. MESSAGE: The AXIOMS of preference is convertible to a UTILITY fn. 13 Explaining the St. Petersburg Paradox • Going back to the St. Petersburg Paradox, we explain it with the help of another “building-block” concept: i.e., RISK-AVERSION. • If an individual’s preference is such that his utility function exhibits: [1] marginal utility being always positive (i.e., the greed assumption), and [2] diminishing MU as W increases (i.e., risk-aversion), i.e., [1] U'(W) > 0 [2] U"(W) < 0 then, MU positive Diminishing MU E(U(W)) = ∑i [(Prob. of state i) x (payoffs in state i)] = αi U(Xi) < • E.g., if U(W)=ln(W), then αi ln(Xi) = 1.39 • Thus, an individual would pay an amount up to 1.39 units of expected utility to play this gamble. • Message: Because everyone is risk-averse, that’s why everyone is only willing to pay limited amount of money to play the St. Petersrburg game. 14 Preferences to Risk: Intro U(W) U(W) U(W) U(b) U(b) U(a) U(b) U(a) U(a) a b Risk-loving U'(W) > 0 U''(W) > 0 W a b Risk Neutral U'(W) > 0 U''(W) = 0 W a b Risk Averse W U'(W) > 0 U''(W) < 0 15 Preferences to Risk: Intro U(W) U(W) U(W) U(b) U(b) U(a) U(b) U(a) U(a) a b Risk-loving W a b Risk Neutral W a b Risk Averse W Goals: (a) Formally define what is risk-aversion. (b) Establish the concept of risk-premium 16 Risk Aversion • Consider the following gamble: • Outcome a prob = α • Outcome b prob = 1-α => G(a,b:α) Question: Will we prefer the expected value of the gamble with certainty, or will we prefer the gamble itself? • E.g., consider the gamble with • 20% chance of winning $30 • 80% chance of winning $5 => E(Payoff of Gamble) = $10 Question: Would you prefer the $10 for sure or would you prefer the gamble? [i] if prefer the gamble, you are risk loving [ii] if indifferent to the options, risk neutral [iii] if prefer the expected value over the gamble, risk averse 17 Risk-aversion as shown in Utility Fn Suppose U(W)=ln(W) 3.40=U(30) Risk-averse U: Let U(W) = ln(W) 2.30=U[E(W)] U'(W) > 0 U''(W) < 0 1.61=U(5) U'(W) = 1/w U''(W) = - 1/W2 MU positive But diminishing 0 1 5 10 20 30 W 18 Risk-aversion as shown in Utility Fn U(W)=lnW 3.40=U(30) Risk-averse U: Let U(W) = ln(W) 2.30=U[E(W)] E[U(W)] =0.8U(5) + 0.2U(30) =0.8(1.61)+0.2(3.4) =1.97 1.97=E[U(W)] 1.61=U(5) Certainty Equivalent: U(CE) = 1.97 = ln(CE) CE=7.17 0 1 5 7.17 10 20 30 W 19 U[E(W)] VS E[U(W)] In general, if U[E(W)] > if U[E(W)] = if U[E(W)] < E[U(W)] E[U(W)] E[U(W)] then risk averse individual then risk neutral individual then risk loving individual risk aversion occurs when the utility function is strictly concave risk neutrality occurs when the utility function is linear risk loving occurs when the utility function is convex Certainty Equivalent Definition: The amount of money that the individual needs to hold for certainty in order to be indifferent from playing the gamble. As the example: This person is indifferent between [i] holding $7.17 for certain [ii] playing the gamble that has 80% chance with $5 and 20% with $30. 20 Markowitz Risk Premium CE’s Definition: The amount of money that the individual needs to hold for certainty in order to be indifferent from playing the gamble. As the example: This person is indifferent between [i] holding $7.17 for certain [ii] playing the gamble that has 80% chance with $5 and 20% with $30. Risk premium: the difference between an individual’s expected wealth, given the gamble, and the certainty equivalent wealth. As the example: This person pays a risk-premium of: RP = E(Wealth given the Gamble) – CE = $10 - $7.17 = $2.83 Meaning: Any insurance that costs less than $2.83 that ensures him the level of wealth of $10 will be attractive to him. Cost of gamble: The difference between an individual’s current wealth and the certainty 21 equivalent wealth. Risk Premium VS cost of gamble Risk premium: the difference between an individual’s expected wealth, given the gamble, and the certainty equivalent wealth. As the example: This person pays a risk-premium of: RP = E(Wealth given the Gamble) – CE = $10 - $7.17 = $2.83 Meaning: Any insurance that costs less than $2.83 that ensures him the level of wealth of $10 will be attractive to him. Cost of gamble: The difference between an individual’s current wealth and the certainty equivalent wealth. e.g., Denote E(x) = E(Wealth given the Gamble), if the individual’s current wealth is: (a) $10 = E(x) Cost of gamble = $10 - $7.17 = $2.83 RP = C of Gamble (b) $11 > E(x) Cost of gamble = $11 - $7.17 = $3.83 RP < C of Gamble (c) $9.5 < E(x) Cost of gamble = $9.5 - $7.17 = $2.43 RP > C of Gamble NOTE: Risk premium may or may not be the same as Cost of Gamble. NOTE: If you are risk-averse, risk premium is always positive!!! 22 The Arrow-Pratt Premium We can have a more solid, or mathematical, definition of premium, given that: • Risk Averse Investors • And that his utility functions are strictly concave and increasing A More Specific Definition of Risk Aversion W ž W+ ž E(W+ ž) (W,Z) = Current wealth = Random gamble payoffs, where E(ž) = 0, Variance of ž = σ2z = Wealth given gamble = Expected Wealth given the Gamble = Arrow-Pratt Premium What risk premium (W,Z) must be added to the gamble to make the individual indifferent between the gamble and the expected value of the gamble? 23 The Arrow-Pratt Premium The risk premium can be defined as the value that satisfies the following equation: E[U(W + ž)] = U[ W + E(ž) - ( W , ž)] LHS: expected utility of the current level of wealth, given the gamble (*) RHS: utility of the current level of wealth plus the expected value of the gamble less the risk premium We use a Taylor series expansion to (*) to derive an expression for the risk premium (W,ž). 24 Absolute Risk Aversion • Arrow-Pratt Measure of a Local Risk Premium (derived from (*) above) = 1 2 U (W) ) Z ( 2 U (W) • Define ARA as a measure of Absolute Risk Aversion ARA = - U (W) U (W) • This is a measure of absolute risk aversion because it measures risk aversion for a given level of wealth ARA > 0 for all risk-averse investors (U'>0, U''<0) How does ARA change with an individual's level of wealth? • ie. A gamble that involves $1,000 fluctuations of wealth up or down may be trivial to Bill Gates, but non-trivial to me: => ARA will probably decrease as our wealth increases i.e., ARA ↓ as W ↑ 25 Relative Risk Aversion • Define RRA as a measure of Relative Risk Aversion RRA = - W * U (W) U (W) • Constant RRA => An individual will have constant risk aversion to a "proportional loss" of wealth, even though the absolute loss increases as wealth does. • That is, with a gamble with 50/50 chance of increasing your wealth by 10% or decreasing it by 10%, you are about as risk-averse to such gamble regardless of how wealthy or how poor you are. The risk premium, measured as a percentage of your initial wealth, will stay constant. 26 E.g.: Quadratic Utility Quadratic Utility - widely used in the academic literature U(W) = a W - b W2 U'(W) = a - 2bW ARA = -U"(W) 2b --------- = --------U'(W) a -2bW d(ARA) ------- > 0 dW RRA = U"(W) = -2b 2b --------a/W - 2b quadratic utility exhibits increasing ARA and increasing RRA ie an individual with increasing RRA would become more averse to a given percentage loss in W as W increases - not intuitive d(RRA) ------- > 0 dW 27 An Example • U=ln(W) W = $20,000 • G(10,-10: 0.5) 50% will win $10, 50% will lose $10 • What is the risk premium associated with this gamble? • Calculate this premium using both the Markowitz and Arrow-Pratt Approaches 28 Arrow-Pratt Measure • = -(1/2) 2z U''(W)/U'(W) • 2z = 0.5*(20,010 – 20,000)2 + 0.5*(19,090 – 20,000)2 = 100 • U'(W) = (1/W) U''(W) = -1/W2 • U''(W)/U'(W) = -1/W = -1/(20,000) • = -(1/2) 2z U''(W)/U'(W) = -(1/2)(100)(-1/20,000) = $0.0025 29 Markowitz Approach • • • • • E(U(W)) = piU(Wi) E(U(W)) = (0.5)U(20,010) + 0.5*U(19,990) E(U(W)) = (0.5)ln(20,010) + 0.5*ln(19,990) E(U(W)) = 9.903487428 ln(CE) = 9.903487428 CE = 19,999.9975 • The risk premium RP = $0.0025 • Therefore, the AP and Markowitz premia are the same 30 Markowitz Approach E(U(W)) = 9.903487 19,990 20,000 CE 20,010 31 Differences in two approaches • Markowitz premium is an exact measures whereas the AP measure is an approximation. • AP is an accurate approximation if – The gamble’s payoffs is relatively small relative to initial wealth. – The gamble’s payoffs is symmetric. • The accuracy of the AP measures decreases in the size of the gamble and its degree of asymmetry 32 E(U) and the end-product • Our final step: the bridging of expected utility theory to the indifference curves Returns = expected return = E(R) EU2 EU1 Risk = standard deviation of return = σR Derivation is from chapter 3 part F. Interested student may consult the text. • The transformations involve: Define [i] Wj as the wealth that you will get in next period if you hold asset j. [ii] W0 your current period wealth. Thus, return of holding asset j = Rj = (Wj -W0)/W0 Assume Wi is normally distributed, so Rj is normally distributed too. (Big assumption) NOTE: we simplify by assuming normally distributed returns. So, we can describe a 33 return simply by its mean and standard deviation. Summary • • • • • With 5 axioms, prefer more to less, we have Expected utility theory, where preferences => Utility function. With risk-aversion assumption, we solve St. Petersburg’s paradox. Assuming we are all greedy, we know every rational investor will maximize his E[U(W)]. Assuming returns of risky assets being jointly normally distributed, we leave ourselves with a 2-D Return diagram with mean of returns and standard deviation of returns (i.e, mean and s.d.) as our two only variables of focus Derive indifference curves on the plane of return and risk as the right diagram with expected utility theory. Risk END-PRODUCT: Essentially, mean and standard deviation are the choice variables investors concern about in order to max their E[U(w)], which is given on the 34 indifference curves.